Insurance and Endogenous Bankruptcy Risk: When is it Rational to Choose Gambling, Insurance and Potential Bankruptcy?

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Insurance and Endogenous Bankruptcy Risk: When is it Rational to Choose Gambling, Insurance and Potential Bankruptcy?"

Transcription

1 Insurance and Endogenous Bankruptcy Risk: When is it Rational to Choose Gambling, Insurance and Potential Bankruptcy? Lisa L. Posey Pennsylvania State University 369 Business Building University Park, PA Vickie Bajtelsmit Colorado State University 321 Rockwell Hall Fort Collins, CO July 2015

2 1 INTRODUCTION It is well established in the literature that potential bankruptcy can play an important role in the decision of whether and how much to insure. In the absence of bankruptcy costs, the effect of limited liability is to reduce the demand for liability insurance by risk averse individuals when damages can exceed net worth (Sinn, 1982; Huberman, Mayers and Smith, 1983). In this case, the floor on wealth created by limited liability allows the potential insured to externalize some of the costs of damages to third party victims if bankruptcy occurs. This dampens insurance demand. As Sinn (1982) and Winter (2006) show under a standard expected utility model with actuarially fair premiums, if a loss of fixed size may occur that is greater than initial wealth, then either full insurance or no insurance will be purchased. The greater the potential loss is, the more likely it is that insurance will not be purchased. A parallel literature considers the coexistence of gambling and insurance, where gambling refers to accepting a risky prospect that has a non-positive expected value. In their classic paper, Friedman and Savage (1948) hypothesized that expected utility maximizers have wealth preferences that are convex over some ranges and concave over others. Others, like Markowitz (1952), Yaari (1965), Machina (1982) and Quiggin (1991) criticized the Friedman and Savage model on several grounds including the fact that it is not applicable to all wealth levels. Markowitz (1952) showed that the Friedman and Savage model could lead to unusual predictions, like a preference for unfair over fair gambles, and suggested that the ranges for the convex and concave portions of the utility function be altered. Yaari (1965) presented experimental evidence that was inconsistent with the Friedman and Savage model and postulated that subjective probabilities that overestimate low probabilities and underestimate high probabilities could explain the coexistence of gambling and insurance. Like Yaari, Quiggin (1991) turned to transformations of the probabilities to explain the phenomenon of insurance with gambling, introducing the rank-dependent utility model with overweighting of low probability, extremely favorable events. In contrast, Conlisk (1993) added a term for the utility of gambling to the standard expected utility of wealth model and was able to explain demand for very small payoff gambles and demand for insurance for large losses. In each of these studies, the models developed were used to explain the decision to gamble and the decision to insure, but

3 2 situations where these decisions were made in conjunction with one another were not explicitly considered. Similar to large uninsured losses, gambles may place sufficient wealth at risk such that the occurrence of an unfavorable outcome can have a significant effect on individual or business wealth. Although limited liability protections under bankruptcy law have been separately shown to increase the incentives for risk-taking and to decrease the incentives for insuring, the combined effects have not been formally addressed in the literature. 1 This issue has practical relevance for small business and entrepreneurial decisions. Despite the relatively high risk of failure, 2 an entrepreneur often invests his or her own wealth in the high-risk gamble of a new venture and yet simultaneously purchases insurance against various risks. Because risk premiums for new venture investments are not particularly high (Vereshchagina and Hopenhayn, 2009), it is often assumed that entrepreneurs must be risk loving. However, there is also evidence of risk averse behavior, 3 such as investment in risk management and business insurance. A major contribution of our paper is that we show that over certain ranges of gambled wealth and insurance, the decision to both gamble and insure is rational and consistent with expected utility maximization and risk aversion. Limited liability 4 plays an important role in this outcome and, to the extent that public policy favors new business formation, the protections of bankruptcy law provide important incentives for entrepreneurial investment. 5 However, because bankruptcy law provides limited liability to individuals as well as businesses, our results are not limited to the business context. We develop a model in which a risk averse individual, in an environment of limited liability, decides whether to gamble on a zero expected value risky project and/or insure a 1 Posey (1993) considers the impact of limited liability on the investment in risky activities and self-protection activities. This paper shows that the impact on both of these types of activities is ambiguous. In particular, individuals may either over-invest, or under-invest in both selfprotection activities and risky activities relative to socially optimal levels. 2 According to SBA (2012), about half of small businesses survive 5 years or more and one-third survive 10 years or more. These survival rates have been consistent over the last two decades. Although corporate entities often have the protection of limited liability, a new venture entrepreneur s personal wealth is usually at stake in the event of business failure. 3 See for example, Forlani and Mullins (2000). 4 For a review of the history and impact of limited liability rules, see Leebron (1991). 5 Limited liability protection in bankruptcy laws has been shown to be an important factor entrepreneurial activity (Jia, 2010) and a factor explaining jurisdictional differences in new business formation. See Fossen (2014), and Athreya (2006).

4 3 potential liability loss that cannot, in and of itself, lead to bankruptcy. 6 Unlike Sinn (1982), Huberman, Mayers and Smith (1983) and Winter (2006), the status quo does not involve any bankruptcy risk. In addition, the occurrence of the liability loss is not certain to lead to bankruptcy even if the risky investment is undertaken without insurance. The individual who may be an entrepreneur, for example, has a riskless component of earnings and a nonbankrupting potential liability loss. 7 The entrepreneur may use some of the earnings to purchase actuarial fair insurance. The amount of money that is not used to purchase insurance, minus a small guaranteed floor on wealth, is available to invest in a risky project that has a zero expected value and is independent of the liability loss. The entrepreneur can invest any percentage of the available funds from 0% to 100%. If full insurance is purchased, the risky project cannot bankrupt the individual because only the initial investment will be lost if the outcome of the project is unfavorable. But in this case, the risky investment is not attractive due to risk aversion and the expected return of zero. Previous research indicates that introduction of an independent, zero expected value risk will not decrease the demand for insurance under any of the familiar DARA utility functions in the absence of bankruptcy risk (Gollier and Pratt, 1996; Guiso and Jappeli, 1998; Pratt and Zeckhauser, 1987; Kimball, 1993). But consider what will happen if insurance is not purchased and the risky project is undertaken. The risky project cannot lead to bankruptcy if there is no liability loss, similar to the case with full insurance. But without insurance, bankruptcy will occur if there is a liability loss, the outcome of the risky investment is unfavorable, and the amount invested is large enough. If this strategy of no insurance with a relatively large risky investment were to be chosen, it would imply that the risk of bankruptcy was endogenously created and the effect of limited liability was a lack of demand for insurance. Two questions arise: can endogenously chosen bankruptcy risk be optimal, and is it possible that some insurance may be purchased at the same time the entrepreneur gambles on the risky investment? The answer to these questions is yes. In the current paper, if both gambling and insurance are chosen, it will be in a range where a sufficiently large amount is gambled and a sufficiently small amount is insured that 6 There are no bankruptcy costs explicitly included in the model. This allows us to abstract from the role of bankruptcy costs in the insurance and investment decisions and focus on the other effects we are trying to uncover. 7 Although we have an entrepreneur in mind, the model can easily be applied to any individual or to a risk averse, closely held corporation.

5 4 bankruptcy will occur if both a liability loss and a gambling loss occur. Rather than avoiding bankruptcy, the individual wants to assure that it is possible because in doing so the expected value of the gamble is changed from zero to positive. This is because the full loss of the gamble is not borne by the individual in the event of bankruptcy since part of the uninsured liability loss will simply go unpaid. Even in light of this, the individual may still choose to purchase insurance since it will be valuable when the gamble is not lost and a liability loss occurs. The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. The next section presents the formal model for the situation of the individual described above. The decisions to insure and to gamble on the risky investment under limited liability are explored. Then an example is presented with a range of parameter values that lead to endogenously chosen bankruptcy risk with a demand for both insurance and investment in the risky project. A final section provides some concluding remarks. A MODEL OF GAMBLING WITH POTENTIAL BANKRUPTCY We begin with a simple mathematical model of an individual s demand for insurance. The individual, with non-random earnings W, faces a potential liability loss of size L with probability p. The loss is zero with probability (1-p). The individual is risk averse with utility function u(x) where x is final wealth, u!(x) > 0 and u!! (x) < 0. Insurance is available at an actuarially fair premium: coverage of α L costs α pl where α [0,1]. An assumption that is key to the analysis below is the existence of limited liability with no bankruptcy costs. Wealth is limited to a minimum of F. The term bankruptcy is used to refer to the situation where wealth would fall below F in the absence of limited liability. It is assumed that L W-F, so that bankruptcy cannot be caused solely by a liability loss. Under these conditions, the individual will buy full insurance, α = 1. In effect, purchasing less than full insurance would be equivalent to participating in a zero expected value gamble. In addition to the insurance decision, the individual has the opportunity to invest in (i.e., gamble on) a risky project that has zero expected value in the absence of limited liability. The investment decision is made immediately following the insurance decision. The money that is left after any insurance has been purchased, minus the small guaranteed floor on wealth, is the most that can be invested (i.e., there is no borrowing). Therefore, up to [W α pl F] can be

6 5 invested in the risky project and the individual must choose the proportion, β [0,1], of that amount to risk. If the project has an unfavorable outcome, the individual loses the full amount invested, β[w α pl F]. The project fails with probability π. If the project succeeds, which it does with probability ( 1 π ), the individual receives ( π (1 π ))β[w α pl F]. Since the investment is restricted to be less than the amount left over after insurance has been purchased, bankruptcy can only occur if the individual suffers a liability loss and an unfavorable outcome for the project, and has purchased a sufficiently small amount of insurance and risked a sufficiently large amount in the project. The individual maximizes the following expected utility function: EU = π p u(max{w α pl β[w α pl F] (1 α)l, F}) +π (1 p) u(w α pl β[w α pl F]) +(1 π )p u(w α pl + ( π (1 π ))β[w α pl F] (1 α)l) +(1 π )(1 p) u(w α pl + ( π (1 π ))β[w α pl F]). (1) This can be rewritten as EU = π p u(max{w 1, F}+ π (1 p) u(w 2 )+ (1 π )p u(w 3 )+ (1 π )(1 p) u(w 4 ) (2) where W 1, W 2, W 3 and W 4 are all functions of α and β. As the first term in EU shows, with probability π p, both a liability and gambling loss occur and final wealth is: Max{W α pl β[w α pl F]+ (1 α)l, F}. (3) Bankruptcy occurs whenw α pl β[w α pl F]+ (1 α)l < F, or equivalently, when (1 α)l β >1 [W α pl F]. (4) Therefore, the probability of bankruptcy is either π p, if the chosen α and β satisfy inequality (4), or 0 otherwise. Let the potential bankruptcy line be defined as (1 α)l β 0 (α) =1 [W α pl F]. (5) Figure 1 depicts the potential bankruptcy line for α, β combinations, where 0 β 1and 0 α 1. For combinations on or below the potential bankruptcy line, bankruptcy is not

7 6 possible even if both types of losses occur. For combinations above the potential bankruptcy line, bankruptcy definitely will occur if both types of losses occur, but will not occur if both types of losses do not occur. The area above the bankruptcy line can be called the feasible bankruptcy range and the area on or below the bankruptcy line can be referred to as the feasible nonbankruptcy range. 1 Figure 1 Feasible Bankruptcy Range β (1 α)l β! (α) = 1 W αpl F Feasible Non-Bankruptcy Range Consider the expected value of the risky project to the individual in light of the effects of limited liability. If the chosen expected value of the bet is α, β combination is below the potential bankruptcy line, the (1 π ){(π / (1 π ))β[w α pl F]} π{β[w α pl F]} = 0. (6) On the other hand, if the chooses an expected value of the risky project is E[Wealth(α, β)] E[Wealth(α, 0)] = π pf + π (1 p){w α pl β[w α pl F]} α, β combination is above the potential bankruptcy line, the +(1 π )p{w α pl + (π / (1 π ))β[w α pl F] (1 α)l} +(1 π )(1 p){w α pl + (π / (1 π ))β[w α pl F]} {W pl} α = π p{w α pl β[w α pl F] (1 α)l} (7)

8 7 = π p{w 1 } > 0. The expected value of the project becomes positive because, in the event the project fails, the full loss will be incurred only if a liability loss does not occur. If a liability loss does occur, then the amount of the uninsured liability paid out to the victim will be reduced to leave the individual with wealth F. So investing in the potential bankruptcy range creates a default put option that transforms a zero expected profit project into one with a positive expected value. The expected utility function in (1) can be redefined as follows. Let EU β represent the expected utility applicable in the feasible non-bankruptcy range and let EU β + represent the expected utility applicable in the feasible bankruptcy range. The difference between EU β + is the first term: in β EU β and EU the first term is πp u W ) which varies with α and β, while in EU β +, the first term is π p u(f) which does not vary with α and β. Below the expected ( 1 bankruptcy line the risky project impacts expected utility as follows: EU β β = π[w α pl F]{p[ u #(W 3 ) u #(W 1 )]+ (1 p)[ u #(W 4 ) u #(W 2 )]} < 0. (8) Here, limited liability plays no role and expected utility is decreasing in β since the investment has zero expected value and the individual is risk averse. So, β = 0 is optimal in this range. When β = 0, expected utility reduces to EU β = p u(w α pl (1 α)l)+ (1 p) u(w α pl). (9) This is increasing in α since insurance is actuarially fair so there is a corner solution for the optimal α. The optimal α, β pair in the range below the bankruptcy line is α = 1 and β = 0, i.e., full insurance and investment in the risky project. It is never optimal to purchase full insurance and invest in the risky prospect, simultaneously; i.e., an outcome of ˆ α = 1 and ˆ β > 0 is never optimal. This follows straightforwardly from the fact that all α, β pairs such that α = 1 are in the feasible non-bankruptcy range where β = 0 is optimal. If an optimal outcome is to be found with both insurance and investment in the risky project, it must be in the feasible bankruptcy range. To see if such a possibility exists, it is necessary to find the levels of α and β that maximize EU β+ within the feasible bankruptcy range

9 8 and to determine whether they provide a level of expected utility above the full insurance/no investment alternative. EU β+ = π p u(f) +π (1 p) u(w α pl β[w α pl F]) +(1 π )p u(w α pl + ( π (1 π ))β[w α pl F] (1 α)l) +(1 π )(1 p) u(w α pl + ( π (1 π ))β[w α pl F]) (10) has the following partial derivatives which, set equal to zero, give the first order conditions for the maximization problem: EU β+ β = π[w α pl F]{p u #(W 3 )+ (1 p)[ u #(W 4 ) u #(W 2 )]} = 0, (11) EU β+ α = π (1-p) u "(W 2 )(β pl pl)+ (1 π )p u " (W ) $ L pl β $ π ' ' 3 & & ) pl) % % 1 π ( ( # # π & & (1 π )(1 p) u "(W 4 )% pl + β % ( pl( = 0. (12) $ $ 1 π ' ' Manipulation of (11) and (12), gives the following conditions for an interior solution to the maximization of (10): uʹ ( W uʹ ( W 3 ) 1 = ) 1 p 2 π uʹ ( W2 ) 1 π =. (14) uʹ ( W4 ) 1 π p The second order condition is " $ # 2 EU β+ β 2 %" ' $ &# 2 EU β+ α 2 % ' & " 2 EU β+ % $ # α β ' & 2 (13) > 0. (15) Defining ˆα and ˆβ as theα and β that solve (13) and (14), the following conditions also must hold for this solution to be in the interior of the feasible bankruptcy range 0 < ˆα <1 (16a) β 0 ( ˆα) < ˆβ <1 EU β+ ( ˆα, ˆβ) u(w pl) > 0. (16b) (16c)

10 9 Remark: For an interior solution to exist with partial insurance and partial investment (i.e., ˆβ <1), it must be true that 1 π p > 0, i.e., the sum of the probabilities of the project failing and of having a liability loss must be less than 1. This follows from condition (14) since u ʹ ( W ) > 0. i A Solution with Power Utility To obtain further insight into the incentives to both insure and invest in the risky project in the presence of bankruptcy risk it will be assumed that the individual has a power utility " 1 % function, u(w i ) = $ ' W i # 1 r & ( ) 1 r, with r > 0. This utility function, commonly used in both empirical and theoretical studies in economics and finance, exhibits decreasing absolute risk aversion (DARA) and constant relative risk aversion (CRRA). If the individual has a power utility function then the conditions (13) and (14) are:! # " W 2 W 3 and! # " W 2 W 4 $ & % $ & % r r! = 1 π $ # & (17) " 1 p %! 1 π $ = # &. (18) " 1 π p % The optimal levels of insurance and investment for an interior solution are: ˆα = L(π + (1 π )b) W (b a) L(π + (1 π )b) pl(b a) (19) and ˆβ = (W pl)(1 π )(b 1) (W pl F)(π + (1 π )b)+ Fp(b a). (20) " where a = 1 π % $ ' # 1 p & 1 r " 1 π % and b = $ ' # 1 π p & 1 r. In order for this α, β combination to be in the feasible bankruptcy range and to be preferred to full insurance without investment in the risky project, (16a) through (16c) must hold as well.

11 10 With the power utility function, r W represents the Arrow-Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion, so risk aversion varies directly with r. The derivative of ˆα with respect to r in the feasible bankruptcy range is obtained by differentiating (19): ˆα r = # (W pl)l (π + (1 π )b) a & (π + (1 π )a) b $ % r r ' ( L(π + (1 π )b) Lp(b a) [ ] 2 > 0. (21) This follows because b > a > 0 and b r < a r < 0. The derivative of ˆβ with respect to r can be derived using the fact that the first order conditions (17) and (18) give the following relationship between ˆα and ˆβ : ˆβ = (b 1)(1 π )(W ˆα pl) (W ˆα pl F)(π + b(1 π )) and then differentiating this with respect to r, ˆβ r = (22) # (1 π ) (W ˆα pl F)(W ˆα pl) b ˆα & + F(b 1)(π + b(1 π ))pl $ % r r ' ( < 0. (23) [(W ˆα pl F)(π + b(1 π ))] 2 These derivatives have the expected signs, i.e., an increase in risk aversion increases the amount of insurance purchased and decreases the amount gambled on the risky project when an interior solution has been obtained. A Numerical Example Next, an example is given to show that an interior solution is possible for the individual s decision regarding whether to insure and gamble on the risky project. In this example, the potential loss from the liability risk is just short of bankrupting if the risky project is rejected, i.e., L = W F. An actuarially fair premium will lead to full insurance in the absence of the risky investment. Recall that after the insurance premium has been paid, the individual can choose to invest any percentage of the wealth remaining above the floor F, but the zero expected profit project is not attractive if full insurance has been purchased. The most that can be lost with the risky investment is the amount invested, so bankruptcy will not occur if no liability loss is

12 11 incurred or if it is fully insured. The floor on wealth is set at F = 1, simply to avoid division by zero in the analysis. A relatively low level of risk aversion is assumed with r =.075. Given these parameters, the second order condition in (15) for an interior solution to the maximization of EU β+ holds for all W 100,000 when.35 π p 0. Therefore, the optimal insurance-gambling choice will be determined for all probability pairs where the sum of the probability of an insurable loss and the probability that the project fails is less than or equal to.35. The results are identical up to at least four decimal places for all wealth levels above 100,000. Figure p π

13 12 Figure 2 shows the values of ˆα from equation (19), which solve the first order conditions for maximizing EU β+ from equation (10) if the second order condition holds. The origin in this figure is in the rear, right-hand corner to allow a more clear view of the contours of the function. For any π, p pair, the value of ˆα depicted will be the optimal fraction of the liability loss to be insured if there is an interior solution in the feasible bankruptcy range. The dark portion of the surface is where ˆα 0 and the lighter portion is where ˆα < 0 ; therefore, only in the region corresponding to the dark surface is an interior solution possible. Figure 3 depicts this latter information from Figure 2 as viewed from below with the origin at the bottom left. The lower left region of Figure 3, below the line where.35 π p = 0, represents the area of focus where the second order condition holds. Note that as depicted in Figure 2, ˆα decreases both as p increases and as π increases. So, the higher the probability of a liability loss, and the higher the probability that the investment will fail, the less insurance is purchased if there is an interior solution. π 0.35" 0.3" Figure " 0.2" 0.15" 0.1" 0.05" α! < 0 α! 0 3(4" 2(3" 1(2" 0(1" 0" 0" 0.05" 0.1" 0.15" 0.2" 0.25" 0.3" 0.35" p Figure 4 depicts the values of ˆβ derived from equation (20). For any π, p pair, this will be the optimal fraction of the wealth to be invested in the risky project if there is an interior solution for both α and β in the feasible bankruptcy range. Note that ˆβ increases as p increases

14 13 and increases more gradually as π increases. As with ˆα, the only region that is relevant for our example is where.35 π p 0 since that is where the second order condition holds. If ˆα < 0 in Figure 3, then for those π, p pairs, α must be replaced with zero in EU β+ in equation (10) and the first order condition for β in (11) must be solved with α = 0 to obtain the optimal fraction of wealth to be invested in the risky asset if an interior solution exists for β in the absence of insurance. Figure β π p Figure 5 depicts three regions in the part of π, p space where π + p.35. In region 1, the optimal decision for the individual is to buy full insurance and to invest nothing in the risky project. This outcome results from the fact that condition (16c), EU β+ ( ˆα, ˆβ) u(w pl) > 0, is violated, or if α < 0, condition (16c) is violated when α is replaced by 0 and β is replaced by the value of β which maximizes (10) when α = 0. For the probability pairs in region 2, it is optimal for the individual to both insure and gamble on the risky project, since α and β comprise an interior solution for the maximization of EU β+ in (10) and at that solution, conditions (16a) - (16c) are not violated. In this region, the higher the probability of a liability loss, and/or the higher the probability that the investment will fail, the more wealth is invested in the risky

15 14 project and the less insurance is purchased. In region 3, the optimal choice for the individual is to go uninsured and to invest in the risky project. Since α is negative in this region, the optimal β is determined by the maximization of EU β+ while α is set to zero. In this range, the proportion of wealth invested in the risky asset increases as p increases and as π increase. In both regions 2 and 3, the proportion of wealth put at risk approaches but remains under 1 as each of the two loss probabilities increases. Figure 5 π 0.35" 0.3" 0.25" 0.2" " 0.1" 0.05" 1 2 0" 0" 0.05" 0.1" 0.15" 0.2" 0.25" 0.3" 0.35" p Bankruptcy is not possible in region 1 of Figure 5, but in regions 2 and 3 the individual is sure to experience bankruptcy if both the liability loss occurs and the risky project fails. This bankruptcy risk is endogenously chosen and makes investment in the risky project desirable. Importantly, in region 2, even while bankruptcy risk is willingly chosen, the individual chooses to purchase insurance. As the level of risk aversion as measured by r decreases, regions 2 and 3 expand toward the south and west such that full insurance is chosen under fewer p, π pairs and the region where the risky project is undertaken correspondingly expands. This also implies that exposure to bankruptcy risk is chosen for this growing set of p, π pairs as well. The opposite is true when the risk aversion parameter r increases, with more p, π pairs corresponding to full insurance and a smaller region of probability pairs associated with endogenously chosen bankruptcy risk.

16 15 CONCLUSION The model and analysis in this paper show that for a large set of parameters, the decision to both gamble on a zero expected profit project and purchase insurance is rational and consistent with expected utility maximization and risk aversion. The affect of limited liability in altering the expected benefits and costs of both the insurance and risky investment is the driving force behind the results presented here. A risk averse individual may choose to purchase less than full insurance, even though premiums are actuarially fair, and simultaneously gamble on a risky project with an otherwise zero expected value, because limited liability both decreases the expected benefit of insurance and increases the expected benefit of the project. Gambling and insurance will not occur simultaneously unless the amount invested is sufficiently large and the amount insured is sufficiently small so that bankruptcy is certain to occur if both an insurable loss and a gambling loss occur. Without the possibility of bankruptcy, the expected benefits of insurance and the risky investment are unaltered and full insurance without investment is preferred. These results offer an explanation for why entrepreneurs and closely held firms may purchase insurance while engaging in a go-for-broke investment strategy. If that type of behavior is optimal for the entrepreneur, a full insurance requirement can stop it. The purchase of partial insurance is not a signal that go-for-broke investing in zero expected value projects will not take place. To the extent that neither the insured loss nor the gamble alone can bankrupt the individual, this type of strategy is distinct from the case where a preexisting chance of default induces excessive risk-taking. Here, the possibility of default is created along with the incentives that typically come along with it.

17 16 REFERENCES Athreya, Kartik, 2006, Fresh Start or Head Start? Uniform Bankruptcy Exemptions and Welfare, Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, Vol. 30, Conlisk, John, 1993, The Utility of Gambling, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 6, Doherty, Neil A. and Harris Schlesinger, 1983, "The Optimal Deductible for an Insurance Policy When Initial Wealth is Random," The Journal of Business, Vol. 56, Forlani, David and John W.Mullins, 2000, Perceived Risks and Choices in Entrepreneurs New Venture Decisions, Journal of Business, Vol. 15, Fossen, Frank M., 2014, Personal Bankruptcy Law, Wealth, and Entrepreneurship - Evidence from the Introduction of a Fresh Start Policy, American Law and Economics Review, Vol. 16, Friedman, Milton and J.L. Savage, 1948, "The Utility Analysis of Choices Involving Risk," Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 56, Gollier, Christian and John W. Pratt, 1996, Risk Vulnerability and the Tempering Effect of Background Risk, Econometrica, 64(5), Guiso, Luigi and Tullio Jappelli, 1998, Background Uncertainty and the Demand for Insurance Against Insurable Risks, The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 23, Huberman, Gur, David Mayers and Clifford W. Smith, Jr., 1983, "Optimal Insurance Indemnity Schedules," Bell Journal of Economics, Vol. 14,

18 17 Jia, Ye, 2010, The Impact of Personal Bankruptcy Law on Entrepreneurship, Working Paper: University of Prince Edward Island. Kimball, Miles S., 1993, Standard Risk Aversion, Econometrica, Vol. 61(3), Leebron, David W., 1991, Limited Liability, Tort Victims and Creditors, Columbia Law Review, Vol. 91, Machina, Mark J., 1982, "'Expected Utility' Analysis Without the Independence Axiom," Econometrica, Vol. 50, Markowitz, Harry, 1952, "The Utility of Wealth," Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 60, Mayers, David, and Clifford W. Smith, Jr., 1983a, On the Corporate Demand for Insurance, Journal of Business, Vol. 55, Mayers, David, and Clifford W. Smith, Jr., 1983b, The Interdependence of Individual Portfolio Decisions and the Demand for Insurance, Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 91, Posey, Lisa Lipowski, 1993, "Limited Liability and Incentives When Firms Can Inflict Damages Greater Than Net Worth," International Review of Law and Economics, Vol. 13, Pratt, John W. and Richard Zeckhauser, 1987, Proper Risk Aversion, Econometrica, 55, Quiggin, John, 1991, "On the Optimal Design of Lotteries," Economica, Vol. 58, Sinn, Hans-Werner, 1982, "Kinked Utility and the Demand for Human Wealth and Liability Insurance," European Economic Review, Vol. 17,

19 18 U.S. Small Business Association, 2012, Small Business Lending in the United States 2012, Winter, Ralph A., 2006, Liability Insurance, Joint Tortfeasors and Limited Wealth, International Review of Law and Economics, 26, Yaari, Menahem E., 1965, Convexity in the Theory of Choice Under Risk, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 79(2),

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty Chapter 7 Choice under Uncertainty 1. Expected Utility Theory. 2. Risk Aversion. 3. Applications: demand for insurance, portfolio choice 4. Violations of Expected Utility Theory. 7.1 Expected Utility Theory

More information

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University \ins\liab\liabinfo.v3d 12-05-08 Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas December

More information

MORAL HAZARD AND BACKGROUND RISK IN COMPETITIVE INSURANCE MARKETS: THE DISCRETE EFFORT CASE. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama.

MORAL HAZARD AND BACKGROUND RISK IN COMPETITIVE INSURANCE MARKETS: THE DISCRETE EFFORT CASE. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama. mhbri-discrete 7/5/06 MORAL HAZARD AND BACKGROUND RISK IN COMPETITIVE INSURANCE MARKETS: THE DISCRETE EFFORT CASE James A. Ligon * University of Alabama and Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas

More information

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Jin Yong Jung We analyze how the wealth of an agent and its distribution affect the profit of the principal by considering the simple

More information

Characterization of the Optimum

Characterization of the Optimum ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 5. Portfolio Allocation with One Riskless, One Risky Asset Characterization of the Optimum Consider a risk-averse, expected-utility-maximizing

More information

This paper addresses the situation when marketable gambles are restricted to be small. It is easily shown that the necessary conditions for local" Sta

This paper addresses the situation when marketable gambles are restricted to be small. It is easily shown that the necessary conditions for local Sta Basic Risk Aversion Mark Freeman 1 School of Business and Economics, University of Exeter It is demonstrated that small marketable gambles that are unattractive to a Standard Risk Averse investor cannot

More information

BACKGROUND RISK IN THE PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama. and. Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas

BACKGROUND RISK IN THE PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama. and. Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas mhbr\brpam.v10d 7-17-07 BACKGROUND RISK IN THE PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL James A. Ligon * University of Alabama and Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas Thistle s research was supported by a grant

More information

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion.

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion. IDEA Economics of Risk and Uncertainty List of Exercises Expected Utility, Risk Aversion, and Stochastic Dominance. 1. Prove that, for every pair of Bernouilli utility functions, u 1 ( ) and u 2 ( ), and

More information

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing Richard M. H. Suen University of Leicester 29 March 2018 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/86499/ MPRA Paper

More information

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Pierre Chaigneau pierre.chaigneau@hec.ca June 14, 2011 Finance: the economics of risk and uncertainty In financial markets, claims associated with random future

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Self-Insurance, Self-Protection and Market Insurance within the Dual Theory of Choice

Self-Insurance, Self-Protection and Market Insurance within the Dual Theory of Choice The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 26: 43 56, 2001 c 2001 The Geneva Association Self-Insurance, Self-Protection and Market Insurance in the Dual Theory of Choice CHRISTOPHE COURBAGE Lombard

More information

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty Introduction to Microeconomics Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty The Five Axioms of Choice Under Uncertainty We can use the axioms of preference to show how preferences can be mapped into measurable

More information

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY LECTURE 5 MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY Choice under Uncertainty (MWG chapter 6, sections A-C, and Cowell chapter 8) Lecturer: Andreas Papandreou 1 Introduction p Contents n Expected utility theory

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions ; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions Prof. Massimo Guidolin Portfolio Management Spring 2016 Outline and objectives Utility functions The expected utility theorem and the axioms

More information

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. FINC3023 Behavioral Finance TOPIC 1: Expected Utility Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. A normative theory based on rational utility maximizers

More information

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I) Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16 (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I) Dealing with Uncertainty 2 Preferences over risky choices (Section 7.1) One simple model: Expected Utility How can old tools be applied to analyze

More information

Behavioral Insurance: An Introduction

Behavioral Insurance: An Introduction Jimmy Martínez-Correa Behavioral Insurance: An Introduction 7 th International Microinsurance Conference Brazil,November 8 th 2011. Center for the Economic Analysis of Risk Department of Risk Management

More information

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk Risky Choice Probability States of Nature Expected Utility Function Interval Measure Violations Risk Preference State Dependent Utility Risk-Aversion Coefficient Actuarially

More information

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance University of Exeter Recap Last class we looked at the axioms of expected utility, which defined a rational agent as proposed by von Neumann and Morgenstern. We then proceeded to look at empirical evidence

More information

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies Harris Schlesinger Department of Finance, University of Alabama, USA Center of Finance & Econometrics, University of Konstanz, Germany E-mail: hschlesi@cba.ua.edu

More information

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions Shuoxun Hellen Zhang WISE & SOE XIAMEN UNIVERSITY March, 2015 1 / 50 Outline Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation Portfolios, Risk Aversion,

More information

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko ECON 581. Decision making under risk Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko 1 / 36 Outline Expected utility Risk aversion Certainty equivalence and risk premium The canonical portfolio allocation problem 2 / 36 Suggested

More information

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Choice under risk and uncertainty Choice under risk and uncertainty Introduction Up until now, we have thought of the objects that our decision makers are choosing as being physical items However, we can also think of cases where the outcomes

More information

Background Risk and Insurance Take Up under Limited Liability (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Background Risk and Insurance Take Up under Limited Liability (Preliminary and Incomplete) Background Risk and Insurance Take Up under Limited Liability (Preliminary and Incomplete) T. Randolph Beard and Gilad Sorek March 3, 018 Abstract We study the effect of a non-insurable background risk

More information

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno Economics 03: Economics of uncertainty and information TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo PROBLEM # : The expected value of the

More information

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key 1. Exercises from MWG (Chapter 6): (a) Exercise 6.B.1 from MWG: Show that if the preferences % over L satisfy the independence axiom, then for all 2 (0; 1) and

More information

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E. Microeconomic Theory -1- Uncertainty Choice under uncertainty A Introduction to choice under uncertainty B Risk aversion 11 C Favorable gambles 15 D Measures of risk aversion 0 E Insurance 6 F Small favorable

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO September 25, 2015 A Brief Look at General Equilibrium Asset Pricing Last week, we saw a general equilibrium model in which banks were irrelevant.

More information

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models Jack Meyer Department of Economics Michigan State University East Lansing, MI 48824 jmeyer@msu.edu SCC-76: Economics and Management

More information

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected utility and risk aversion 1/ 58 Introduction Expected utility is the standard framework for modeling investor choices. The following topics will be covered:

More information

Mistakes, Negligence and Liabilty. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University. Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas.

Mistakes, Negligence and Liabilty. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University. Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas. \ins\liab\mistakes.v1a 11-03-09 Mistakes, Negligence and Liabilty Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas November, 2009 Thistle would like to thank Lorne

More information

Economic of Uncertainty

Economic of Uncertainty Economic of Uncertainty Risk Aversion Based on ECO 317, Princeton UC3M April 2012 (UC3M) Economics of Uncertainty. April 2012 1 / 16 Introduction 1 Space of Lotteries (UC3M) Economics of Uncertainty. April

More information

Advanced Risk Management

Advanced Risk Management Winter 2014/2015 Advanced Risk Management Part I: Decision Theory and Risk Management Motives Lecture 1: Introduction and Expected Utility Your Instructors for Part I: Prof. Dr. Andreas Richter Email:

More information

STX FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO Risk Aversion and the Purchase of Risky Insurance. Harris Schlesinger

STX FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO Risk Aversion and the Purchase of Risky Insurance. Harris Schlesinger STX FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 1348 *P«F?VOFTH Risk Aversion and the Purchase of Risky Insurance Harris Schlesinger J. -Matthias Graf v. d. Schulenberg College of Commerce and Business Administration Bureau

More information

Prevention and risk perception : theory and experiments

Prevention and risk perception : theory and experiments Prevention and risk perception : theory and experiments Meglena Jeleva (EconomiX, University Paris Nanterre) Insurance, Actuarial Science, Data and Models June, 11-12, 2018 Meglena Jeleva Prevention and

More information

Modeling Interest Rate Parity: A System Dynamics Approach

Modeling Interest Rate Parity: A System Dynamics Approach Modeling Interest Rate Parity: A System Dynamics Approach John T. Harvey Professor of Economics Department of Economics Box 98510 Texas Christian University Fort Worth, Texas 7619 (817)57-730 j.harvey@tcu.edu

More information

Large Losses and Equilibrium in Insurance Markets. Lisa L. Posey a. Paul D. Thistle b

Large Losses and Equilibrium in Insurance Markets. Lisa L. Posey a. Paul D. Thistle b Large Losses and Equilibrium in Insurance Markets Lisa L. Posey a Paul D. Thistle b ABSTRACT We show that, if losses are larger than wealth, individuals will not insure if the loss probability is above

More information

Corporate Financial Management. Lecture 3: Other explanations of capital structure

Corporate Financial Management. Lecture 3: Other explanations of capital structure Corporate Financial Management Lecture 3: Other explanations of capital structure As we discussed in previous lectures, two extreme results, namely the irrelevance of capital structure and 100 percent

More information

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the open text license amendment to version 2 of the GNU General

More information

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract Linear risk tolerance and mean variance preferences Andreas Wagener University of Vienna Abstract We translate the property of linear risk tolerance (hyperbolical Arrow Pratt index of risk aversion) from

More information

Behavioral Economics (Lecture 1)

Behavioral Economics (Lecture 1) 14.127 Behavioral Economics (Lecture 1) Xavier Gabaix February 5, 2003 1 Overview Instructor: Xavier Gabaix Time 4-6:45/7pm, with 10 minute break. Requirements: 3 problem sets and Term paper due September

More information

Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment

Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment George Alogoskoufis, Dynamic Macroeconomic Theory, 2015 Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment In this chapter we present the main neoclassical model of investment, under convex adjustment costs. This

More information

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk Preliminaries We treat, for convenience, money as a continuous variable when dealing with monetary outcomes. Strictly speaking, the derivation

More information

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Measuring Risk Preferences. Professor: Pamela Jakiela

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Measuring Risk Preferences. Professor: Pamela Jakiela AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics Measuring Risk Preferences Professor: Pamela Jakiela Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics University of Maryland, College Park Expected Utility

More information

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty Unit 4.: Uncertainty Michael Malcolm June 8, 20 Up until now, we have been considering consumer choice problems where the consumer chooses over outcomes that are known. However, many choices in economics

More information

THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS. A. Schepanski The University of Iowa

THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS. A. Schepanski The University of Iowa THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS A. Schepanski The University of Iowa May 2001 The author thanks Teri Shearer and the participants of The University of Iowa Judgment and Decision-Making

More information

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński Decision Making in Manufacturing and Services Vol. 9 2015 No. 1 pp. 79 88 Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment Andrzej Paliński Abstract. This paper presents a model of bank-loan repayment as

More information

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING?

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING? Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING? Kathryn Sullivan* Abstract This study reports on five experiments that

More information

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility Alexander Wolitzky MIT 14.121 1 Expected Utility and Its Discontents Expected utility (EU) is the workhorse model of choice under uncertainty. From very early

More information

General Equilibrium with Risk Loving, Friedman-Savage and other Preferences

General Equilibrium with Risk Loving, Friedman-Savage and other Preferences General Equilibrium with Risk Loving, Friedman-Savage and other Preferences A. Araujo 1, 2 A. Chateauneuf 3 J.Gama-Torres 1 R. Novinski 4 1 Instituto Nacional de Matemática Pura e Aplicada 2 Fundação Getúlio

More information

A Simple Utility Approach to Private Equity Sales

A Simple Utility Approach to Private Equity Sales The Journal of Entrepreneurial Finance Volume 8 Issue 1 Spring 2003 Article 7 12-2003 A Simple Utility Approach to Private Equity Sales Robert Dubil San Jose State University Follow this and additional

More information

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2013 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Subjective Expected Utility Theory

Subjective Expected Utility Theory Subjective Expected Utility Theory Mark Dean Behavioral Economics Spring 2017 Introduction In the first class we drew a distinction betweem Circumstances of Risk (roulette wheels) Circumstances of Uncertainty

More information

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion Uncertainty Outline Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion 2 Simple Lotteries 3 Simple Lotteries Advanced Microeconomic Theory

More information

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009 MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 14.123 Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. MIT 14.123 (2009) by

More information

WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05

WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05 October 2011 WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05 Even (mixed) risk lovers are prudent David Crainich CNRS-LEM and IESEG School of Management Louis Eeckhoudt IESEG School of Management (LEM-CNRS) and CORE

More information

Equation Chapter 1 Section 1 A Primer on Quantitative Risk Measures

Equation Chapter 1 Section 1 A Primer on Quantitative Risk Measures Equation Chapter 1 Section 1 A rimer on Quantitative Risk Measures aul D. Kaplan, h.d., CFA Quantitative Research Director Morningstar Europe, Ltd. London, UK 25 April 2011 Ever since Harry Markowitz s

More information

A Simple Model of Bank Employee Compensation

A Simple Model of Bank Employee Compensation Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Research Department A Simple Model of Bank Employee Compensation Christopher Phelan Working Paper 676 December 2009 Phelan: University of Minnesota and Federal Reserve

More information

Precautionary Insurance Demand with State-Dependent. Background Risk

Precautionary Insurance Demand with State-Dependent. Background Risk Precautionary Insurance Demand with State-Dependent Background Risk Wenan Fei, University of Alabama and Hartford Insurance Harris Schlesinger, University of Alabama and University of Konstanz June 21,

More information

Initial Public Offerings With Bankruptcy Risk: The Entrepreneur's Problem. Paul D. Thistle * Department of Finance University of Nevada Las Vegas

Initial Public Offerings With Bankruptcy Risk: The Entrepreneur's Problem. Paul D. Thistle * Department of Finance University of Nevada Las Vegas \fin\ipobr.v6 4-14-06 Initial Public Offerings With Bankruptcy Risk: The Entrepreneur's Problem Paul D. Thistle * Department of Finance University of Nevada Las Vegas * 4505 Maryland Parkway, Las Vegas,

More information

Bankruptcy risk and the performance of tradable permit markets. Abstract

Bankruptcy risk and the performance of tradable permit markets. Abstract Bankruptcy risk and the performance of tradable permit markets John Stranlund University of Massachusetts-Amherst Wei Zhang University of Massachusetts-Amherst Abstract We study the impacts of bankruptcy

More information

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude Duan LI Department of Systems Engineering & Engineering Management The Chinese University of Hong Kong http://www.se.cuhk.edu.hk/

More information

Non-Expected Utility and the Robustness of the Classical Insurance Paradigm: Discussion

Non-Expected Utility and the Robustness of the Classical Insurance Paradigm: Discussion The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 20:51-56 (1995) 9 1995 The Geneva Association Non-Expected Utility and the Robustness of the Classical Insurance Paradigm: Discussion EDI KARNI Department

More information

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance Risk preferences and stochastic dominance Pierre Chaigneau pierre.chaigneau@hec.ca September 5, 2011 Preferences and utility functions The expected utility criterion Future income of an agent: x. Random

More information

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION Szabolcs Sebestyén szabolcs.sebestyen@iscte.pt Master in Finance INVESTMENTS Sebestyén (ISCTE-IUL) Choice Theory Investments 1 / 65 Outline 1 An Introduction

More information

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty Information Economics (Ec 515) George Georgiadis Today, we will study settings in which decision makers face uncertain outcomes. Natural when dealing with asymmetric

More information

An Economic Analysis of Compulsory and Voluntary Insurance

An Economic Analysis of Compulsory and Voluntary Insurance Volume, Issue (0) ISSN: 5-839 An Economic Analysis of Compulsory and Voluntary Insurance Kazuhiko SAKAI Mahito OKURA (Corresponding author) Faculty of Economics Kurume University E-mail: sakai_kazuhiko@kurume-uacjp

More information

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Answers to chapter 3 review questions Answers to chapter 3 review questions 3.1 Explain why the indifference curves in a probability triangle diagram are straight lines if preferences satisfy expected utility theory. The expected utility of

More information

On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries. James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt

On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries. James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt Experimental Economics Center Working Paper 2008-05 Georgia State University On the Empirical Relevance

More information

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017 Problem Set Theory of Banking - Academic Year 06-7 Maria Bachelet maria.jua.bachelet@gmai.com March, 07 Exercise Consider an agency relationship in which the principal contracts the agent, whose effort

More information

Higher-Order Risk Attitudes

Higher-Order Risk Attitudes ANDBOOK OF INSURANCE January, 0 igher-order Risk Attitudes LOUIS EECKOUDT IESEG School of Management, 3 rue de la Digue, 59000 Lille (France) and CORE, 34 Voie du Roman Pays, 348 Louvain-la-Neuve (Belgium);

More information

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2 Prospect theory 1 Introduction Kahneman and Tversky (1979) Kahneman and Tversky (1992) cumulative prospect theory It is classified as nonconventional theory It is perhaps the most well-known of alternative

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure Feedback Effect and Capital Structure Minh Vo Metropolitan State University Abstract This paper develops a model of financing with informational feedback effect that jointly determines a firm s capital

More information

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard December 5, 2012 Question 1 (Comparative Performance Evaluation) Consider the same normal linear model as in Question 1 of Homework 1. This time the principal employs

More information

Citation Economic Modelling, 2014, v. 36, p

Citation Economic Modelling, 2014, v. 36, p Title Regret theory and the competitive firm Author(s) Wong, KP Citation Economic Modelling, 2014, v. 36, p. 172-175 Issued Date 2014 URL http://hdl.handle.net/10722/192500 Rights NOTICE: this is the author

More information

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice Prof. Massimo Guidolin Portfolio Management Spring 2017 Outline and objectives Choice under uncertainty: dominance o Guidolin-Pedio, chapter 1, sec. 2 Choice under

More information

Academic Editor: Emiliano A. Valdez, Albert Cohen and Nick Costanzino

Academic Editor: Emiliano A. Valdez, Albert Cohen and Nick Costanzino Risks 2015, 3, 543-552; doi:10.3390/risks3040543 Article Production Flexibility and Hedging OPEN ACCESS risks ISSN 2227-9091 www.mdpi.com/journal/risks Georges Dionne 1, * and Marc Santugini 2 1 Department

More information

Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited

Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 29: 137 144, 2004 c 2004 The Geneva Association Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited TIMOTHY MATHEWS tmathews@csun.edu Department of Economics,

More information

Wage discrimination and partial compliance with the minimum wage law. Abstract

Wage discrimination and partial compliance with the minimum wage law. Abstract Wage discrimination and partial compliance with the minimum wage law Yang-Ming Chang Kansas State University Bhavneet Walia Kansas State University Abstract This paper presents a simple model to characterize

More information

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013 STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013 Model Structure EXPECTED UTILITY Preferences v(c 1, c 2 ) with all the usual properties Lifetime expected utility function

More information

Exercises for Chapter 8

Exercises for Chapter 8 Exercises for Chapter 8 Exercise 8. Consider the following functions: f (x)= e x, (8.) g(x)=ln(x+), (8.2) h(x)= x 2, (8.3) u(x)= x 2, (8.4) v(x)= x, (8.5) w(x)=sin(x). (8.6) In all cases take x>0. (a)

More information

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows: Topics Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting Expected Utility Theory Violations of EUT Prospect Theory Framing Mental Accounting Application of Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental

More information

Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I

Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I April 2005 PREPARING FOR THE EXAM What models do you need to study? All the models we studied

More information

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours Ekonomia nr 47/2016 123 Ekonomia. Rynek, gospodarka, społeczeństwo 47(2016), s. 123 133 DOI: 10.17451/eko/47/2016/233 ISSN: 0137-3056 www.ekonomia.wne.uw.edu.pl Aggregation with a double non-convex labor

More information

Explaining Insurance Policy Provisions via Adverse Selection

Explaining Insurance Policy Provisions via Adverse Selection The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 22: 121 134 (1997) c 1997 The Geneva Association Explaining Insurance Policy Provisions via Adverse Selection VIRGINIA R. YOUNG AND MARK J. BROWNE School

More information

Analysis of a highly migratory fish stocks fishery: a game theoretic approach

Analysis of a highly migratory fish stocks fishery: a game theoretic approach Analysis of a highly migratory fish stocks fishery: a game theoretic approach Toyokazu Naito and Stephen Polasky* Oregon State University Address: Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics Oregon

More information

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours YORK UNIVERSITY Faculty of Graduate Studies Final Examination December 14, 2010 Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics S. Bucovetsky time=2.5 hours Do any 6 of the following 10 questions. All count

More information

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring Holmstrom and Tirole (JPE, 1993) The main idea A firm would like to issue shares in the capital market because once these shares are publicly traded, speculators

More information

An Empirical Note on the Relationship between Unemployment and Risk- Aversion

An Empirical Note on the Relationship between Unemployment and Risk- Aversion An Empirical Note on the Relationship between Unemployment and Risk- Aversion Luis Diaz-Serrano and Donal O Neill National University of Ireland Maynooth, Department of Economics Abstract In this paper

More information

Advanced Risk Management

Advanced Risk Management Winter 2015/2016 Advanced Risk Management Part I: Decision Theory and Risk Management Motives Lecture 4: Risk Management Motives Perfect financial markets Assumptions: no taxes no transaction costs no

More information

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers. Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel)

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers. Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel) All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel) First Name: Waterloo, April 2013. Last Name: UW ID #:

More information

Leverage Aversion, Efficient Frontiers, and the Efficient Region*

Leverage Aversion, Efficient Frontiers, and the Efficient Region* Posted SSRN 08/31/01 Last Revised 10/15/01 Leverage Aversion, Efficient Frontiers, and the Efficient Region* Bruce I. Jacobs and Kenneth N. Levy * Previously entitled Leverage Aversion and Portfolio Optimality:

More information

Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes

Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes A Simple Martingale Method Approach Frank Thomas Seifried University of Kaiserslautern March 20, 2009 F. Seifried (Kaiserslautern) Deferred Capital

More information

The Kelly Criterion. How To Manage Your Money When You Have an Edge

The Kelly Criterion. How To Manage Your Money When You Have an Edge The Kelly Criterion How To Manage Your Money When You Have an Edge The First Model You play a sequence of games If you win a game, you win W dollars for each dollar bet If you lose, you lose your bet For

More information

Keeping Up with the Joneses Preferences: Asset Pricing Considerations

Keeping Up with the Joneses Preferences: Asset Pricing Considerations Keeping Up with the Joneses Preferences: Asset Pricing Considerations Fernando Zapatero Marshall School of Business USC February 2013 Motivation Economics and Finance have developed a series of models

More information

A Rational, Decentralized Ponzi Scheme

A Rational, Decentralized Ponzi Scheme A Rational, Decentralized Ponzi Scheme Ronaldo Carpio 1,* 1 Department of Economics, University of California, Davis November 17, 2011 Abstract We present a model of an industry with a dynamic, monopoly

More information

Casino gambling problem under probability weighting

Casino gambling problem under probability weighting Casino gambling problem under probability weighting Sang Hu National University of Singapore Mathematical Finance Colloquium University of Southern California Jan 25, 2016 Based on joint work with Xue

More information