Risk Management Decisions in Low Probability and High Loss Risk Situations: Experimental Evidence

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Risk Management Decisions in Low Probability and High Loss Risk Situations: Experimental Evidence"

Transcription

1 Risk Management Decisions in Low Probability and High Loss Risk Situations: Experimental Evidence Ozlem Ozdemir Associate Professor Middle East Technical University (METU) Department of Business Administration, Ankara, Turkey Phone: Andrea Morone (Corresponding Author) Assistant Professor Università degli studi di Bari, Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche, Italy Phone: Fax:

2 Risk Management Decisions in Low Probability and High Loss Risk Situations: Experimental Evidence Abstract Most theoretical and empirical studies have consistently demonstrated that insurance markets for high probability events can be expressed by standard expected utility; however, the EUT is inadequate to explain decision making processes in low probability risk situations. The current study aims to investigate the way people make their insurance decisions in low probability and high loss contexts such as bankruptcy, insolvency, natural disasters etc. More specifically, we try to examine whether elicitation method (buying or paying) induces similar risk management decisions or not, and whether risk attitude and/or threshold probabilities affect the valuations. We test whether preference reversal exists and we elicit individuals threshold probabilities to explore prospective reference theory. The results indicate that subjects considered the probability of loss (the size of the loss) when they face buy or not decision (willingness to pay decision). In addition, the second-order stochastic dominance is supported, however, no evidence is found to conclude that a threshold probability is present in subjects minds. Implications for the insurance market are derived. Keywords: risk management, insurance, low probability. JEL Classification: C91, D81, G 22, G 32 Acknowledgement: The authors would like to gratefully acknowledge the helpful comments of Werner Güth, Jamie Brown Kruse, and the contributions of the participants at the International Association of Research in Economic Psychology and Society for the Advancement of Behavioral Economics Joint Meeting, This paper has been made possible through the financial support of Max Planck Institute of Economics, Jena, Germany. 2

3 I. INTRODUCTION The low probability and high loss (LPHL from now on) events can be expressed as risky situations: the probability of occurrence is low, but the harmful effect can be very dreadful (e.g., bankruptcy, insolvency, natural disasters, terrorism, and some environmental hazards). Both individuals and firms use different risk reduction mechanisms (protective measures) such as credit life insurance, credit insurance, home insurance, storm shelters etc.) in LPHL events. The risky situations have been investigated based on studies conducted at Decision Research (an organization founded in 1976 by Paul Slovic). The different behavioral finance theories and concepts that influence an individual's perception of risk for different types of financial services and investment products are heuristics, overconfidence, prospect theory, loss aversion, representativeness, framing, anchoring, familiarity bias, perceived control, expert knowledge, affect (feelings), and worry (Ricciardi, 2008). Theoretical framework concerning risk and the protective measures chosen by individuals against LPHL risk situations have also been developed over the past thirty years (e.g., Kunreuther, 1979, 1996; Cook and Graham, 1975; Dong et al., 1996; Arrow, 1996). A majority of these models are developed within the framework of Expected Utility Theory (EUT) (von Neumann and Morgenstern, 1944) and most of them attempt to explain the mechanism through which insurance is purchased, specific decision making processes individuals go through, and the factors at play during this incidence (e.g., Friedman and Savage, 1948). However, as Morgenstern (1979, p.178)) mentioned: [T]he domain of our axioms on utility theory is also restricted.for example, the probabilities used must be within certain plausible ranges and not go to 0.01 or even less to 0.001, then be compared to other equally tiny numbers such as 0.02, etc. 3

4 Theories other than the expected utility (e.g. rank-dependent utility theory, generalized expected utility, and prospect theory) have a tendency to overweight low-probability or to be oversensitive towards it (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1981; Machina, 1982; Karmarkar, 1978). With little help from theory, researchers conducted survey and laboratory studies that have mixed conclusions for explaining how individuals value insurance against LPHL risk situations. In numerous survey studies, people are found to perceive the risk as if no hazard exists, while others rate low-probability risk equal to more frequent risk exposure (e.g. McClelland et al., 1990, Brookshire et al., 1985; McDaniels et al., 1992; Slovic et al., 1980; Camerer and Kunreuther, 1989; Kunreuther, 1996). Most laboratory studies have consistently demonstrated that insurance markets for high probability events can be expressed by standard expected utility; however, the EUT is inadequate to explain decision making processes in low probability risk situations 1 (e.g., Schoemaker and Kunreuther, 1979; Hershey and Schoemaker, 1980). Most experiments that took into account the size of loss 2 in addition to the probability of loss conclude that individuals have insurance preference for high probability, low loss risks over low probability, high loss events, when expected losses are the same (Slovic et al., 1977; Schoemaker and Kunreuther, 1979; Kunreuther and Slovic, 1978; Kunreuther and Pauly, 2004; Etchart-Vincent, 2004). While there are many studies investigating insurance decisions under various probabilities of loss events, to the authors knowledge, there exist two main studies on the insurance purchase decisions specifically for LPHL risk situations. McClelland et al. (1993) found bimodal distribution for willingness-to-pay for insuring, the ratio of insurance bid to expected value, at probability of 0.01 and loss of $40 out of $50. However, Ganderton et al. 4

5 (2000) concluded that the insurance bid-expected value ratio values are not showing bimodality (for probabilities between 0.01 and 0.36). Further, they found that probability of the occurrence of the risky event has a dominant role in valuing insurance for low probability and high loss situations. In sum, McClelland et al. (1993) investigated paying decisions while Ganderton et al. (2000) examined buying decisions. The general purpose of our study is to investigate the way people make their insurance decisions in LPHL contexts. Specifically, we try to examine whether elicitation method (buying or paying) induces similar decisions or not, and whether risk attitude and/or threshold probabilities affect the valuations. For the first objective of the current study, we design an experiment that includes both open-ended question to elicit individual willingness to pay for protective measure i.e. insurance (WTP hereafter) and dichotomous question to individual buying the insurance or not decision in order to examine whether Ganderton et al. (2000) conclusion about the relative importance of probability on individual insurance buying decision holds for WTP decision. In fact, according to the preference reversal phenomenon, individuals may consider different kinds of information when they make choice versus pricing decision (Kagel and Roth 1995, Slovic and Lichtenstein, 1968, Grether and Plott, 1979; Holt, 1986; Segal, 1988). The second purpose of our experiment is to determine the subjects risk attitudes. For that, we calculated the ratio of willingness to pay values to expected values and compare the distribution of our data with McClelland et al. (1993). It is important to note that we particularly use the probability of 0.01 since it is the common low probability used in both McClelland et al. (1993) and Ganderton et al. (2000). Third, we aim to elicit threshold probability in individuals minds that make them start to consider having insurance. According to the prospective reference theory, people 5

6 overestimate the risk if the probability is below a particular threshold and underestimate when it is above the threshold probability, clarifying the difference between the actual versus perceived risk (Viscusi and Evans, 1990). The paper is organized as follows: section II presents a model that explains the empirical framework along with the hypotheses to be tested. Section III presents the experimental design and sections IV and V respectively results and conclusion of the paper. II. THE RESEARCH MODEL Suppose the loss event occurs with a probability of P and the amount of loss is L, the value of the willingness to pay to reduce risk is B, hence given the amount of endowment, W; the individual expected utility would be: 1. without the insurance: (1) 2. with the insurance: (2) where 0 < P < 1, L 0, B 0, and W > 0. Individual maximum WTP can be found by setting Equation (1) equal to Equation (2) and solving for B i.e. certainty equivalent. We determine the certainty equivalents for four different risk situations in our experiment, depending upon whether the loss size is partial, L= W/2 or full, L=W, and upon the probability of loss equals 0.01 or Note that the expected values for full loss size with probability and partial loss size with probability 0.01 are equal. With the framework explained above, we aim to show whether B is mainly affected by P or L. We believe it depends on how B is elicited from the subjects in the experimental setting. If dichotomous question (whether they would buy insurance or not) is asked, then B has a binary value and subjects have to make a choice decision, but if open ended question 6

7 (their WTP) is asked, then B has a continuous value and subjects have to make a payment decision. Hence, Hypothesis 1: When B has a binary value, B is mainly affected by the probability of loss, while it is affected by the loss size when it has a continuous value (consistent with preference reversal) We think it can be interesting to test whether second-degree stochastic dominance (SDSD hereafter) is satisfied for our data. The stochastic dominance, which was introduced by Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) using a mean-preserving spread concept, has had many theoretical and empirical applications in the risk and insurance literature (e.g., Machina and Pratt, 1997; Müller, 1998). It can be briefly explained as: a probability distribution dominates another probability distribution if the expected utility of G is at least large as the expected utility of F for every concave and non-decreasing utility function (Borglin and Keiding, 2002). If we define B1 as the certainty equivalent in the risk situation with full loss size, probability of loss being 0.01, B2 as the certainty equivalent for the risk with full loss size, probability of loss being 0.005, B3 as the certainty equivalent for the risk with partial loss size, probability of loss being 0.01, B4 as the certainty equivalent for the risk with partial loss size, probability of loss being 0.005, then: Hypothesis 2: The second-degree stochastic dominance is satisfied, meaning that B1>B2>B3>B4. The relative risk attitude is measured through calculating the value of B/EV (EV is the expected value) based on McClelland et al. (1993). Values of B/EV higher than 1 indicates 7

8 risk aversion lower than 1 indicates risk seeking, and the equality to 1 indicates risk neutrality. 3 According to the well-known fourfold patterns of risk attitudes as suggested by Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979), people are risk averse for gains and risk seekers for losses in high probability events, and risk averse for losses and risk seekers for gains in low probability events. Hypothesis 3: Consistent with well-known fourfold patterns of risk attitudes as suggested by Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979), B/EV values are greater than 1 for individuals that make an insurance decision under low probability of loss situations. In addition, individual threshold probability of loss i.e. the minimum probability in individual s mind for a given amount of loss for which s/he buys insurance is also elicited in the experiment. Thus, taking into account the equations (1) and (2), we try to determine minimum P for a given B. Further, B is stated to be equal to the expected values of four different risk situations mentioned above. Hypothesis 4: Consistent with Prospective Reference Theory, P values (threshold probabilities) stated by individuals should be equal to or smaller than probability 0.01 for the risk situation with probability 0.01 and should be equal to or smaller than probability 0.05 for the risk situation with probability III. THE EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN The experiment was run in December 2005 at the lab of the Max Planck Institute of Economics, Jena, Germany. The software of the computerized experiment has been developed in z-tree (Fischbacher, 2007). 96 students from Jena University, 32 in each of the 3 8

9 treatments, were recruited to participate in the experiment using the ORSEE software (Greiner, 2004). 45 percent of the subjects were male and 55 percent was female. The average age was 23 (minimum 19 and maximum 39), average monthly income earned by the individual was 348 Euro (minimum 0 and maximum 1100 Euro). Subjects received written instructions after being seated at a computer terminal. 4 As instructions stated, only three out of 96 subjects earned a big payoff. In each of the 3 treatments we had 32 subjects divided in 2 groups in order to test for order effect. The experiment had two phases. In the first phase, we used pair-wise choice (PC), willingness-to-pay (WTP) and willingness-to-accept (WTA) mechanisms. The purpose of this first part was not only to make subjects practice Becker, DeGroot, and Marschak (1964) (hereafter BDM) 5 procedure but also to give them a hard earned income that they had to protect in the second part of the experiment, this would raise the salience of the incentive scheme since we believed subjects would perceive this income as their income and not as manna. The procedure of Phase 1 differed for each treatment. In the first session/treatment, 32 subjects were asked to choose their preferred lottery from 10 (pair-wise choice) lotteries. In the second session, 32 subjects were given 500 ECU (Experimental Currency Unit) in the beginning of the experiment to buy the same 10 lotteries. They were asked to state their buying price for each lottery. We determined whether they bought the lotteries or not through BDM procedure. In the last session, 32 subjects were given 10 lotteries and stated their selling price for each lottery. The selling process was determined through BDM mechanism. A randomly chosen decision was played to determine the initial endowment for Phase 2. All the lotteries used in Phase 1 were composed by two of the four consequences 200 ECU, 300 ECU, 400 ECU, and 500 ECU. The probabilities of these consequences were 9

10 recorded in Table 1. In the experiment the lotteries were presented as segmented circles on the computer screen. Insert Table 1 The procedure of Phase 2 was the same for all three sessions. The subjects completed the first phase of the experiment were randomly divided into two groups. Thus, the first group of 16 subjects stated willingness to pay for buying full insurance that reduced all of their loss in four different loss situations: two different probabilities of loss (p=0.01 and 0.005) and two loss amounts (all the endowment and half of the endowment). For example, WTP1 is WTP 6 in the loss situation where subjects can lose all their money they earned from Phase 1 with a probability of 0.01, WTP2 is WTP in the loss situation where subjects can lose all their money they earned from Phase 1 with a probability of 0.005, WTP3 is WTP in the loss situation where subjects can lose half of their money they earned from Phase 1 with a probability of 0.01, WTP4 is WTP in the loss situation where subjects can lose half of their money they earned from Phase 1 with a probability of BDM mechanism 7 was used to elicit the WTP values: whether subjects got the insurance or not depends on whether their stated WTP was greater or equal to the random price determined by the computer. This random price was between 0 and the amount of money earned from Phase 1. The other 16 subjects stated whether they would buy the insurance (p=0.01 and 0.005, L= all the endowment and half of the endowment)or not. The prices of the insurances were equal to the expected values, ten times the expected values, twenty times the expected values, and finally fifty times the expected values. 8 After all the decisions were made, one of them was selected randomly and played for real to determine subjects money balances at the end of the experiment. 10

11 Then, all of the subjects were asked to state their threshold probabilities after they made buying and paying decisions 9 for the same four different loss situations with prices that were equal to the expected values. Threshold probability was the smallest probability of the occurrence of the loss situation for which the subject would buy the insurance. Whether the subjects got the insurance depended on whether their probability number was smaller or equal to the random number selected by the computer and the random number was between 0 and 1. After subjects completed all 8 situations, one of the loss situations was chosen randomly by the computer and played for real to determine subjects money balances in the experiment. ECU was converted to Euros at the end of the experiment for each session separately. One person in the entire group of respondents participating in each session (about 32 people) converted ECU to Euros at the following exchange rate: 1ECU = 1, and for the others the rate is: 1 ECU = 0.02 (for example, for one person 500 ECU= 500, for others 500ECU = 10). To select that person, we drew a number (1 to 32), and if the number selected matches with the subject s seat number, that person actually received a good amount of money. 10 It is important to note that our data support the second-degree stochastic dominance hypothesis (Hypothesis 2). Indeed, WTP4 dominates WTP3 which dominates WTP2, which dominates WTP1 (WTP1 > WTP2 > WTP3 >WTP4). Further, reducing the probability of loss and increasing the size of loss in a way which preserves the mean (as done in risk situations to determine WTP2 and 3) is called mean-preserving spread (Rothschild and Stiglitz, 1970). Note the WTP 2 is riskier than WTP3. IV. RESULTS Table 2 represents the statistics for 48 individuals that stated their maximum willingness to pay for the insurance in four loss situations. 11

12 Insert Table 2 Subjects stated higher mean value for WTP2 than WTP3 even though both had the same expected values, however Wilcoxon sign rank test (Z=-0.368, p-value= 0.713) concluded that these two values were coming from the same parental distribution which was consistent with EUT 11. To test the statistical significance between willingness-to pay values, we used a Sign test (Table 3). We rejected the hypothesis that the two samples with different loss amounts were drawn for the same parental distribution (p-value for WTP1-WTP3 and p-value for WTP2 - WTP4 are below 0.05). This result might point out that it was the amount of loss that actually determined individual protection valuation when subjects were asked to state their WTP to protect themselves i.e. when they made payment decisions (consistent with Hypothesis 1). Insert Table 3 As for the analysis of 48 subjects that stated whether they would buy the insurance or not in Phase 2, as it can be seen from Table 4, 20.8% of the individuals said yes when asked if they would buy the insurance when the probability of the occurrence of the loss event was 0.01, no matter what the loss amount was (all of the endowment or half of it). The frequency of the buy or not binary responses indicated the dominance of the probability change rather than the loss amount change on the individual decision-making (supporting Hypothesis 1). Insert Table 4 As a result, subjects changed their decisions of buying the insurance or not when probability of occurrence of the event changed; this result was also supported by McNemar test (Table 5). Having analyzed the connection between the effect of the cost of insurance on individual buy- or- not decision and their risk attitudes, we observe that the higher the cost of the insurance was the lower was the percentage of individuals buying it. More specifically, 12

13 when the cost was lower than the twenty times the expected value, the percentage of individuals who decided to buy was higher (around 80%); when the cost of the insurance was the twenty times the expected value, the percentage of subjects who decided to buy and the ones who decided not to buy was almost equal (around 50%). Finally, when the cost was fifty times the EV, the percentage of the individuals that did not buy the insurance (around 75%) became higher than the rate of the ones who bought it. Insert Table 5 The relative risk aversion was calculated as WTP/EV by using willingness to pay for insurance (see McClelland et al. (1993) for details). Higher values of WTP/EV indicated higher level of relative risk aversion. For all individuals, the WTP/EV was above one, indicating risk aversion, which was consistent with the well known fourfold pattern of risk attitudes i.e. Hypothesis 3 (Tversky and Kahneman, 1992; Harbaugh, Krause, and Vesterlund, 2002). A bimodal distribution was found for the ratio of the willingness to pay for protection in situations of probability 0.01 and loss of all endowment (Figure 1). This can be interpreted as evidence to the fact that while some individuals stated 0 as their WTP values others stated values higher than the expected value. Insert Figure 1 Intuitively, a risk-averse individual should more likely to state a threshold probability that is not too much higher than, the probabilities used to calculate the expected values: 0.01 and However, the mean values for the threshold probabilities were 9%, 3.7%, 5.5%, and 4.5% to buy insurance in four loss situations (rejecting the hypothesis 3). In addition, we checked the effects of endowment, gender, age, income 12, and threshold probability on individuals willingness to buy the insurance for a probability of loss that was equal to 0.01 and loss amount of all of the endowment by using a linear regression 13

14 analysis (Table 6). As a result, the higher the endowment of the individual was and the more relatively risk averse the individual was, the higher was value he or she stated as the willingness to pay to buy the insurance (p-values are 0.000). In addition, women were found to state higher values as their willingness to pay to buy the insurance (p-value is 0.041). Insert Table 6 Further, the binary logistic regression was used to analyze the buy- the- insurance or not binary decision (against a loss situation where the probability of loss was 0.01 and loss amount was all of the endowment) as the dependent variable and endowment, gender, age, and income as the independent variables. Gender was found to be the only statistically significant factor (p-value is 0.019) that influenced the buy- or- not decision as women were more inclined to buy the insurance (Table 7). Insert Table 7 V. CONCLUSION AND DISCUSSIONS The LPHL events have not been fully explained by the EUT. While there are many empirical studies investigating insurance decisions under various probabilities of loss events, only two previous works (McClelland et al., 1993; Ganderton et al., 2000) with contradictory results examined insurance decisions in LPHL situations. The current study explores individual insurance valuations for LPHL risks, particularly, it tests whether the valuations differ because some people focus on probability, while others focus on loss or because each individual has his/her own threshold probability (that is consistent with the prospective reference theory) or it is individual risk attitudes that dominates people s decisions. For these purposes, we design an experiment that uses four loss situations with probabilities and 0.01 and loss sizes all income and half income to elicit individuals insurance valuations. To our knowledge, our experiment is the first attempt that 14

15 determines insurance decisions in LPHL situations using both open-ended and dichotomous questions. That not only allows us to compare our results with previous research, but also to test preference reversal phenomenon and to determine individual risk attitudes using the ratios of willingness-to-pay values to the expected values. Further, there is no empirical work that tries to elicit threshold probabilities in individuals minds. In our experiment, we ask subjects to write down the likelihood of the monetary loss that will make them think buying insurance. Our results show that when individuals are asked to state their willingness-to-pay to buy the insurance (payment decision), they perceive the risk to be higher in the case of higher amount of loss rather than higher probability of loss (it is interesting to note that our WTP values support the stochastic dominance introduced by Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970)). However, when individuals are asked whether they will buy the insurance or not (choice decision), the frequencies of the buy or not binary responses seem to support the dominance of the probability of loss rather than the loss amount on the individual decision making. Note that Ganderton et al. (2000) through using a buy or not question (rather than WTP question) concluded the relative importance of probability on individual insurance buying decision. In sum, one important contribution of this study is to reveal the distinction between the action (or choice) decision and the valuation (or payment) decision embodied in the different descriptions of WTP. Economic theory does not distinguish the WTP measures along these lines. However, this result seems supportive of the preference reversal phenomenon (individuals may consider different kinds of information when they make choice versus pricing decision) of which significance remains even in experiments with different structures (Pommerehne et al., 1982). In fact, regulatory agencies even distinguish between probabilistic (concerned with likelihood) and deterministic (concerned with magnitude) risk assessments (Kuhn and Budescu, 1996). 15

16 When people decide whether to buy insurance or not against LPHL events, they focus on probability that is low and this may be a possible reason of why people do not prefer to insure themselves against for example bankruptcy. However, when people pass the buying decision stage and come to the payment decision, they primarily take into account the high loss amount. For that, it is very important to convince individuals to decide to buy credit insurance. For all subjects, the ratio of the willingness to pay to the expected value is above one, indicating risk aversion, which is consistent with well-known fourfold patterns of risk attitudes as suggested by Prospect Theory: risk averse for gains and risk seeking for losses in high probability events, and risk averse for losses and risk seeking for gains in low probability events. As an additional investigation for the ratio of WTP to expected value, McClelland et al. (1993) bimodal distribution conclusion for the probability 0.01 is supported in our study. One possible reason may be we used BDM mechanism that enables us to see zero bids. However, as it is mentioned by Ganderton et al. (2000), dichotomous buying insurance or not question might not allow to see zero bids and that is why Ganderton et al. (2000) results contradicts with McClelland et al. (1993) results. This interpretation might have been generalized if we could estimate WTP values from buy or not questions. The threshold probabilities, in average, are much higher than the probabilities used to calculate the expected values and seem to have no significant correlation with any variable, providing no support for the prospective reference theory. Consistent with intuition, initial endowment of the individuals is found to have a positive impact on the value of their willingness to pay. Finally, being a woman has a positive impact on both individual insurance buying decision and willingness to pay for buying the insurance. 16

17 For further studies, insurance can be assumed to reduce the possible monetary loss to a certain level rather than to zero. Various elicitation mechanisms (see Holt, 1986 for the drawbacks of paying only one round) and loss situations with different probabilities and loss amounts can be used to investigate the distinction between insurance payment and choice decisions to generalize the results. The dichotomous versus open-ended questions used to elicit individual protection valuation can be designed in a way that enables the researcher to compare the risk attitude measurements for both. The current experiment takes the expected values as the prices of the insurances to get the threshold probabilities in individuals minds, different price levels may help for further contributions. Finally, an extended theoretical investigation is necessary to support the findings of the current experiment s results. 17

18 REFERENCES K. J. ARROW (1996), The theory of risk bearing: small and great risks. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 12(2/3), pp G. M. BECKER, M. E. DEGROOT, J. MARSCHAK (1964), Measuring utility by a single-response sequential method. Behavioral Science, vol. 9, pp A. BORGLIN, H. KEIDING, Stochastic dominance and conditional expectation-an insurance theoretical approach. The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, vol. 27, pp D. S. BROOKSHIRE, M. A. THAYER, J. TSCHIRHART, W. D. SCHULZE (1985), A test of the expected utility model: evidence from earthquake risks. Journal of Political Economy, 93(2), pp C. F. CAMERER, H. KUNREUTHER (1989), Decision processes for low probability events: policy implications. Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 8(4), pp C. CAMERER (1995), Individual Decision Making, in J. H. Kagel, and A. E. Roth (eds), Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton University Press, pp P. J. COOK, D. A. GRAHAM (1975), The Demand for Insurance and Protection: The Case of the Irreplaceable Commodity. Draft Report, Duke University, North Carolina. W. DONG, H. C. SHAH, F. WONG (1996), A rational approach to pricing of catastrophe insurance. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 12(2/3), pp

19 N. ETCHART-VINCENT (2004), Is probability weighting sensitive to the magnitude of consequences: an experimental investigation on losses. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 28 (3), pp ,. M. FRIEDMAN, L. J. SAVAGE (1948), The utility analysis of choices involving risk. Journal of Political Economy, vol. 56, pp U. FISCHBACHER (2007), Zurich toolbox for readymade economic experiments. Experimental Economics, vol.10, pp P. T. GANDERTON, D. S. BROOKSHIRE, M. MCKEE, S. STEWART, H. THURSTON (2000), Buying insurance for disaster-type risks: experimental evidence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 20 (3), pp B. GREINER (2004), An Online Recruitment System for Economic Experiments, in K. Kremer and V. Macho (eds.), Forschung und wissenschaftliches Rechnen. GWDG Bericht 63. Ges. für Wiss. Datenverarbeitung, Göttingen, 2004, D.M. GRETHER, PLOTT, C. R. (1979), Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review, 69 (4), pp W. HARBAUGH, K. KRAUSE, L. VESTERLUND (2002), Prospect theory in choice and pricing tasks. University of Oregon Economics Working Paper No J. C. HERSHEY, P. J. H. SCHOEMAKER (1980), Risk taking and problem context in the domain of losses: an expected utility analysis. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 47 (1), pp C. A. HOLT (1986), Preference reversals and the independence axiom. American Economic Review, 76 (3), pp J. H. KAGEL, A. E. ROTH (1995), The Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton. 19

20 D. KAHNEMAN, A. TVERSKY (1979), Prospect Theory, an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, vol. 47, pp U. D. KARMARKAR (1978), Subjectively weighted utility: a descriptive extension of the expected utility model. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, vol. 21, pp K. M. KUHN, BUDESCU D. V. (1996), The relative importance of probabilities, outcomes, and vagueness in hazard risk decisions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 68 (3), pp H. KUNREUTHER, M. PAULY (2004), Neglecting disaster: why don t people insure against large losses?. The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 28 (1), pp H. KUNREUTHER (1979), The changing societal consequences of risks from natural hazards. Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, vol. 443: pp H. KUNREUTHER, P. SLOVIC (1978), Economics, psychology, and protective behavior. American Economic Review, 68:2, Papers and Proceedings of the Ninetieth annual Meeting of the American Economic Association, pp S. LICHTENSTEIN, P. SLOVIC (1971), Reversals of preferences between bids and choices in gambling decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, vol. 89, pp M. J. MACHINA (1982), Expected utility analysis without the independence axiom. Econometrica, vol. 50, pp M. J. MACHINA, J. W. PRATT (1997), Increasing risk: some direct constructions. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol.14, pp

21 G. H. MCCLELLAND, W. D. SCHULZE, B. HURD (1990), The effect of risk beliefs on property values: a case study of a hazardous waste site. Risk Analysis, 10(4), pp G. H. MCCLELLAND, W. D. SCHULZE, D. L. COURSEY (1993), Insurance for lowprobability hazards: a bimodal response to unlikely events. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 7, pp T. L. MCDANIELS, M. S. KAMLET, G. W. FISCHER (1992), Risk Perception and the value of safety. Risk Analysis, 12 (4), pp O. MORGENSTERN (1979), Some Reflections on Utility Theory, in M. Allais and O. Hagen (eds.), Expected Utility Hypothesis and the Allais Paradox, Dorbrecht: D. Reidel. A. MÜLLER (1998), Comparing risks with unbounded distributions. Journal of Mathematical Economics, vol. 30, pp W.W. POMMEREHNE, F. SCHNEIDER, P. GRETHER, C. R. PLOTT (1982), Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon: a reexamination/reply. American Economic Review, 72 (3), pp V. RICCIARDI (2008), The Psychology of Risk: The Behavioral Finance Perspective, in F. J. Fabozzi (eds.), Handbook of Finance: Volume 2: Investment Management and Financial Management, Wiley, pp M. ROTHSCHILD, J. E. STIGLITZ (1970), Increasing risk: I.A. definition. Journal of Economic Theory, vol. 2, pp P. J. H. SCHOEMAKER, H. KUNREUTHER (1979), An experimental study of insurance decisions. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 46 (4), pp

22 U. SEGAL (1988), Does the preference reversal phenomenon necessarily contradict the independence axiom?. American Economic Review, 78 (1), pp P. SLOVIC, S. LICHTENSTEIN (1968), Relative importance of probabilities and payoffs in risk taking. Journal of Experimental Psychology Monograph Supplement, 78 (3/2), pp P. SLOVIC, B. FISCHHOFF, S. LICHTENSTEIN (1980), Facts and Fears: Understanding Perceived Risk, in R. C. Schwing and W. Albers (eds.), Societal Risk Assessments: How Safe Is Safe Enough? Jr. Plenum Press, New York, P. SLOVIC, B. FISCHHOFF, S. LICHTENSTEIN, B. CORRIGAN, B. COMBS (1977), Preference for insuring against probable small losses: insurance implications. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 44(2), pp A. TVERSKY, D. KAHNEMAN (1981), The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, New Series, vol. 221, pp W. K. VISCUSI, W. N. EVANS (1990), Utility functions that depend on health status: estimates and economic implications. American Economic Review, 80 (3), pp J. VON NEUMANN, O. MORGENSTERN (1944), Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton University Press, Princeton. 22

23 Table 1. The probabilities & gains of the lotteries in part ECU 300 ECU 400 ECU 500 ECU

24 Table 2. Descriptive Statistics for Willingness-to-pay Values* Mean Standard deviation Minimum Maximum WTP WTP WTP WTP *WTP1 the willingness to pay amount when probability of loss= 0.01 and loss amount=all of the endowment, WTP2 is the willingness to pay amount when probability of loss= and loss amount= all of the endowment, WTP3 is the willingness to pay amount when probability of loss= 0.01 and loss amount= half of the endowment, WTP4 is the willingness to pay amount when probability of loss= and loss amount= half of the endowment. 24

25 Table 3. Sign Test between Each Pair of WTP Values (Payment Decision) WTP3- WTP2 WTP2- WTP1 WTP3- WTP1* WTP4- WTP3 WTP4- WTP2* WTP4- WTP1* Z values p-values * Significant at 95% level (2-tailed) in that these values are not derived from the same parental distribution. WTP3-WTP2 = the difference in the mean values of WTP when expected values are the same. WTP2- WTP1= the difference in the mean values of WTP when probability changes from to 0.01, loss amount being the same (L= all of the endowment). WTP3-WTP1 = the difference in the mean values of WTP when loss amount changes from half of the endowment to all of the endowment, probability being the same (p= 0.01). WTP4-WTP3 = the difference in the mean values of WTP when probability changes from to 0.01, loss amount being the same (L= half of the endowment). WTP4-WTP2 = the difference in the mean values of WTP when loss amount changes from half of the endowment to all of the endowment, probability being the same (p= 0.005). 25

26 Table 4. Frequencies of Individual Buy or Not (Choice) Decisions* Frequency Percent BON BON BON BON *BON1= buy or not decision when the probability of the occurrence of the loss event is 0.01, loss amount is all of the endowment, BON2= buy or not decision when the probability of the occurrence of the loss event is 0.005, loss amount is all of the endowment, BON3= probability of the occurrence of the loss event is 0.01, loss amount is half of the endowment, BON4= probability of the loss event is 0.005, loss amount is half of the endowment. 0 refers to not buying the insurance and 1 refers to buying the insurance. 26

27 Table 5. McNemar Test between Each Pair of Buy or not Values (Choice Decision) BON1& BON2** BON1& BON3 BON2& BON4 BON1& BON4* BON2& BON3 BON3& BON4* N p-values BON1= buy or not decision when the probability of the occurrence of the loss event is 0.01, loss amount is all of the endowment, BON2= buy or not decision when the probability of the occurrence of the loss event is 0.005, loss amount is all of the endowment, BON3= probability of the occurrence of the loss event is 0.01, loss amount is half of the endowment, BON4= probability of the loss event is 0.005, loss amount is half of the endowment. 0 refers to not buying the insurance and 1 refers to buying the insurance. *Significant at 95% level (2-tailed) in that these values are not derived from the same parental distribution. ** Significant at 90% level (2-tailed) in that these values are not derived from the same parental distribution. 27

28 Figure 1. The frequency distribution for WTP1/EV* *WTP1/EV refers to the ratio of the willingness to pay value for the insurance when probability of the occurrence of the loss event is 0.01 and the loss amount is all of the endowment to the expected value (EV= 0.01*all of the endowment earned in Phase 1). 28

29 Table 6. Regression Analysis Results of WTP1* Coefficient t-statistics p-value s Intercept Endowment** Gender** Age Income Threshold Risk attitude** Adj.R-square=0.77, degrees of freedom=6, F-statistics= significance p-value=0.000 * Dependent variable: WTP1= WTP value in the loss situation where subjects can lose all their money they earned from Phase 1 with a probability of the occurence of loss event **Significant at the 95% level in that being women, having larger amount of endowment, being relatively more risk averse person have positive impact on WTP1. Endowment is the amount of money that subjects earn form Phase 1 of the experiment. Data for age and income (the monthly income of the subjects) are obtained through a questionnaire asked before the experiment. Threshold is the threshold probability that is stated by the subjects during the experiment. Risk attitude is the four WTP/expected values that are used as a multiple-indicant measure of the participants risk attitudes. The internal consistency measure (Crobach s alpha) across these four indicants is estimated as 0.88, suggesting that the risk attitude measure is highly reliable. 29

30 Table 7. Regression Analyses for Buying Insurance Decisions Coefficient p-value Endowment Gender * Age Income Wald= , degrees of freedom=1, p-value = R-square=0.46, degrees of freedom=5, F-statistics=7.258, p-value=0.000 Dependent variable: BON1= Buying the insurance or not binary values, 0 refers to not buying and 1 refers to buying, in the loss situation where subjects can lose all their endowment they earned from Phase 1 with the probability of the occurence of loss event being *Significant at the 95% level in that being women has a positive impact on buying the insurance. Date for age and income (the monthly income of the subjects) is obtained through a questionnaire asked before the experiment. Endowment is the amount of money subjects earned from Phase 1 of the experiment. 30

31 1 The low probability is taken below 0.2 in Camerer (Kagel and Roth, Ch 8, pg. 641, 1995), 0.01 in McClelland et al. (1993), and between and 0.36 (mostly below 0.01) in Ganderton et al. (2000). 2 The frequency of EU violations appears to depend on the size of gamble payoffs. [ ] There are more violations when payoffs are large in magnitude Camerer (1995). 3 The proof is provided by McClelland et al. (1993, pg. 98). 4 The original instructions were in German. Instructions in English are available upon request. 5 We chose to use BDM, because we wanted the subjects to get used to the mechanism used in the second phase. 6 WTP refers to B value in our research model. 7 We intentionally choose to use BDM mechanism to elicit willingness to pay values (Kagel and Roth, 1995), because we wanted the mechanism to be noncompetitive to compare our results with the results of McClelland et al. (1993) competitive auction study (see Ganderton et al. (2000) for more discussions). 8 The reason why these prices are chosen is that expected values are already very low as for the price of the insurance that would eliminate all the loss (for example for the probability of with the endowment of 500 ECU, the expected value would be only 5 ECU and this is the highest value for the price that can be stated), that, most people are expected to be willing to pay that price. However, it is interesting to detect how far they can pay for this insurance that will enable us to determine the degree of their risk aversion. 9 The reason of not asking some subjects threshold questions first and then the willingness to pay questions is that the main aim of the paper is to relate somehow the bids with the threshold probabilities. By asking the threshold questions initially, most probably subjects would have stated extremely high threshold probability values that would be out of the scope of our research objective. 10 We wanted subjects to make their decisions considering a high loss by not giving them any information about who is going to be selected for the big payment. We had to go through this procedure of selecting only one person because we did not have enough budget to give every subject good amount of money. 11 In fact this result is supported by t-statistics test. 12 The information about subjects age, gender, and income are gathered from a questionnaire asked before the experiment. 31

Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions

Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions Susan K. Laury and Charles A. Holt Prepared for the Handbook of Experimental Economics Results February 2002 I. Introduction

More information

Insurance Demand under Prospect Theory: A Graphical Analysis. by Ulrich Schmidt

Insurance Demand under Prospect Theory: A Graphical Analysis. by Ulrich Schmidt Insurance Demand under Prospect Theory: A Graphical Analysis by Ulrich Schmidt No. 1764 March 2012 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No. 1764

More information

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance University of Exeter Recap Last class we looked at the axioms of expected utility, which defined a rational agent as proposed by von Neumann and Morgenstern. We then proceeded to look at empirical evidence

More information

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING?

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING? Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING? Kathryn Sullivan* Abstract This study reports on five experiments that

More information

A Note on Measuring Risk Aversion

A Note on Measuring Risk Aversion A Note on Measuring Risk Aversion Johannes Maier and Maximilian Rüger March 1, 2010 [Very Preliminary Version!] Abstract In this paper we propose a new method to elicit the intensity of individual s risk

More information

Contracts, Reference Points, and Competition

Contracts, Reference Points, and Competition Contracts, Reference Points, and Competition Behavioral Effects of the Fundamental Transformation 1 Ernst Fehr University of Zurich Oliver Hart Harvard University Christian Zehnder University of Lausanne

More information

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM The Journal of Prediction Markets 2016 Vol 10 No 2 pp 14-21 ABSTRACT A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM Arthur Carvalho Farmer School of Business, Miami University Oxford, OH, USA,

More information

Information Dissemination on Asset Markets with. Endogenous and Exogenous Information: An Experimental Approach. September 2002

Information Dissemination on Asset Markets with. Endogenous and Exogenous Information: An Experimental Approach. September 2002 Information Dissemination on Asset Markets with Endogenous and Exogenous Information: An Experimental Approach Dennis Dittrich a and Boris Maciejovsky b September 2002 Abstract In this paper we study information

More information

The concept of risk is fundamental in the social sciences. Risk appears in numerous guises,

The concept of risk is fundamental in the social sciences. Risk appears in numerous guises, Risk Nov. 10, 2006 Geoffrey Poitras Professor of Finance Faculty of Business Administration Simon Fraser University Burnaby BC CANADA The concept of risk is fundamental in the social sciences. Risk appears

More information

Preference Reversals and Induced Risk Preferences: Evidence for Noisy Maximization

Preference Reversals and Induced Risk Preferences: Evidence for Noisy Maximization The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 27:2; 139 170, 2003 c 2003 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Manufactured in The Netherlands. Preference Reversals and Induced Risk Preferences: Evidence for Noisy Maximization

More information

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Choice under risk and uncertainty Choice under risk and uncertainty Introduction Up until now, we have thought of the objects that our decision makers are choosing as being physical items However, we can also think of cases where the outcomes

More information

Preference Reversals Without the Independence Axiom

Preference Reversals Without the Independence Axiom Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Economics Faculty Publications Department of Economics 1989 Preference Reversals Without the Independence Axiom James C. Cox Georgia State

More information

Ostracism and the Provision of a Public Good Experimental Evidence

Ostracism and the Provision of a Public Good Experimental Evidence Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods Bonn 2005/24 Ostracism and the Provision of a Public Good Experimental Evidence Frank P. Maier-Rigaud Peter Martinsson Gianandrea

More information

Investment in Information Security Measures: A Behavioral Investigation

Investment in Information Security Measures: A Behavioral Investigation Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) WISP 2015 Proceedings Pre-ICIS Workshop on Information Security and Privacy (SIGSEC) Winter 12-13-2015 Investment in Information Security

More information

Investment Decisions and Negative Interest Rates

Investment Decisions and Negative Interest Rates Investment Decisions and Negative Interest Rates No. 16-23 Anat Bracha Abstract: While the current European Central Bank deposit rate and 2-year German government bond yields are negative, the U.S. 2-year

More information

Loss Aversion and Intertemporal Choice: A Laboratory Investigation

Loss Aversion and Intertemporal Choice: A Laboratory Investigation DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES IZA DP No. 4854 Loss Aversion and Intertemporal Choice: A Laboratory Investigation Robert J. Oxoby William G. Morrison March 2010 Forschungsinstitut zur Zukunft der Arbeit Institute

More information

Investor Competence, Information and Investment Activity

Investor Competence, Information and Investment Activity Investor Competence, Information and Investment Activity Anders Karlsson and Lars Nordén 1 Department of Corporate Finance, School of Business, Stockholm University, S-106 91 Stockholm, Sweden Abstract

More information

Measuring and Utilizing Corporate Risk Tolerance to Improve Investment Decision Making

Measuring and Utilizing Corporate Risk Tolerance to Improve Investment Decision Making Measuring and Utilizing Corporate Risk Tolerance to Improve Investment Decision Making Michael R. Walls Division of Economics and Business Colorado School of Mines mwalls@mines.edu January 1, 2005 (Under

More information

Volume 39, Issue 1. Tax Framing and Productivity: evidence based on the strategy elicitation

Volume 39, Issue 1. Tax Framing and Productivity: evidence based on the strategy elicitation Volume 39, Issue 1 Tax Framing and Productivity: evidence based on the strategy elicitation Hamza Umer Graduate School of Economics, Waseda University Abstract People usually don't like to pay income tax

More information

Psychological Factors of Voluntary Retirement Saving

Psychological Factors of Voluntary Retirement Saving Psychological Factors of Voluntary Retirement Saving (August 2015) Extended Abstract 1 Psychological Factors of Voluntary Retirement Saving Andreas Pedroni & Jörg Rieskamp University of Basel Correspondence

More information

Low-Probability Insurance: Are Decisions Consistent with Normative Predictions?

Low-Probability Insurance: Are Decisions Consistent with Normative Predictions? Low-Probability Insurance: Are Decisions Consistent with Normative Predictions? Christian Schade Howard Kunreuther Klaus Peter Kaas * 8 th draft Comments welcome Please do not cite or circulate 23-Sep-01

More information

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk Risky Choice Probability States of Nature Expected Utility Function Interval Measure Violations Risk Preference State Dependent Utility Risk-Aversion Coefficient Actuarially

More information

Asset Pricing in Financial Markets

Asset Pricing in Financial Markets Cognitive Biases, Ambiguity Aversion and Asset Pricing in Financial Markets E. Asparouhova, P. Bossaerts, J. Eguia, and W. Zame April 17, 2009 The Question The Question Do cognitive biases (directly) affect

More information

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. FINC3023 Behavioral Finance TOPIC 1: Expected Utility Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. A normative theory based on rational utility maximizers

More information

Contract Nonperformance Risk and Ambiguity in Insurance Markets

Contract Nonperformance Risk and Ambiguity in Insurance Markets Contract Nonperformance Risk and in Insurance Markets Christian Biener, Martin Eling (University of St. Gallen) Andreas Landmann, Maria Isabel Santana (University of Mannheim) 11 th Microinsurance Conference

More information

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY LECTURE 5 MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY Choice under Uncertainty (MWG chapter 6, sections A-C, and Cowell chapter 8) Lecturer: Andreas Papandreou 1 Introduction p Contents n Expected utility theory

More information

ARE LOSS AVERSION AFFECT THE INVESTMENT DECISION OF THE STOCK EXCHANGE OF THAILAND S EMPLOYEES?

ARE LOSS AVERSION AFFECT THE INVESTMENT DECISION OF THE STOCK EXCHANGE OF THAILAND S EMPLOYEES? ARE LOSS AVERSION AFFECT THE INVESTMENT DECISION OF THE STOCK EXCHANGE OF THAILAND S EMPLOYEES? by San Phuachan Doctor of Business Administration Program, School of Business, University of the Thai Chamber

More information

Are dyads conditionally cooperative? Evidence from a public goods experiment

Are dyads conditionally cooperative? Evidence from a public goods experiment MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Are dyads conditionally cooperative? Evidence from a public goods experiment Andrea Morone and Tiziana Temerario Università degli Studi di Bari Aldo Moro, Italy October

More information

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application Vivek H. Dehejia Carleton University and CESifo Email: vdehejia@ccs.carleton.ca January 14, 2008 JEL classification code:

More information

Further Reflections on Prospect Theory

Further Reflections on Prospect Theory Further Reflections on Prospect Theory Susan K. Laury and Charles A. Holt * June 2002 Abstract This paper reports a new experimental test of prospect theory s reflection effect. We conduct a sequence of

More information

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION Szabolcs Sebestyén szabolcs.sebestyen@iscte.pt Master in Finance INVESTMENTS Sebestyén (ISCTE-IUL) Choice Theory Investments 1 / 65 Outline 1 An Introduction

More information

Reference Dependence and Loss Aversion in Probabilities: Theory and Experiment of Ambiguity Attitudes

Reference Dependence and Loss Aversion in Probabilities: Theory and Experiment of Ambiguity Attitudes Reference Dependence and Loss Aversion in Probabilities: Theory and Experiment of Ambiguity Attitudes Jianying Qiu Utz Weitzel Abstract In standard models of ambiguity, the evaluation of an ambiguous asset,

More information

A study on the significance of game theory in mergers & acquisitions pricing

A study on the significance of game theory in mergers & acquisitions pricing 2016; 2(6): 47-53 ISSN Print: 2394-7500 ISSN Online: 2394-5869 Impact Factor: 5.2 IJAR 2016; 2(6): 47-53 www.allresearchjournal.com Received: 11-04-2016 Accepted: 12-05-2016 Yonus Ahmad Dar PhD Scholar

More information

Causes, consequences, and cures of myopic loss aversion - An experimental investigation

Causes, consequences, and cures of myopic loss aversion - An experimental investigation Discussion Paper No. 171 Causes, consequences, and cures of myopic loss aversion - An experimental investigation Gerlinde Fellner* Matthias Sutter** June 2005 *Gerlinde Fellner, University of Bonn, Department

More information

Bubbles, Experience, and Success

Bubbles, Experience, and Success Bubbles, Experience, and Success Dmitry Gladyrev, Owen Powell, and Natalia Shestakova March 15, 2015 Abstract One of the most robust findings in experimental asset market literature is the experience effect

More information

Real Options: Experimental Evidence

Real Options: Experimental Evidence Real Options: Experimental Evidence C.F. Sirmans School of Business, Unit 1041RE University of Connecticut Storrs, CT 06269-2041 (860) 486-3227 Fax (860) 486-0349 CF@SBA.UCONN.EDU and Abdullah Yavas 409

More information

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected utility and risk aversion 1/ 58 Introduction Expected utility is the standard framework for modeling investor choices. The following topics will be covered:

More information

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium Draft chapter from An introduction to game theory by Martin J. Osborne. Version: 2002/7/23. Martin.Osborne@utoronto.ca http://www.economics.utoronto.ca/osborne Copyright 1995 2002 by Martin J. Osborne.

More information

Diminishing Preference Reversals by Inducing Risk Preferences

Diminishing Preference Reversals by Inducing Risk Preferences Diminishing Preference Reversals by Inducing Risk Preferences By Joyce E. Berg Department of Accounting Henry B. Tippie College of Business University of Iowa Iowa City, Iowa 52242 John W. Dickhaut Department

More information

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows: Topics Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting Expected Utility Theory Violations of EUT Prospect Theory Framing Mental Accounting Application of Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental

More information

On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries. James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt

On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries. James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt Experimental Economics Center Working Paper 2008-05 Georgia State University On the Empirical Relevance

More information

Prize-linked savings mechanism in the portfolio selection framework

Prize-linked savings mechanism in the portfolio selection framework Business and Economic Horizons Prize-linked savings mechanism in the portfolio selection framework Peer-reviewed and Open access journal ISSN: 1804-5006 www.academicpublishingplatforms.com The primary

More information

On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences *

On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences * On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences * By Joyce E. Berg ** John W. Dickhaut *** And Thomas A. Rietz ** July 1999 * We thank James Cox, Glenn Harrison, Vernon Smith

More information

Risk Aversion and Tacit Collusion in a Bertrand Duopoly Experiment

Risk Aversion and Tacit Collusion in a Bertrand Duopoly Experiment Risk Aversion and Tacit Collusion in a Bertrand Duopoly Experiment Lisa R. Anderson College of William and Mary Department of Economics Williamsburg, VA 23187 lisa.anderson@wm.edu Beth A. Freeborn College

More information

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2 Prospect theory 1 Introduction Kahneman and Tversky (1979) Kahneman and Tversky (1992) cumulative prospect theory It is classified as nonconventional theory It is perhaps the most well-known of alternative

More information

Risk-Taking Tournaments: Theory and Experimental Evidence

Risk-Taking Tournaments: Theory and Experimental Evidence DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES IZA DP No. 3400 Risk-Taking Tournaments: Theory and Experimental Evidence Petra Nieken Dirk Sliwka March 2008 Forschungsinstitut zur Zukunft der Arbeit Institute for the Study of

More information

A STUDY ON INFLUENCE OF INVESTORS DEMOGRAPHIC CHARACTERISTICS ON INVESTMENT PATTERN

A STUDY ON INFLUENCE OF INVESTORS DEMOGRAPHIC CHARACTERISTICS ON INVESTMENT PATTERN International Journal of Innovative Research in Management Studies (IJIRMS) Volume 2, Issue 2, March 2017. pp.16-20. A STUDY ON INFLUENCE OF INVESTORS DEMOGRAPHIC CHARACTERISTICS ON INVESTMENT PATTERN

More information

8/31/2011. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. Suggested approximation (See Benartzi and Thaler, 1995) The value function (see Benartzi and Thaler, 1995)

8/31/2011. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. Suggested approximation (See Benartzi and Thaler, 1995) The value function (see Benartzi and Thaler, 1995) ECON4260 Behavioral Economics 3 rd lecture Endowment effects and aversion to modest risk Suggested approximation (See Benartzi and Thaler, 1995) w( p) p p (1 p) 0.61for gains 0.69 for losses 1/ 1 0,9 0,8

More information

Behavioral Responses to Subsidies in Risky Investment Decisions and the Effectiveness of Tax Credits and Grants

Behavioral Responses to Subsidies in Risky Investment Decisions and the Effectiveness of Tax Credits and Grants Arbeitskreis Quantitative Steuerlehre Quantitative Research in Taxation Discussion Papers Hagen Ackermann, Martin Fochmann, Rebecca Temme Behavioral Responses to Subsidies in Risky Investment Decisions

More information

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery? ECON4260 Behavioral Economics 2 nd lecture Cumulative Prospect Theory Expected utility This is a theory for ranking lotteries Can be seen as normative: This is how I wish my preferences looked like Or

More information

Contents. Expected utility

Contents. Expected utility Table of Preface page xiii Introduction 1 Prospect theory 2 Behavioral foundations 2 Homeomorphic versus paramorphic modeling 3 Intended audience 3 Attractive feature of decision theory 4 Structure 4 Preview

More information

Reverse Common Ratio Effect

Reverse Common Ratio Effect Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459 Working Paper No. 478 Reverse Common Ratio Effect Pavlo R. Blavatskyy February 2010 Reverse Common

More information

Advanced Risk Management

Advanced Risk Management Winter 2014/2015 Advanced Risk Management Part I: Decision Theory and Risk Management Motives Lecture 1: Introduction and Expected Utility Your Instructors for Part I: Prof. Dr. Andreas Richter Email:

More information

epub WU Institutional Repository

epub WU Institutional Repository epub WU Institutional Repository Gerlinde Fellner and Matthias Sutter Causes, consequences, and cures of myopic loss aversion - an experimental investigation Working Paper Original Citation: Fellner, Gerlinde

More information

How to Measure Herd Behavior on the Credit Market?

How to Measure Herd Behavior on the Credit Market? How to Measure Herd Behavior on the Credit Market? Dmitry Vladimirovich Burakov Financial University under the Government of Russian Federation Email: dbur89@yandex.ru Doi:10.5901/mjss.2014.v5n20p516 Abstract

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY PART ± I CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 Foundations of Finance I: Expected Utility Theory Foundations of Finance II: Asset Pricing, Market Efficiency,

More information

On the evolution of probability-weighting function and its impact on gambling

On the evolution of probability-weighting function and its impact on gambling Edith Cowan University Research Online ECU Publications Pre. 2011 2001 On the evolution of probability-weighting function and its impact on gambling Steven Li Yun Hsing Cheung Li, S., & Cheung, Y. (2001).

More information

Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky- Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function: A Cautionary Note

Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky- Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function: A Cautionary Note European Financial Management, Vol. 14, No. 3, 2008, 385 390 doi: 10.1111/j.1468-036X.2007.00439.x Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky- Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function: A Cautionary Note Jonathan Ingersoll

More information

Paradoxes and Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Ulrich Schmidt

Paradoxes and Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Ulrich Schmidt Paradoxes and Mechanisms for Choice under Risk by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Ulrich Schmidt No. 1712 June 2011 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel

More information

A STUDY ON FACTORS INFLUENCING OF WOMEN POLICYHOLDER S INVESTMENT DECISION TOWARDS LIFE INSURANCE CORPORATION OF INDIA POLICIES IN CHENNAI

A STUDY ON FACTORS INFLUENCING OF WOMEN POLICYHOLDER S INVESTMENT DECISION TOWARDS LIFE INSURANCE CORPORATION OF INDIA POLICIES IN CHENNAI www.singaporeanjbem.com A STUDY ON FACTORS INFLUENCING OF WOMEN POLICYHOLDER S INVESTMENT DECISION TOWARDS LIFE INSURANCE CORPORATION OF INDIA POLICIES IN CHENNAI Ms. S. Pradeepa, (PhD) Research scholar,

More information

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives CHAPTER Duxbury Thomson Learning Making Hard Decision Third Edition RISK ATTITUDES A. J. Clark School of Engineering Department of Civil and Environmental Engineering 13 FALL 2003 By Dr. Ibrahim. Assakkaf

More information

PERUVIAN ECONOMIC ASSOCIATION. Does Competition Aggravate Moral Hazard? A Multi-Principal-Agent Experiment

PERUVIAN ECONOMIC ASSOCIATION. Does Competition Aggravate Moral Hazard? A Multi-Principal-Agent Experiment PERUVIAN ECONOMIC ASSOCIATION Does Competition Aggravate Moral Hazard? A Multi-Principal-Agent Experiment Olga A. Rud Jean Paul Rabanal John Horowitz Working Paper No. 86, December 2016 The views expressed

More information

The Investment Behavior of Small Investors in the Hong Kong Derivatives Markets: A Statistical Analysis

The Investment Behavior of Small Investors in the Hong Kong Derivatives Markets: A Statistical Analysis The Investment Behavior of Small Investors in the Hong Kong Derivatives Markets: A Statistical Analysis Tai-Yuen Hon* Abstract: In the present study, we attempt to analyse and study (1) what sort of events

More information

Reduction of Compound Lotteries with. Objective Probabilities: Theory and Evidence

Reduction of Compound Lotteries with. Objective Probabilities: Theory and Evidence Reduction of Compound Lotteries with Objective Probabilities: Theory and Evidence by Glenn W. Harrison, Jimmy Martínez-Correa and J. Todd Swarthout July 2015 ABSTRACT. The reduction of compound lotteries

More information

Learning and Peer Effects Alternating or compensating? An experiment on the repeated sequential best shot game

Learning and Peer Effects Alternating or compensating? An experiment on the repeated sequential best shot game No. 86 Lisa Bruttel Werner Güth Learning and Peer Effects Alternating or compensating? An experiment on the repeated sequential best shot game Research Paper Series Thurgau Institute of Economics and Department

More information

THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS. A. Schepanski The University of Iowa

THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS. A. Schepanski The University of Iowa THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS A. Schepanski The University of Iowa May 2001 The author thanks Teri Shearer and the participants of The University of Iowa Judgment and Decision-Making

More information

Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences

Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24:2; 131 142, 2002 2002 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Manufactured in The Netherlands. Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences WILLIAM S. NEILSON

More information

Risk aversion, Under-diversification, and the Role of Recent Outcomes

Risk aversion, Under-diversification, and the Role of Recent Outcomes Risk aversion, Under-diversification, and the Role of Recent Outcomes Tal Shavit a, Uri Ben Zion a, Ido Erev b, Ernan Haruvy c a Department of Economics, Ben-Gurion University, Beer-Sheva 84105, Israel.

More information

WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05

WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05 October 2011 WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05 Even (mixed) risk lovers are prudent David Crainich CNRS-LEM and IESEG School of Management Louis Eeckhoudt IESEG School of Management (LEM-CNRS) and CORE

More information

Exchange Rate Exposure and Firm-Specific Factors: Evidence from Turkey

Exchange Rate Exposure and Firm-Specific Factors: Evidence from Turkey Journal of Economic and Social Research 7(2), 35-46 Exchange Rate Exposure and Firm-Specific Factors: Evidence from Turkey Mehmet Nihat Solakoglu * Abstract: This study examines the relationship between

More information

Catastrophic risk: social influences on insurance decisions

Catastrophic risk: social influences on insurance decisions Theory Dec. (2017) 82:309 326 DOI 10.1007/s18-016-9571-y Catastrophic risk: social influences on insurance decisions Michal W. Krawczyk 1 Stefan T. Trautmann 2,3 GijsvandeKuilen 3 Published online: 6 September

More information

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Answers to chapter 3 review questions Answers to chapter 3 review questions 3.1 Explain why the indifference curves in a probability triangle diagram are straight lines if preferences satisfy expected utility theory. The expected utility of

More information

Under-Insurance Against Low-Probability Losses: New Experimental Evidence. By Susan K. Laury, Melayne Morgan McInnes, and J.

Under-Insurance Against Low-Probability Losses: New Experimental Evidence. By Susan K. Laury, Melayne Morgan McInnes, and J. Under-Insurance Against Low-Probability Losses: New Experimental Evidence By Susan K. Laury, Melayne Morgan McInnes, and J. Todd Swarthout First Draft: Preliminary and Incomplete 1. Introduction There

More information

Protecting Against Low-Probability Disasters: The Role of Worry

Protecting Against Low-Probability Disasters: The Role of Worry University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Business Economics and Public Policy Papers Wharton Faculty Research 12-2012 Protecting Against Low-Probability Disasters: The Role of Worry Christian Schade

More information

Doing Good or Doing Harm Experimental Evidence on Giving and Taking in Public Good Games

Doing Good or Doing Harm Experimental Evidence on Giving and Taking in Public Good Games Doing Good or Doing Harm Experimental Evidence on Giving and Taking in Public Good Games Menusch Khadjavi and Andreas Lange* University of Hamburg August, 2011 Abstract. This paper explores motives and

More information

Inflation Expectations and Behavior: Do Survey Respondents Act on their Beliefs? October Wilbert van der Klaauw

Inflation Expectations and Behavior: Do Survey Respondents Act on their Beliefs? October Wilbert van der Klaauw Inflation Expectations and Behavior: Do Survey Respondents Act on their Beliefs? October 16 2014 Wilbert van der Klaauw The views presented here are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect those

More information

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion Uncertainty Outline Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion 2 Simple Lotteries 3 Simple Lotteries Advanced Microeconomic Theory

More information

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Pierre Chaigneau pierre.chaigneau@hec.ca June 14, 2011 Finance: the economics of risk and uncertainty In financial markets, claims associated with random future

More information

All-Hazards Homeowners Insurance: A Possibility for the United States?

All-Hazards Homeowners Insurance: A Possibility for the United States? All-Hazards Homeowners Insurance: A Possibility for the United States? Howard Kunreuther Key Points In the United States, standard homeowners insurance policies do not include coverage for earthquakes

More information

COMPARING THE PREDICTIVE POWER OF RISK ELICITATION INSTRUMENTS: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE FROM GERMAN FARMERS

COMPARING THE PREDICTIVE POWER OF RISK ELICITATION INSTRUMENTS: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE FROM GERMAN FARMERS COMPARING THE PREDICTIVE POWER OF RISK ELICITATION INSTRUMENTS: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE FROM GERMAN FARMERS Jens Rommel 1, Daniel Hermann 2, Malte Müller 3, Oliver Mußhoff 2 Contact: jens.rommel@zalf.de

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren October, 2013 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Which Measures Predict Risk Taking in a Multi-Stage Controlled Decision Process? *

Which Measures Predict Risk Taking in a Multi-Stage Controlled Decision Process? * Which Measures Predict Risk Taking in a Multi-Stage Controlled Decision Process? * Kremena Bachmann, Thorsten Hens and Remo Stössel January 2016 Abstract: In this paper we assess the ability of different

More information

An Experimental Test of Precautionary Bidding

An Experimental Test of Precautionary Bidding An Experimental Test of Precautionary Bidding Martin G. Kocher Department of Economics, University of Munich, Germany Department of Economics, University of Gothenburg, Sweden Julius Pahlke Department

More information

Risk attitude, investments, and the taste for luxuries versus. necessities. Introduction. Jonathan Baron

Risk attitude, investments, and the taste for luxuries versus. necessities. Introduction. Jonathan Baron Risk attitude, investments, and the taste for luxuries versus necessities Jonathan Baron Introduction Individuals should differ in their tolerance for risky financial investments. For one thing, people

More information

Summer 2003 (420 2)

Summer 2003 (420 2) Microeconomics 3 Andreas Ortmann, Ph.D. Summer 2003 (420 2) 240 05 117 andreas.ortmann@cerge-ei.cz http://home.cerge-ei.cz/ortmann Week of May 12, lecture 3: Expected utility theory, continued: Risk aversion

More information

Framing Lottery Choices

Framing Lottery Choices Framing Lottery Choices by Dale O. Stahl Department of Economics University of Texas at Austin stahl@eco.utexas.edu February 3, 2016 ABSTRACT There are many ways to present lotteries to human subjects:

More information

Ideal Bootstrapping and Exact Recombination: Applications to Auction Experiments

Ideal Bootstrapping and Exact Recombination: Applications to Auction Experiments Ideal Bootstrapping and Exact Recombination: Applications to Auction Experiments Carl T. Bergstrom University of Washington, Seattle, WA Theodore C. Bergstrom University of California, Santa Barbara Rodney

More information

International Review of Management and Marketing ISSN: available at http:

International Review of Management and Marketing ISSN: available at http: International Review of Management and Marketing ISSN: 2146-4405 available at http: www.econjournals.com International Review of Management and Marketing, 2017, 7(1), 85-89. Investigating the Effects of

More information

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli Decision Theory Refail N. Kasimbeyli Chapter 3 3 Utility Theory 3.1 Single-attribute utility 3.2 Interpreting utility functions 3.3 Utility functions for non-monetary attributes 3.4 The axioms of utility

More information

Measuring Attitude towards Risk Treatment Actions amongst Information Security Professionals: an Experimental Approach

Measuring Attitude towards Risk Treatment Actions amongst Information Security Professionals: an Experimental Approach Measuring Attitude towards Risk Treatment Actions amongst Information Security Professionals: an Experimental Approach Konstantinos Mersinas 1, Bjoern Hartig 2, Keith M. Martin 1 and Andrew Seltzer 2,3

More information

An Introduction to Experimental Economics and Insurance Experiments. J. Todd Swarthout

An Introduction to Experimental Economics and Insurance Experiments. J. Todd Swarthout An Introduction to Experimental Economics and Insurance Experiments J. Todd Swarthout One possible way of figuring out economic laws... is by controlled experiments.... Economists (unfortunately )... cannot

More information

Reference Dependence Lecture 1

Reference Dependence Lecture 1 Reference Dependence Lecture 1 Mark Dean Princeton University - Behavioral Economics Plan for this Part of Course Bounded Rationality (4 lectures) Reference dependence (3 lectures) Neuroeconomics (2 lectures)

More information

Volume 35, Issue 1. Effects of Aging on Gender Differences in Financial Markets

Volume 35, Issue 1. Effects of Aging on Gender Differences in Financial Markets Volume 35, Issue 1 Effects of Aging on Gender Differences in Financial Markets Ran Shao Yeshiva University Na Wang Hofstra University Abstract Gender differences in risk-taking and investment decisions

More information

Rational Choice and Moral Monotonicity. James C. Cox

Rational Choice and Moral Monotonicity. James C. Cox Rational Choice and Moral Monotonicity James C. Cox Acknowledgement of Coauthors Today s lecture uses content from: J.C. Cox and V. Sadiraj (2010). A Theory of Dictators Revealed Preferences J.C. Cox,

More information

ECON 312: MICROECONOMICS II Lecture 11: W/C 25 th April 2016 Uncertainty and Risk Dr Ebo Turkson

ECON 312: MICROECONOMICS II Lecture 11: W/C 25 th April 2016 Uncertainty and Risk Dr Ebo Turkson ECON 312: MICROECONOMICS II Lecture 11: W/C 25 th April 2016 Uncertainty and Risk Dr Ebo Turkson Chapter 17 Uncertainty Topics Degree of Risk. Decision Making Under Uncertainty. Avoiding Risk. Investing

More information

Frontiers in Social Neuroscience and Neuroeconomics: Decision Making under Uncertainty. September 18, 2008

Frontiers in Social Neuroscience and Neuroeconomics: Decision Making under Uncertainty. September 18, 2008 Frontiers in Social Neuroscience and Neuroeconomics: Decision Making under Uncertainty Kerstin Preuschoff Adrian Bruhin September 18, 2008 Risk Risk Taking in Economics Neural Correlates of Prospect Theory

More information

AN EMPIRICAL ANALYSIS ON PERCEPTION OF RETAIL INVESTORS TOWARDS DERIVATIVES MARKET WITH REFERENCE TO VISAKHAPATNAM DISTRICT

AN EMPIRICAL ANALYSIS ON PERCEPTION OF RETAIL INVESTORS TOWARDS DERIVATIVES MARKET WITH REFERENCE TO VISAKHAPATNAM DISTRICT INDIAN JOURNAL OF MANAGEMENT SCIENCE (IJMS) EISSN -79X ISSN 49-080 54 AN EMPIRICAL ANALYSIS ON PERCEPTION OF RETAIL INVESTORS TOWARDS DERIVATIVES MARKET WITH REFERENCE TO VISAKHAPATNAM DISTRICT Mrs. E.V.P.A.S

More information

Measuring Strategic Uncertainty in Coordination Games *

Measuring Strategic Uncertainty in Coordination Games * Measuring Strategic Uncertainty in Coordination Games * By Frank Heinemann, a Rosemarie Nagel, b and Peter Ockenfels c First version: August 2003 This version: Friday, 14 May 2004 Abstract This paper explores

More information

HANDBOOK OF EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS RESULTS

HANDBOOK OF EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS RESULTS HANDBOOK OF EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS RESULTS Edited by CHARLES R. PLOTT California Institute of Technology and VERNON L. SMITH Chapman University NORTH-HOLLAND AMSTERDAM NEW YORK OXFORD TOKYO North-Holland

More information