Information Inertia. June 6, Abstract

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Information Inertia. June 6, Abstract"

Transcription

1 Information Inertia Scott Condie Jayant Ganguli Philipp Karl Illeditsch June 6, 2012 Abstract We study how information about an asset affects optimal portfolios and equilibrium asset prices when investors are not sure about the model that predicts future asset values and thus treat the information as ambiguous. We show that this ambiguity may lead to asset demand that is insensitive to changes in news and investors use only their prior information when making portfolio decisions. This insensitivity to news is more severe when prices deviate a lot from its unconditional mean and in contrast to other ambiguity models it also occurs when demand is sensitive to changes in the price. In equilibrium, we show that stock prices may not react to public information that is worse than expected even though there are no information processing costs or other market frictions. The severity of this mispricing depends on the risk of the stock and the magnitude of the news surprise. Keywords: Ambiguity Aversion, Knightian Uncertainty, Informational Efficiency, Information Inertia, Inattention to News, Public Information. JEL Classification: D80, D81, G10, G11, G12. We would like to thank Kerry Back, James Dow, Christian Heyerdahl-Larsen, Sujoy Mukerji, Emre Ozdenoren, Han Ozsoylev, seminar participants at the Wharton Brown Bag Seminar, Oxford University, London Business School, and participants at the European workshop on general equilibrium theory at the University of Exeter for helpful comments and suggestions. Department of Economics, Brigham Young University, Provo, UT Telephone: , Fax: , ssc@byu.edu School of Economics, University of Nottingham, University Park, Nottingham NG7 2RD, UK. Telephone: +44 (0) , Fax: +44 (0) , jayant.ganguli@nottingham.ac.uk Finance Department, The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania, 3620 Locust Walk, 2426 SH-DH, Philadelphia, PA , Telephone: , Fax: , pille@wharton.upenn.edu 1

2 There is a vast amount of empirical research which documents that returns for many asset classes around the world are predictable. 1 The economic and statistical significance of the predictability results vary from study to study and the strength of these results as well as the theoretical underpinnings and interpretations are widely debated. In this paper, we study how information about an asset affects optimal portfolios and equilibrium asset prices when investors are not sure about the model that predicts future asset values and thus treat the information as ambiguous. We show that this ambiguity leads investors to ignore some information and hence asset prices in equilibrium do not always reflect all available public information about an asset. We refer to this phenomenon as information inertia. Suppose investors receive a public signal and its correlation with the future value of an asset is unknown. Investors are ambiguous (uncertain in the sense of Knight (1921)) about the predictability of future asset values and consider a range of correlations when processing this signal. Specifically, investors consider the correlation that leads to the lowest expected utility for each portfolio they evaluate. This max-min formulation of preferences is axiomatized in Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989) and is a commonly used representation of decisions-making under ambiguity in asset markets, as discussed in Epstein and Schneider (2010). 2 We show that ambiguity about the predictability of future asset values may cause inattention to news and lead investors to use only their prior information when making portfolio decisions. Specifically, there is a range of prices for which investors ignore bad news when they are long in the asset and they ignore good news when they are short in the asset. This insensitivity of demand to news occurs even for risky portfolios that are sensitive to changes in the price in contrast to previous work on ambiguous information where it only occurs with portfolio inertia (Condie and Ganguli (2011a) and Illeditsch (2011)). Moreover, we show that it is more severe when prices deviate 1 For a review of this literature see Cochrane (2005) or Koijen and Nieuwerburgh (2011) and the references therein. 2 These preferences imply behavior that is consistent with experimental evidence (Ellsberg (1961)) and more recent portfolio choice experiments (Ahn, Choi, Gale, and Kariv (2010) and Bossaerts, Ghirardato, Guarnaschelli, and Zame (2010)). 2

3 a lot from its unconditional mean. Investors inattention to some news implies that stock prices fail to incorporate all publicly available information in equilibrium. While good news is always reflected in the stock price some bad news is not. on information processing costs or other market frictions. 3 This mispricing of news does not rely We also show that the reaction of the stock price to news depends on its risk. Risky stocks are more likely to underreact to bad news whereas stocks that are not very risky tend to overreact to this news. However, the most striking result is that stocks with moderate risk show almost no reaction to bad signals even though there is no ambiguity about the fact that the signal is positively correlated with the asset. This paper complements recent work on optimal portfolios and equilibrium asset prices when investors process public signals. Caskey (2009) shows that prices do not reflect all available signals because ambiguity averse investors may prefer a less informative aggregate signal to its more ambiguous components. In contrast to his paper, we focus on one public signal about the future value of an asset and show that the apparent mispricing of this signal depends on the risk of the asset and the magnitude of the news surprise. 4 Epstein and Schneider (2008) show that investors react more to bad signals than to good signals when there is ambiguity about the precision of these signals. Illeditsch (2011) shows that this ambiguity leads to risky portfolios that are insensitive to changes in the stock price. However, these portfolios are sensitive to changes in the signal and thus in equilibrium prices always reflect all available information. This paper contributes to the literature on optimal portfolio choice with ambiguity. We know from Dow and Werlang (1994), Cao, Wang, and Zhang (2005), Epstein and Schneider (2007), Easley and O Hara (2009), and Campanale (2011) that am- 3 There is a growing literature in Finance and Economics that imposes an exogenous bound or cost on the ability of investors to process information (see Sims (2006), Sims (2010), or Veldkamp (2011) and the references therein). 4 Other papers who study the effects of private signals on the informational efficiency of prices in the presence of ambiguity are Condie and Ganguli (2011a), Condie and Ganguli (2011b), Mele and Sangiorgi (2011), Ozsoylev and Werner (2011), and Tallon (1998). 3

4 biguity leads to portfolio inertia at certainty and thus can help explain nonmarket participation. Epstein and Wang (1994), Epstein and Schneider (2010), and Illeditsch (2011) show that portfolio inertia can also arise for risky portfolios which can help explain why many investors who own stock do not show much trading activity. Garlappi, Uppal, and Wang (2007) characterize optimal portfolios with multiple ambiguous assets. Uppal and Wang (2003), Benigno and Nistico (2012), and Boyle, Garlappi, Uppal, and Wang (2012) show that ambiguity leads to under-diversified portfolios and thus can help explain the international home bias puzzle. We show that if there is ambiguity about the predictability of future asset values, then investors use their prior information when contemplating a long (short) position with moderate risk instead of relying on an ambiguous signal that conveys bad (good) news. Our paper is also related to recent literature on portfolio choice and asset pricing when there is ambiguity about the predictability of future asset returns/cash flows. Hansen and Sargent (2010a) study the price of risk when investors who seek robust decision rules find it difficult to differentiate between i.i.d. consumption growth and one with a persistent component (long run risk of Bansal and Yaron (2004)). 5 Chen, Ju, and Miao (2011) solve a dynamic consumption and portfolio choice problem when there is ambiguity about whether stock returns are IID or predictable. Ju and Miao (2012) and Collard, Mukerji, Sheppard, and Tallon (2011) explain many asset pricing puzzles by introducing ambiguity into a dynamic representative agent model in which consumption and dividends follow a hidden state regime-switching process and a hidden state model with a persistent latent state variable, respectively. The first paper considers the robust control approach and the other three papers consider the recursive smooth ambiguity model to describe preferences. 6 Our focus in this paper is on non-smooth preferences which are a good description for ambiguity averse behavior as shown by Ahn, Choi, Gale, and Kariv (2010) and Bossaerts, Ghirardato, 5 For a survey of learning models when investors seek robust decision rules see Hansen and Sargent (2007). 6 Strzalecki (2011) and Maccheroni, Marinacci, and Rustichini (2006) provide axiomatic foundations for the robust control model and Klibanoff, Marinacci, and Mukerji (2005), Nau (2006), Klibanoff, Marinacci, and Mukerji (2009), and Hayashi and Miao (2011) provide axiomatic foundations for the smooth ambiguity model and its dynamic extension. 4

5 Guarnaschelli, and Zame (2010). 7 The rest of the paper is organized as follows. In Section I, we introduce the model. In Section II, we solve for optimal demand and discuss the information inertia results. In Section, III we solve for the equilibrium stock price and discuss the mispricing results, and in Section IV we show that our results are robust to aggregation. I Model Suppose there are two dates 0 and 1. Investors can invest in a risk-free asset and a risky asset. Let p denote the price of the risky asset, d the future value or dividend of the risky asset, and θ the number of shares invested in the risky asset. There is no consumption at date zero. The risk-free asset is used as numeraire, so the risk-free rate is zero. Hence, future wealth w is given by w = w 0 + ( d p ) θ, (1) in which w 0 denotes initial wealth. Suppose investors receive a signal s about the future value of the asset d. Wefocus in this paper on ambiguity averse investors in the sense of Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989). Let u( ) denote the Bernoulli utility function of the investor and define a model m as a joint distribution of d and s. An ambiguity averse investor in the sense of Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989) chooses a portfolio θ to maximize inf E m [u ( w) s = s], (2) m M where M denotes the set of all models considered by the investor and E m [ ] denotes the expectation with respect to the belief generated by the model m. 7 For a discussion of different preferences specifications that describe aversion to ambiguity see Backus, Routledge, and Zin (2004), Epstein and Schneider (2010), and Hansen and Sargent (2010b). 5

6 Suppose that the joint distribution of d and s is normal: d N d, σ2 d ρσ d σ s. (3) s s ρσ d σ s σs 2 Investors are ambiguous about the correlation between the signal and the dividend and thus ρ [ρ a,ρ b ] with ρ a > 0andρ b < 1. 8 We follow Gilboa and Schmeidler (1993) and assume that investors update their beliefs model by model using Bayes rule. 9 Hence, standard normal-normal updating for each ρ [ρ a,ρ b ]leadsto ( d s = s N ρ d + σ ) d ρ (s s),σd 2 σ (1 ρ2 ). (4) s The utility of an investor who holds θ shares of the risky asset is ( ( ) ) ] min E ρ [u w 0 + d p θ s = s. (5) ρ [ρ a,ρ b ] Investors are more averse to ambiguity if the interval [ρ a,ρ b ] is large and therefore the degree of aversion to ambiguous information can be measured by ρ b ρ a. II Optimal Demand In this section, we determine the optimal portfolio of investors who are ambiguous about the predictability of the future value of an asset. We show that investors with long positions do not always react to news that is worse than expected and investors with short positions do not always react to news that is better than expected. We refer to this insensitivity to news as information inertia. γ w Suppose investors have CARA utility over future wealth w (i.e. u( w) = e with γ>0) and let CE(θ) denote the certainty equivalent of an ambiguity averse 8 If ρ b < 0, then replace the signal s with s and the interval [ρ a,ρ b ]with[ ρ b, ρ a ]. The results for the case when 0 [ρ a,ρ b ] are not reported but are available from the authors upon request. 9 See Epstein and Schneider (2003) and Epstein and Schneider (2007) for learning under ambiguity. 6

7 investor. Then the investor s utility given in equation (5) is equal to u (CE(θ)) with CE(θ) = ( min E ρ [ w s = s] 1 ) ρ [ρ a,ρ b ] 2 γvar ρ [ w s = s]. (6) The assumption of CARA utility and normal beliefs lead to mean-variance preferences over future wealth in which the posterior mean is a linear function and the residual variance is a quadratic function of the correlation ρ. Ambiguity averse investors are worried about the effects of ρ on the mean and variance of future wealth and thus consider for each portfolio θ and signal realization s the minimum expected value of future utility (certainty equivalent). Hence, their worst case scenario belief will depend on the portfolio θ and signal s as the next proposition shows. Proposition 1 (Preferences). Let ˆθ a ( s s)/(γσ d σ s ρ a ) and ˆθ b ( s s)/(γσ d σ s ρ b ). The certainty equivalent of an investor with risk aversion γ and aversion to ambiguity described by [ρ a,ρ b ] is ) E ρa [ w s = s] 1γVar 2 ρ a [ w s = s] if θ min (ˆθa, 0 ( ) 2 ) ) E[ w] 1 1 s s γvar [ w] 2 2γ σ s if min (ˆθa, 0 <θ min (ˆθb, 0 ) ) CE(θ) = E ρb [ w s = s] 1γVar 2 ρ b [ w s = s] if min (ˆθb, 0 <θ max (ˆθb, 0 ( ) 2 ) ) E[ w] 1 1 s s γvar [ w] 2 2γ σ s if max (ˆθb, 0 <θ max (ˆθa, 0 ) E ρa [ w s = s] 1γVar 2 ρ a [ w s = s] if θ>max (ˆθa, 0. (7) The certainty equivalent CE(θ) is a continuous and concave function of the stock demand θ. Moreover, it is continuously differentiable except for the portfolio θ =0if s s. Investors who are contemplating a long position in the asset are worried about bad signals with a high ρ and good signals with a low ρ because informative bad signals significantly lower the posterior asset mean whereas good signals that are not very informative only moderately increase the posterior asset mean. Similarly, investors who are contemplating a short position in the asset fear high posterior asset means and thus are worried about good signals that have a high ρ and bad signals that have a low ρ. On the other hand, investors who are contemplating either a long or short position in the asset always fear risk and thus are worried about signals with a low ρ. 7

8 Investors are more worried about the posterior mean for small risks and are more worried about the residual variance for big risks. Hence, investors treat bad signals as informative for moderate long positions in the asset (0 <θ ˆθ b ) and as not very informative for very large long positions (θ >ˆθ a ). 10 There is a range of portfolio positions (ˆθ b <θ ˆθ a ) for which investors beliefs balance the counteracting mean and variance effects. Specifically, ρ (θ) argmin CE S (θ, ρ) = s s 1 ρ [ρ a,ρ b ] γσ d σ s θ, (8) where CE S (θ, ρ) denotes the certainty equivalent of a standard expected utility maximizer in the sense of Savage (1954) with belief ρ. Investors hedge against ambiguity by immunizing utility against changes in the belief ρ and thus CE S (θ, ρ (θ))/ ρ = 0. This leads to marginal utility that is not affected by changes in the signal. It follows from the Envelope Theorem that CE(θ) θ = CES (θ, ρ (θ)) + CES (θ, ρ (θ)) ρ (θ) θ ρ θ = CES (θ, ρ (θ)) ] [ ] =E[ d p θγvar d. θ (9) We will show below that this desire to hedge against ambiguity leads to demand that is insensitive to changes in news. A Savage Benchmark The demand of a standard expected utility maximizer in the sense of Savage (1954) with belief ρ is given in the next proposition. 11 Proposition 2 (Optimal Demand Savage Benchmark). Let ρ a = ρ b = ρ. Then the 10 If investors contemplate a short position in the asset, then they treat bad signals as not very informativebecausetheworstcasescenariofor the posterior mean and variance is a low ρ. 11 The proof is straightforward and thus omitted. 8

9 demand function for the risky asset is θ ρ (p) = E ρ [ d s = s ] p γvar ρ [ d s = s ]. (10) An increase in the signal will always lead to an increase in the stock position. This is no longer true when investors are ambiguous about the correlation between the signal and the dividend as the next theorem shows. B Ambiguity-Averse Investors Let θ a (p) denote the demand of a Savage investor with belief ρ a, θ 0 (p) denotethe demand of a Savage investor with belief ρ =0,andθ b (p) the demand of a Savage investor with belief ρ b,andθ(p) the demand of an ambiguity averse investor. The optimal demand for an ambiguity averse investor is given in the next proposition. Theorem 1 (Optimal Demand). Let ˆθ a ( s s)/(γσ d σ s ρ a ) and ˆθ b ( s s)/(γσ d σ s ρ b ). Optimal demand for an investor with risk aversion γ and aversion to ambiguity described by [ρ a,ρ b ] is θ(p) = ) θ a (p) p p 1 μ ρa γv ρa max (ˆθa, 0 ) max (θ 0 (p), 0) p 1 < p p 2 μ ρb γv ρb max (ˆθb, 0 ) θ b (p) p 2 < p p 3 μ ρb γv ρb min (ˆθb, 0 ) min (θ 0 (p), 0) p 3 < p p 4 μ ρa γv ρa min (ˆθa, 0 θ a (p) p > p 4, where μ ρ (s) = d + σ d σ s ρ (s s) and v ρ σ 2 d (1 ρ2 ). (11) Suppose the signal conveys bad news (see left graph of Figure 1). 12 Ambiguity averse investors (solid line) are more worried about risk than a low posterior mean when they take on large long positions in the asset and hence their demand coincides with the demand of a Savage investor with belief ρ a (blue dashed line). However, they are more worried about a low posterior mean than risk if they take on a moderate 12 Optimal demand when the signal conveys good news is shown in the right graph of Figure 1. 9

10 long position and hence their demand coincides with the demand of a Savage investor with belief ρ b (chain-dotted line) Bad News ρ a = Good News ρ a = 0.5 ρ b = 0.9 ρ b = ρ = 0 [ ρ a, ρ b ] = [ 0.5, 0.9 ] ρ = 0 [ ρ a, ρ b ] = [ 0.5, 0.9 ] 0 Demand 0.5 Demand Price Price Figure 1: Optimal Demand The left graph shows optimal demand when the signal conveys bad news (s =90< s = 100) and the right graph shows optimal demand when the signal conveys good news (s = 110 > s = 100). Demand is plotted as a function of the stock price for a Savage investor with belief ρ b (red chain dotted line), for a Savage investor with belief ρ a (blue dashed line), for a Savage investor with belief ρ = 0 (green dotted line), and for an ambiguity averse investor with range of beliefs [ρ a,ρ b ] (black solid line). There is a range of prices over which ambiguity averse investors are neither long nor short the stock. Moreover, there is a range of prices for which ambiguity averse investors adjust their stock position but do not react to news. The parameters are d = s = 100, σ d = σ s =5,ρ a =5/10, ρ b =9/10, and γ =1. It is well known that hedging against ambiguity leads to portfolio inertia at the risk-free portfolio because investors who are contemplating a long (short) position in the asset are worried about a low (high) posterior asset mean and thus fear bad (good) signals with a high ρ and good (bad) signals with a low ρ. Hence, there is a range of prices for which they would rather not be invested in the stock (see Dow and Werlang (1992)). What is new in this paper is that there is a range of prices for which investors hedge against ambiguity by choosing a risky portfolio that does not depend on the 13 If ambiguity averse investors take on a short position in the asset, then they behave like a Savage investor with belief ρ a because in this case the worst case scenario for the posterior asset mean and residual asset variances is a low ρ. 10

11 signal. In this case their demand coincides with the demand of a Savage investor who thinks the correlation between the asset and the signal is zero. This is the case even though there is no ambiguity about the fact that the signal is positively correlated with the asset. However, the utility of the ambiguity averse investor is not the same as the utility of a Savage investor with belief ρ = 0 because hedging against ambiguity comes at an utility cost (see Proposition 1). There is a range of long positions that do not depend on signals that convey bad news because investors want to avoid ambiguity. Similarly, there is a range of short position that do not depend on signals that convey good news. Hence, hedging against ambiguity leads to risky portfolios that are insensitive to changes in the signal. 14 These portfolios are more risky for large news surprises. Moreover, the range of prices for which investors hedge against ambiguity by choosing a risky portfolio that does not depend on the signal is increasing in the news surprise as the next proposition shows. 15 Proposition 3. The size of the price region for which investors have downward sloping demand which does not depend on the signal is σ d ( 1 ρ a 1 ρ b ) s s σ s. (12) We now summarize the predictions for optimal portfolios. Model Predictions 1 (Portfolio Choice). If investors are ambiguous about the predictability of future asset values, then (i) there is a range of prices over which investors adjust their long stock position but do not react to news that is worse than expected, (ii) there is a range of prices over which investors adjust their short stock position but do not react to news that are better than expected, 14 There is no portfolio inertia away from certainty because there is no risky portfolio that is independent of the correlation ρ and perfectly hedges against ambiguity by making utility independent of the correlation ρ. Illeditsch (2011) assumes ambiguity about the precision of the signal and shows that there is a risky portfolio that perfectly hedges against ambiguity and thus causes portfolio inertia away from certainty. However, this portfolio is sensitive to changes in the signal and thus there is no information inertia. 15 The size of the price region for which investors are neither long nor short the asset is reported in Proposition 8 of the appendix. 11

12 (iii) there is a range of prices over which investors are neither long nor short the stock when news is surprising, and (iv) the inaction regions are larger for extreme news surprises. C Information Inertia So far we have only looked at how price changes affect the optimal demand for the risky asset. We now take prices as given and ask how changes in the signal affect asset demand. We know that for a Savage investor with belief ρ demand is strictly increasing in the signal. Moreover, there is a strong price reaction to news if ρ is high and/or risk aversion is low. Specifically, for every price p and correlation 0 < ρ < 1 we have that θ(s) s = 1 ρ γσ d σ s 1 ρ. 2 If investors are ambiguous about the correlation ρ and the unconditional risk premium of the stock is non-zero (p d), then there are two ranges of signals for which demand is insensitive to changes in the signal. The left graph of Figure 2 shows optimal demand as a function of the signal when the unconditional risk premium is positive (p < d) and the right graph of Figure 2 shows it when the unconditional risk premium is negative (p > d). 12

13 Positive Unconditional Risk Premium Negative Unconditional Risk Premium 0.6 Dbar p = 10 Dbar p = 5 Dbar p = Dbar p = 10 Dbar p = 5 Dbar p = Demand 0 Demand Signal Signal Figure 2: Information Inertia in Demand The left graph shows optimal demand as a function of the signal when the unconditional risk premium is positive and the right graph shows it when the unconditional risk premium is negative. Both graphs show that when the price deviates a lot from its unconditional mean, then information inertia is more severe and the nonzero portfolios at which investors exhibit information inertia are more risky. The parameters are d = s = 100, σ d = σ s =5,ρ a =5/10, ρ b =9/10, and γ =1. There is no information inertia when the unconditional risk premium is zero (black solid line) because in this case the ambiguity averse investor behaves like a Savage investor with belief ρ a. Intuitively, investors will long the asset when news are good and they will short the asset when news are bad. But there is no confusion about the interpretation of the signal when news are good (bad) and investors are long (short) the asset because the worst case scenario for the posterior mean and the posterior variance is a low ρ. Suppose the unconditional risk premium is positive (blue dashed line and red chain-dotted line in the left graph of Figure 2). If the signal conveys good news, then investors buy the asset and the worst case scenario for both the mean and the variance is always a low ρ. This is no longer true when the signal conveys bad news. Specifically, for a moderate bad news surprise, investors are still long in the asset and thus behave like a Savage investor with belief ρ b if they are more worried about a low posterior mean and they behave like a Savage investor with belief ρ a if they are more worried about risk. On the other hand, if news is very bad then investors take on a 13

14 short position in the asset and thus always behave like a Savage investor with belief ρ a because the worst case scenario for the posterior mean and variance is a low ρ. There are two ranges of signal values for which demand is insensitive to changes in the news. The first range corresponds to the well known case of portfolio inertia at certainty (θ = 0) whereas the second range corresponds to risky portfolios (θ 0) for which investors do not exhibit portfolio inertia. Intuitively, investors exhibit information inertia when they exhibit portfolio inertia at certainty because a small increase (decrease) in the signal does not sufficiently raise (lower) the posterior asset mean to convince an investor to give up a portfolio that perfectly hedges against risk and ambiguity. 16 What is new in this paper is the second range of signal values for which investors change their risky portfolio in response to changes in the stock price but not in response to changes in the signal. This information inertia is more severe when price deviates a lot from its unconditional mean. However, the probability of having information inertia is not monotone in the unconditional risk premium. We determine in the next proposition the size of the signal inaction region and the probability of having information inertia. 17 Proposition 4 (Information Inertia for Risky Portfolios). Thesizeofthesignal region for which investors are either long ( d >p) or short ( d <p) the asset and demand does not react to changes in the signal is σ s σ d (ρ b ρ a ) d p. (13) The probability of investors exhibiting information inertia for either a long ( d >p) or a short ( d <p) position in the asset is ( N p 0,1 ρ d ) ( p a N 0,1 ρ d ) b, (14) σ d σ d where N 0,1 ( ) denotes the cumulative distribution function of a standard normal distributed variable. 16 This form of inertia appears in Condie and Ganguli (2011a) and Illeditsch (2011). 17 The size of the signal region for which investors are neither long nor short the asset and the probability of having information inertia in this case is reported in Proposition 9 of the appendix. 14

15 The probability of having information inertia depends on the unconditional risk premium and is plotted in Figure 3. If the unconditional risk premium is zero, then there is no information inertia because investors behave like Savage investors with belief ρ a. The probability of investors taking on a large long position in the asset increases with the unconditional risk premium and thus the probability of having information inertia decreases because investors with very risky positions are more worried about risk than a low posterior asset mean and thus behave like Savage investors with belief ρ a. The intuition is similar for investors with large short positions. Hence, the probability of short sellers, asset buyers, and investors who do not participate in the stock market to exhibit information inertia is non monotonic in the unconditional risk premium of the asset Positive Unconditional Risk Premium θ < 0 θ = 0 θ > 0 total Negative Unconditional Risk Premium θ < 0 θ = 0 θ > 0 total Probability Probability Unconditional Risk Premium Unconditional Risk Premium Figure 3: Probability of Information Inertia in Demand Both graphs show the probability of having information inertia in demand as a function of the unconditional risk premium. The blue dashed line shows the probability of having inertia for a short position in the stock, the red chain-dotted line shows it for a long position in the stock, the green dotted line shows it for the risk-free portfolio, and the black solid line shows the total probability of having information inertia in demand. The parameters are d = s = 100, σ d = σ s =5,ρ a =5/10, ρ b =9/10, and γ =1. We conclude this section with a summary of the information inertia results. Model Predictions 2 (Information Inertia in Demand). If investors are ambiguous about the predictability of future asset values, then 15

16 (i) there is a range of bad signals over which investors do not adjust their long stock position when the unconditional risk premium is positive, (ii) there is a range of good signals over which investors do not adjust their short stock position when the unconditional risk premium is negative, (iii) information inertia is more severe when price deviates a lot from its unconditional mean, and (iv) the probability of having information inertia in demand is non monotonic in the unconditional risk premium of the asset. III Equilibrium In this section, we solve for the equilibrium stock price when a representative investors is ambiguous about the predictability of future cash flows. 18 We show that prices do not always incorporate public information that is worse than expected. Moreover, the probability of this mispricing depends on the riskiness of the stock. Suppose there is a representative investor with CARA utility who is averse to ambiguity. In equilibrium, the representative investor holds the stock and consumes the liquidating dividend d. Hence, the stock price at date 1 equals the liquidating dividend and θ = 1. The price at date 0 depends on the signal and is determined below. A Savage Benchmark The equilibrium price when the representative investor is a standard expected utility maximizer with belief ρ (in the sense of Savage (1954)) is provided in the next proposition There exists a representative investor if all investors in the economy have the same aversion to ambiguity (for a proof see Wakai (2007) or Illeditsch (2011)). Properties of the equilibrium stock price when there does not exist a representative investor are discussed in the next section. 19 The proof is straightforward and thus omitted. 16

17 Proposition 5 (Savage Benchmark). If the representative investor is a standard expected utility maximizer with belief ρ, then [ ] [ ] p(s) =E ρ d s = s γvar ρ d s = s. (15) The stock price is strictly increasing in the signal when the signal is positively correlated with the asset. This is no longer true when the representative investor is averse to ambiguity as the next theorem shows. B Ambiguity-Averse Investors Theorem 2. Let ŝ a = s γσ d σ s ρ a and ŝ b = s γσ d σ s ρ b. Then for each s there is a unique equilibrium stock price p(s). Specifically, [ ] [ ] E ρa d s = s γvar ρa d s = s if s>ŝ a [ ] [ ] p(s) = E d γvar d if ŝ b <s ŝ a (16) [ ] [ ] E ρb d s = s γvar ρb d s = s if s ŝ b. Figure 4 shows the equilibrium stock price as a function of the signal. The stock price reacts moderately to good news because in this case the worst case scenario for both the mean and the variance is a signal with a low ρ. However, if news is very bad, then investors are more worried about a low posterior mean than a high residual variance and thus the price strongly reacts to changes in the signal. There is a range of bad signal values for which the representative investor hedges against ambiguity by avoiding the signal and hence the stock price does not react to these signals. Specifically, the equilibrium stock price is constant for all signals s [ŝ b, ŝ a ]. 17

18 90 Equilibrium Price ρ a ρ b ρ = 0 [ρ a, ρ b ] Price ShatB = 77.5 ShatA = Sbar = 100 Signal Figure 4: Equilibrium Price This graph shows the equilibrium stock price as a function of the signal. The red dashed line represents an economy in which the representative investor (RI) is a Savage with belief ρ b, the blue chain-dotted line represents an economy in which the RI is a Savage with belief ρ a, and the black solid line represents an economy in which the RI is ambiguity averse ([ρ a,ρ b ]). There is a range of signals that are not priced and thus prices fail to incorporate all available public information. The parameters are d = s = 100, σ d = σ s =5,andγ =1. The left graph of Figure 5 shows the equilibrium stock price a function of the signal. The blue chain-dotted line represents an economy in which the unconditional risk premium is 0, the red dashed line represents an economy in which the unconditional risk premium is 25, and the black solid line represents an economy in which the unconditional risk premium is 50. The figure shows that the inaction region increases with the riskiness of the stock. It also shows that increasingly worse signals will not be reflected in the price if there is more risk in the economy. The right graph of Figure 5 shows that the probability of the mispricing of public information is not monotonic in the riskiness of the stock. Moreover, it also shows that conditional on increasingly bad news surprises this probability is very large for some stocks. 18

19 γ σ d 2 = 0 γ σ d 2 = 25 γ σ d 2 = 50 Price Inertia Price Inertia Two St. Dev. Bad News Suprise One St. Dev. Bad News Suprise Bad News Surprise News Surprise Price Probability Signal Risk ( γ σ 2 d ) Figure 5: Mispricing of Public Information The left graph shows the equilibrium stock price as a function of the signal for different unconditional risk premia. It shows that the information inertia in prices is more severe for risky stocks. The right graph shows the probability of having a failure of prices to incorporate public information. The black solid line shows the unconditional probability, the red chain-dotted line shows the probability conditional on bad news, the blue dashed line shows the probability conditional on having an at least one standard deviation bad news surprise, and the green dotted line shows the probability conditional on having an at least two standard deviation bad news surprise. The parameters are d = s = 100, and σ d = σ s =5. We determine the size of the inaction region and the probability of being in that region in the next proposition. 20 Proposition 6 (Failure of prices to incorporate public information). Let ŝ a = s γσ d σ s ρ a and ŝ b = s γσ d σ s ρ b. The stock price does not react to the signal for the range of signal values: ŝ a ŝ b = γσ d σ s (ρ b ρ a ). (17) The unconditional probability of the mispricing of public information is N 0,1 ( γσ d ρ a ) N 0,1 ( γσ d ρ b ). (18) The graphs in Figure 6 show the probability of having a moderate price reaction (red area), a strong price reaction (blue area), and no price reaction (black area) as a function of the riskiness of the stock. The graphs in the last row show that stocks 20 The proof follows directly from Theorem 2 and is thus omitted. 19

20 which are not very risky are more likely to react very strongly to news that are much worse than expected than stocks which are very risky. However, it is striking that stocks with moderate risk show almost no reaction to very bad ambiguous news. 100% Price Reaction 100% Price Reaction 90% 90% Unconditional Probability 80% 70% 60% 50% 40% 30% 20% 10% 0% moderate inertia strong Prob. Cond. on Bad News Surprise 80% 70% 60% 50% 40% 30% 20% 10% 0% moderate inertia strong Risk ( γ σ d 2 ) Risk ( γ σ d 2 ) Prob. Cond. on 1 St. Dev. Bad News Surprise 100% 90% 80% 70% 60% 50% 40% 30% 20% 10% 0% Price Reaction moderate inertia strong Prob. Cond. on 2 St. Dev. Bad News Surprise 100% 90% 80% 70% 60% 50% 40% 30% 20% 10% 0% moderate inertia strong Price Reaction Risk ( γ σ d 2 ) Risk ( γ σ d 2 ) Figure 6: Price Reaction to News All four graphs show the probability of having a moderate price reaction (red area), a strong price reaction (blue area), and no price reaction (black area) as a function of the riskiness of the stock. The first graphs shows the unconditional probability, the second graphs shows the probability conditional on bad news, the third graphs shows the probability conditional on having an at least one standard deviation bad news surprise, and the last graph shows the probability conditional on having an at least two standard deviation bad news surprise. The parameters are d = s = 100, and σ d = σ s =5. We now summarize the predictions for the equilibrium stock price. Model Predictions 3 (Failure of prices to incorporate public information). If investors are ambiguous about the predictability of future asset values, then 20

21 (i) prices do not always react to public signals that convey bad news and (ii) the probability of this mispricing depends on the riskiness of the stock. IV Heterogeneous Investors In this section, we study equilibrium prices and demands when the economy is populated by investors who may differ with respect to aversion to risk and ambiguity. We show that in equilibrium there are some investors who are inattentive to news and use their prior information when computing optimal demand. Moreover, the result that prices may not reflect all available public information in equilibrium is robust to this heterogeneity. Suppose there are H investors who all receive the same signal but may differ with respect to their initial wealth, and their aversion to risk and ambiguity. Let w 0h denote investor h s initial wealth, γ h > 0 her risk aversion coefficient, and [ρ ah,ρ bh ] her set of beliefs with ρ ah > 0 h {1,...,H}. An equilibrium in this economy is defined as follows: Definition 1 (Equilibrium). The signal-to-price map p(s) is an equilibrium s R if and only if (i) each investor chooses a portfolio θ h to maximize [ ( ) ) ] min E ρ h u h (w 0h + d p(s) θ h s = s, s R (19) ρ h [ρ ah,ρ bh ] and (ii) markets clear; i.e. H h=1 θ h =1and investors consume the liquidating d at date 1. If all investors have the same ambiguity, then we know from Wakai (2007) and Illeditsch (2011) that there exists a representative investor with risk tolerance equal to the sum of the risk tolerances of all H investors. We show in the next proposition that equilibrium prices still fail to incorporate all available public information when investors are heterogeneous in their aversion to ambiguity and their range of beliefs overlap. 21

22 Proposition 7 (Aggregation). Let 1/γ H h=1 1/γ h denote aggregate risk tolerance and let [ρ a,ρ b ] H h=1 [ρ ah,ρ bh ]. Then the equilibrium stock price is where ŝ a = s γσ d σ s ρ a and ŝ b = s γσ d σ s ρ b. p(s) = d γσ 2 d s [ŝ b, ŝ a ], (20) The size of the price inaction region is determined by the investors with the smallest ambiguity and it is increasing with aggregate risk aversion γ. Hence, the size of the inaction region and the probability of the mispricing of public information are given in equation (17) and (18) of the previous section. To gain some more intuition consider an economy in which both investors (Knights) are averse to ambiguity. The first Knight has the range of beliefs [ρ a1,ρ b1 ]=[0.2, 0.6] and the second Knight has the range of beliefs [ρ a2,ρ b2 ]=[0.4, 0.8]. The black solid line in the left graph of Figure 7 shows the equilibrium stock price as a function of the signal. For comparison, we also show the equilibrium stock price for five economies that are populated by two Savages with different beliefs. For instance, the red dotted line shows the price in an economy where the first Savage has the belief ρ 1 =0.6 and the second Savage has the belief ρ 2 =0.8. The right graph of Figure 7 shows the equilibrium demand as a function of the signal when the economy is populated by the two Knights described above. There is a range of signals that are worse than expected for which both investors use their priors when computing demands and thus the equilibrium stock price does not react to changes in these signals. 22

23 Equilibrium with Two Knights 2 Knights ([ 0.2, 0.6 ], [ 0.4, 0.8 ]) 2 Savages (0.6, 0.8) 2 Savages (0, 0.6) 2 Savages (0, 0.4) 2 Savages (0.2, 0.4) Savages with ρ = Equilibrium with Two Knights [ ρ a, ρ b ] = [ 0.2, 0.6 ] [ ρ a, ρ b ] = [ 0.4, 0.8 ] Stock Price Demand Signal Signal Figure 7: Investors with different ambiguity The left graph shows the equilibrium stock price as a function of the signal for six different economies. The black solid line represents an economy that consists of two Knights with range of beliefs ([ρ a1,ρ b1 ]=[0.2, 0.6], [ρ a2,ρ b2 ]=[0.4, 0.8]). The colored dotted lines represent economies that consist of two Savages with different beliefs. The left graph shows that if there is ambiguity, then there is a range of bad signals for which the price does not react much. The right graph shows equilibrium demand in an economy that consists of two Knights. The red dashed line shows demand of a Knight with range of beliefs [ρ a1,ρ b1 ]=[0.2, 0.6] and the black solid line shows demand of a Knight with range of beliefs [ρ a2,ρ b2 ]=[0.4, 0.8]. If the signal lies in the interval [77.92, 95.17], then at least one of the investors ignores the signal and uses her prior information when determining demand. When both investors hedge against ambiguity ([ŝ b, ŝ a ] = [85, 90]), then demand is insensitive to changes in these signals and thus equilibrium prices fail to incorporate these signals. All investors have the same risk aversion γ = 1 and the remaining parameters are d = s = 100, and σ d = σ s =5. To discuss the properties of equilibrium demand and price given in Figure 7 we consider the five different signal regions (i) (, 77.92], (ii) [77.92, 85], (iii) [85, 90], (iv) [90, 95.17], and (v) [95.17, ). Both Knights behave like Savages with beliefs ρ 1 = 0.6 andρ 2 = 0.8 for the first range of signals because if news is very bad ambiguity averse investors are more worried about a low posterior mean than a high residual variance and thus consider a high ρ. Hence, the equilibrium stock price reacts a lot to these signals. Equilibrium demand of the second Knight (red dashed line) is increasing in the signal because her worst case scenario belief (ρ =0.8) is larger than the worst case scenario belief of the second Knight (black solid line) and thus 23

24 she puts more weight on the signal. The analysis is similar for the fifth range because with good news the worst case scenario for both investors is a low ρ. For the other three ranges of signals there is at least one investor who avoids the signal and uses her prior when forming optimal demand. In other words, there is at least one investor who behaves as if there is no correlation between the signal and the dividend even though there is no ambiguity about the fact that this correlation is positive. Consider the second signal range. The first Knight sill behaves like a Savage investor with belief ρ =0.6 but the second Knight hedges against ambiguity by ignoring the signal. Hence her demand which is increasing for the first range of signals is now decreasing because neither mean nor variance depends on the signal and the equilibrium price increases with it. The equilibrium price still reacts to signals in the second region because of the first investor but not as much as for the first range of signals. Both investors ignore all signals in the third region and hence the equilibrium does not reflect these signals. The intuition for the fourth signal range is similar to the second. In this case the first investor ignores the signal when forming demand and hence in equilibrium her demand decreases with the signal. We conclude this section with a comparison of equilibrium demand for different economies. Specifically, the left graph of Figure 8 shows equilibrium demand as a function of the signal and the right graph shows it as a function of the equilibrium stock price. In both graphs the black solid line represents an economy consisting of two Knights, the red dashed line represents an economy consisting of two Savages with different beliefs, and the blue chain-dotted line represents an economy with one Knight and one Savage. The graphs show that if there is ambiguity, then equilibrium demand is neither monotone in the signal nor in the equilibrium stock price. Moreover, the left graph shows that this non monotone and erratic demand behavior only occurs for signals that are worse than expected. This is in stark contrast to an economy without ambiguity for which equilibrium demand is a smooth and monotone function of the signal If everybody has the same belief (or ambiguity) then equilibrium demand is constant. 24

25 Heterogenous Investors Heterogenous Investors Equilibrium Demand Equilibrium Demand Two Savages 0.42 One Savage and One Knight Two Knights Signal 0.4 Two Savages One Savage and One Knight Two Knights Equilibrium Stock Price Figure 8: Equilibrium Demand The left graph shows equilibrium demand as a function of the signal and the right graph shows it as a function of the equilibrium stock price. In both graphs the black solid line represents an economy consisting of two Knights with range of beliefs [ρ a1,ρ b1 ]=[0.2, 0.6] and [ρ a2,ρ b2 ]=[0.4, 0.8]). The red dashed line represents an economy consisting of two Savages with beliefs ρ 1 =0.4 andρ 2 =0.6 andthe blue chain-dotted line represents an economy with one Knight with range of beliefs [ρ a1,ρ b1 ]=[0.2, 0.8] and one Savage with belief ρ 2 =0.5. Both graphs show that equilibrium demand is non-monotone if there is ambiguity. All investors have the same risk aversion γ = 1 and the remaining parameters are d = s = 100, and σ d = σ s =5. V Conclusion We study optimal portfolios and equilibrium asset prices when there is ambiguity (uncertainty in the sense of Knight) about the predictability of future asset values. We show that this ambiguity may lead to asset demand that is insensitive to changes in news and investors use only their prior information when making portfolio decisions. In equilibrium, we show that stock prices may not react to public information that is worse than expected even though there are no information processing costs or other market frictions. 25

26 References Ahn, David, Syngjoo Choi, Douglas Gale, and Shachar Kariv, 2010, Estimating ambiguity aversion in a portfolio choice experiment, Working Paper. Backus, David K., Bryan R. Routledge, and Stanley E. Zin, 2004, Exotic preferences for macroeconomists, NBER Working Paper Bansal, Ravi, and Amir Yaron, 2004, Risks for the long run: A potential resolution of asset pricing puzzles, Journal of Finance LIX, Benigno, Pierpaolo, and Salvatore Nistico, 2012, International portfolio allocation under model uncertainty, American Economic Journal: Macroeconomics 4, Bossaerts, Peter, Paolo Ghirardato, Serena Guarnaschelli, and William Zame, 2010, Ambiguity in asset markets: Theory and experiment, Review of Financial Studies 23, Boyle, Phelim, Lorenzo Garlappi, Raman Uppal, and Tan Wang, 2012, Keynes meets markowitz: The trade-off between familiarity and diversification, Management Science 58, Campanale, Claudio, 2011, Learning, ambiguity and life-cycle portfolio allocation, Review of Economic Dynamics 14, Cao, H. Henry, Tan Wang, and Harold H. Zhang, 2005, Model uncertainty, limited market participation, and asset prices, Review of Financial Studies 18, Caskey, Judson A., 2009, Information in equity markets with ambiguity-averse investors, Review of Financial Studies 22, Chen, Hui, Nengjiu Ju, and Jianjun Miao, 2011, Dynamic asset allocation with ambiguous return predictability, Working Paper. Cochrane, John H., 2005, Asset Pricing (Princeton University Press) 1 revised edn. 26

27 Collard, Fabrice, Sujoy Mukerji, Kevin Sheppard, and Jean-Marc Tallon, 2011, Ambiguity and the historical equity premium, Working Paper. Condie, Scott, and Jayant Ganguli, 2011a, Ambiguity and rational expectations equilibria, Review of Economic Studies 78, , 2011b, Informational efficiency with ambiguous private information, Economic Theory 48, Dow, J., and S. Werlang, 1992, Uncertainty aversion, risk aversion, and the optimal choice of portfolio, Econometrica 60, Dow, James, and Sergio Ribeiro Da Costa Werlang, 1994, Nash equilibrium under knightian uncertainty breaking down backward induction, Journal of Economic Theory 64, Easley, David, and Maureen O Hara, 2009, Ambiguity and nonparticipation: The role of regulation, Review of Financial Studies 22, Ellsberg, D., 1961, Risk, ambiguity, and the savage axioms, Quarterly Journal of Economics 75, Epstein, Larry G., and Martin Schneider, 2003, Recursive multiple-priors, Journal of Economic Theory 113, 1 31., 2007, Learning under ambiguity, Review of Economic Studies 74, , 2008, Ambiguity, information quality, and asset pricing, Journal of Finance pp , 2010, Ambiguity and asset markets, Annual Review of Financial Economics 2, Epstein, Larry G., and Tan Wang, 1994, Intertemporal asset pricing under Knightian uncertainty, Econometrica 62,

Information Inertia. ScholarlyCommons. University of Pennsylvania. Scott Condie. Jayant Ganguli. Philipp Karl Illeditsch University of Pennsylvania

Information Inertia. ScholarlyCommons. University of Pennsylvania. Scott Condie. Jayant Ganguli. Philipp Karl Illeditsch University of Pennsylvania University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Finance Papers Wharton Faculty Research 1-28-2013 Information Inertia Scott Condie Jayant Ganguli Philipp Karl Illeditsch University of Pennsylvania Follow this

More information

Ambiguous Information, Risk Aversion, and Asset Pricing

Ambiguous Information, Risk Aversion, and Asset Pricing Ambiguous Information, Risk Aversion, and Asset Pricing Philipp Karl ILLEDITSCH May 7, 2009 Abstract I study the effects of aversion to risk and ambiguity (uncertainty in the sense of Knight (1921)) on

More information

Ambiguous Information, Risk Aversion, and Asset Pricing

Ambiguous Information, Risk Aversion, and Asset Pricing Ambiguous Information, Risk Aversion, and Asset Pricing Philipp Karl ILLEDITSCH February 14, 2009 Abstract I study the effects of aversion to risk and ambiguity (uncertainty in the sense of Knight (1921))

More information

Ambiguous Information, Portfolio Inertia, and Excess Volatility

Ambiguous Information, Portfolio Inertia, and Excess Volatility University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Finance Papers Wharton Faculty Research 2011 Ambiguous Information, Portfolio Inertia, and Excess Volatility Philipp Karl Illeditsch University of Pennsylvania

More information

trading ambiguity: a tale of two heterogeneities

trading ambiguity: a tale of two heterogeneities trading ambiguity: a tale of two heterogeneities Sujoy Mukerji, Queen Mary, University of London Han Ozsoylev, Koç University and University of Oxford Jean-Marc Tallon, Paris School of Economics, CNRS

More information

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market Meng-Wei Chen Department of Economics, Indiana University at Bloomington April 21, 2011 Abstract This paper studies the information transmission

More information

When Good News Is Not That Good: The Asymmetric Effect of Correlation Uncertainty

When Good News Is Not That Good: The Asymmetric Effect of Correlation Uncertainty When Good News Is Not That Good: The Asymmetric Effect of Correlation Uncertainty Junya Jiang University of North Carolina at Charlotte. Abstract This paper examines how aversion to uncertainty about the

More information

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Jan Werner March 2014. Abstract: Ambiguous beliefs may lead to speculative trade and speculative bubbles. We demonstrate this by showing that the classical Harrison and

More information

Risk and Ambiguity in Asset Returns

Risk and Ambiguity in Asset Returns Risk and Ambiguity in Asset Returns Cross-Sectional Differences Chiaki Hara and Toshiki Honda KIER, Kyoto University and ICS, Hitotsubashi University KIER, Kyoto University April 6, 2017 Hara and Honda

More information

Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity

Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity Jan Werner December 2013, revised August 2014. Abstract: This paper is about (non) participation in efficient risk sharing in an economy where agents have

More information

The pricing effects of ambiguous private information

The pricing effects of ambiguous private information The pricing effects of ambiguous private information Scott Condie Jayant Ganguli June 6, 2017 Abstract When private information is observed by ambiguity averse investors, asset prices may be informationally

More information

Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information

Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information Han Ozsoylev University of Oxford Jan Werner University of Minnesota Abstract: The quality of information in financial

More information

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Jan Werner November 2014, revised March 2017 Abstract: Ambiguous beliefs may lead to speculative trade and speculative bubbles. We demonstrate this by showing that the

More information

Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information

Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information Han Ozsoylev SBS, University of Oxford Jan Werner University of Minnesota September 006, revised March 007 Abstract:

More information

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Jan Werner March 2014. Abstract: Ambiguous beliefs may lead to speculative trade and speculative bubbles. We demonstrate this by showing that the classical Harrison and

More information

Signal or noise? Uncertainty and learning whether other traders are informed

Signal or noise? Uncertainty and learning whether other traders are informed Signal or noise? Uncertainty and learning whether other traders are informed Snehal Banerjee (Northwestern) Brett Green (UC-Berkeley) AFA 2014 Meetings July 2013 Learning about other traders Trade motives

More information

Ambiguity Aversion in Standard and Extended Ellsberg Frameworks: α-maxmin versus Maxmin Preferences

Ambiguity Aversion in Standard and Extended Ellsberg Frameworks: α-maxmin versus Maxmin Preferences Ambiguity Aversion in Standard and Extended Ellsberg Frameworks: α-maxmin versus Maxmin Preferences Claudia Ravanelli Center for Finance and Insurance Department of Banking and Finance, University of Zurich

More information

Workshop on the pricing and hedging of environmental and energy-related financial derivatives

Workshop on the pricing and hedging of environmental and energy-related financial derivatives Socially efficient discounting under ambiguity aversion Workshop on the pricing and hedging of environmental and energy-related financial derivatives National University of Singapore, December 7-9, 2009

More information

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Speculative Trade under Ambiguity Jan Werner November 2014, revised November 2015 Abstract: Ambiguous beliefs may lead to speculative trade and speculative bubbles. We demonstrate this by showing that

More information

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the open text license amendment to version 2 of the GNU General

More information

LECTURE NOTES 10 ARIEL M. VIALE

LECTURE NOTES 10 ARIEL M. VIALE LECTURE NOTES 10 ARIEL M VIALE 1 Behavioral Asset Pricing 11 Prospect theory based asset pricing model Barberis, Huang, and Santos (2001) assume a Lucas pure-exchange economy with three types of assets:

More information

Ambiguity, ambiguity aversion and stores of value: The case of Argentina

Ambiguity, ambiguity aversion and stores of value: The case of Argentina LETTER Ambiguity, ambiguity aversion and stores of value: The case of Argentina Eduardo Ariel Corso Cogent Economics & Finance (2014), 2: 947001 Page 1 of 13 LETTER Ambiguity, ambiguity aversion and stores

More information

Asset Pricing under Information-processing Constraints

Asset Pricing under Information-processing Constraints The University of Hong Kong From the SelectedWorks of Yulei Luo 00 Asset Pricing under Information-processing Constraints Yulei Luo, The University of Hong Kong Eric Young, University of Virginia Available

More information

Dynamic Asset Allocation with Ambiguous Return Predictability

Dynamic Asset Allocation with Ambiguous Return Predictability Dynamic Asset Allocation with Ambiguous Return Predictability Hui Chen Nengjiu Ju Jianjun Miao First draft: September 2008. This draft: February 2009 Abstract We study an investor s optimal consumption

More information

Dynamic Asset Allocation with Ambiguous Return Predictability

Dynamic Asset Allocation with Ambiguous Return Predictability Dynamic Asset Allocation with Ambiguous Return Predictability Hui Chen Nengjiu Ju Jianjun Miao March 9, 23 Abstract We study an investor s optimal consumption and portfolio choice problem when he is confronted

More information

Risk, Uncertainty, and Option Exercise

Risk, Uncertainty, and Option Exercise Risk, Uncertainty, and Option Exercise Jianjun Miao and Neng Wang September 9, 2010 Abstract Many economic decisions can be described as an option exercise or optimal stopping problem under uncertainty.

More information

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011 Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011 There are two questions on the exam, representing Macroeconomic Finance (234A) and Corporate Finance (234C). Please answer both questions to the best of your

More information

CONSUMPTION-BASED MACROECONOMIC MODELS OF ASSET PRICING THEORY

CONSUMPTION-BASED MACROECONOMIC MODELS OF ASSET PRICING THEORY ECONOMIC ANNALS, Volume LXI, No. 211 / October December 2016 UDC: 3.33 ISSN: 0013-3264 DOI:10.2298/EKA1611007D Marija Đorđević* CONSUMPTION-BASED MACROECONOMIC MODELS OF ASSET PRICING THEORY ABSTRACT:

More information

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Shingo Ishiguro Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University 1-7 Machikaneyama, Toyonaka, Osaka 560-0043, Japan August 2002

More information

What Can Rational Investors Do About Excessive Volatility and Sentiment Fluctuations?

What Can Rational Investors Do About Excessive Volatility and Sentiment Fluctuations? What Can Rational Investors Do About Excessive Volatility and Sentiment Fluctuations? Bernard Dumas INSEAD, Wharton, CEPR, NBER Alexander Kurshev London Business School Raman Uppal London Business School,

More information

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION Szabolcs Sebestyén szabolcs.sebestyen@iscte.pt Master in Finance INVESTMENTS Sebestyén (ISCTE-IUL) Choice Theory Investments 1 / 65 Outline 1 An Introduction

More information

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants April 2008 Abstract In this paper, we determine the optimal exercise strategy for corporate warrants if investors suffer from

More information

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure Feedback Effect and Capital Structure Minh Vo Metropolitan State University Abstract This paper develops a model of financing with informational feedback effect that jointly determines a firm s capital

More information

Should Norway Change the 60% Equity portion of the GPFG fund?

Should Norway Change the 60% Equity portion of the GPFG fund? Should Norway Change the 60% Equity portion of the GPFG fund? Pierre Collin-Dufresne EPFL & SFI, and CEPR April 2016 Outline Endowment Consumption Commitments Return Predictability and Trading Costs General

More information

Ambiguity Aversion. Mark Dean. Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University

Ambiguity Aversion. Mark Dean. Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University Ambiguity Aversion Mark Dean Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University 1 Subjective Expected Utility So far, we have been considering the roulette wheel world of objective probabilities:

More information

1 Asset Pricing: Bonds vs Stocks

1 Asset Pricing: Bonds vs Stocks Asset Pricing: Bonds vs Stocks The historical data on financial asset returns show that one dollar invested in the Dow- Jones yields 6 times more than one dollar invested in U.S. Treasury bonds. The return

More information

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints 1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints In this section we study conditions under which savings react to changes in income uncertainty. Recall that in the PIH, when you abstract from

More information

1 Asset Pricing: Replicating portfolios

1 Asset Pricing: Replicating portfolios Alberto Bisin Corporate Finance: Lecture Notes Class 1: Valuation updated November 17th, 2002 1 Asset Pricing: Replicating portfolios Consider an economy with two states of nature {s 1, s 2 } and with

More information

THE CARLO ALBERTO NOTEBOOKS

THE CARLO ALBERTO NOTEBOOKS THE CARLO ALBERTO NOTEBOOKS Ambiguity in Asset Markets: Theory and Experiment Peter Bossaerts Paolo Ghirardato Serena Guarnaschelli William R. Zame No.27, September 2006* www.carloalberto.org *Revised

More information

Uncertainty, Information Acquisition and Price Swings in Asset Markets

Uncertainty, Information Acquisition and Price Swings in Asset Markets Uncertainty, Information Acquisition and Price Swings in Asset Markets Antonio Mele London School of Economics Francesco Sangiorgi Stockholm School of Economics First draft: May 4, 009. This draft: March

More information

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1 A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model of Inequity Aversion 1 Kirsten I.M. Rohde 2 January 12, 2009 1 The author would like to thank Itzhak Gilboa, Ingrid M.T. Rohde, Klaus M. Schmidt, and

More information

Home Bias Puzzle. Is It a Puzzle or Not? Gavriilidis Constantinos *, Greece UDC: JEL: G15

Home Bias Puzzle. Is It a Puzzle or Not? Gavriilidis Constantinos *, Greece UDC: JEL: G15 SCIENFITIC REVIEW Home Bias Puzzle. Is It a Puzzle or Not? Gavriilidis Constantinos *, Greece UDC: 336.69 JEL: G15 ABSTRACT The benefits of international diversification have been well documented over

More information

Dynamic asset allocation with ambiguous return predictability

Dynamic asset allocation with ambiguous return predictability Dynamic asset allocation with ambiguous return predictability The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation As Published

More information

Solving dynamic portfolio choice problems by recursing on optimized portfolio weights or on the value function?

Solving dynamic portfolio choice problems by recursing on optimized portfolio weights or on the value function? DOI 0.007/s064-006-9073-z ORIGINAL PAPER Solving dynamic portfolio choice problems by recursing on optimized portfolio weights or on the value function? Jules H. van Binsbergen Michael W. Brandt Received:

More information

Risk and Ambiguity in Models of Business Cycles by David Backus, Axelle Ferriere and Stanley Zin

Risk and Ambiguity in Models of Business Cycles by David Backus, Axelle Ferriere and Stanley Zin Discussion Risk and Ambiguity in Models of Business Cycles by David Backus, Axelle Ferriere and Stanley Zin 1 Introduction This is a very interesting, topical and useful paper. The motivation for this

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH http://www.kier.kyoto-u.ac.jp/index.html Discussion Paper No. 657 The Buy Price in Auctions with Discrete Type Distributions Yusuke Inami

More information

Asset Prices in General Equilibrium with Transactions Costs and Recursive Utility

Asset Prices in General Equilibrium with Transactions Costs and Recursive Utility Asset Prices in General Equilibrium with Transactions Costs and Recursive Utility Adrian Buss Raman Uppal Grigory Vilkov February 28, 2011 Preliminary Abstract In this paper, we study the effect of proportional

More information

Ambiguity, Learning, and Asset Returns

Ambiguity, Learning, and Asset Returns Ambiguity, Learning, and Asset Returns Nengjiu Ju and Jianjun Miao June 2011 Abstract We propose a novel generalized recursive smooth ambiguity model which permits a threeway separation among risk aversion,

More information

Measuring the Amount of Asymmetric Information in the Foreign Exchange Market

Measuring the Amount of Asymmetric Information in the Foreign Exchange Market Measuring the Amount of Asymmetric Information in the Foreign Exchange Market Esen Onur 1 and Ufuk Devrim Demirel 2 September 2009 VERY PRELIMINARY & INCOMPLETE PLEASE DO NOT CITE WITHOUT AUTHORS PERMISSION

More information

Reading the Tea Leaves: Model Uncertainty, Robust Foreca. Forecasts, and the Autocorrelation of Analysts Forecast Errors

Reading the Tea Leaves: Model Uncertainty, Robust Foreca. Forecasts, and the Autocorrelation of Analysts Forecast Errors Reading the Tea Leaves: Model Uncertainty, Robust Forecasts, and the Autocorrelation of Analysts Forecast Errors December 1, 2016 Table of Contents Introduction Autocorrelation Puzzle Hansen-Sargent Autocorrelation

More information

Asset Pricing in Financial Markets

Asset Pricing in Financial Markets Cognitive Biases, Ambiguity Aversion and Asset Pricing in Financial Markets E. Asparouhova, P. Bossaerts, J. Eguia, and W. Zame April 17, 2009 The Question The Question Do cognitive biases (directly) affect

More information

Ambiguity, Learning, and Asset Returns

Ambiguity, Learning, and Asset Returns Ambiguity, Learning, and Asset Returns Nengjiu Ju and Jianjun Miao September 2007 Abstract We develop a consumption-based asset-pricing model in which the representative agent is ambiguous about the hidden

More information

The Role of Risk Aversion and Intertemporal Substitution in Dynamic Consumption-Portfolio Choice with Recursive Utility

The Role of Risk Aversion and Intertemporal Substitution in Dynamic Consumption-Portfolio Choice with Recursive Utility The Role of Risk Aversion and Intertemporal Substitution in Dynamic Consumption-Portfolio Choice with Recursive Utility Harjoat S. Bhamra Sauder School of Business University of British Columbia Raman

More information

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Jin Yong Jung We analyze how the wealth of an agent and its distribution affect the profit of the principal by considering the simple

More information

Capital Asset Pricing under Ambiguity

Capital Asset Pricing under Ambiguity Capital Asset Pricing under Ambiguity Yehuda Izhakian February 17, 01 Abstract This paper generalizes the mean variance preferences to mean variance ambiguity preferences by relaxing the standard assumption

More information

Comparing Different Regulatory Measures to Control Stock Market Volatility: A General Equilibrium Analysis

Comparing Different Regulatory Measures to Control Stock Market Volatility: A General Equilibrium Analysis Comparing Different Regulatory Measures to Control Stock Market Volatility: A General Equilibrium Analysis A. Buss B. Dumas R. Uppal G. Vilkov INSEAD INSEAD, CEPR, NBER Edhec, CEPR Goethe U. Frankfurt

More information

Long-run Consumption Risks in Assets Returns: Evidence from Economic Divisions

Long-run Consumption Risks in Assets Returns: Evidence from Economic Divisions Long-run Consumption Risks in Assets Returns: Evidence from Economic Divisions Abdulrahman Alharbi 1 Abdullah Noman 2 Abstract: Bansal et al (2009) paper focus on measuring risk in consumption especially

More information

Market Timing Does Work: Evidence from the NYSE 1

Market Timing Does Work: Evidence from the NYSE 1 Market Timing Does Work: Evidence from the NYSE 1 Devraj Basu Alexander Stremme Warwick Business School, University of Warwick November 2005 address for correspondence: Alexander Stremme Warwick Business

More information

Liquidity and Valuation in an Uncertain Market with Multiple Risky Assets and Difference of Opinions

Liquidity and Valuation in an Uncertain Market with Multiple Risky Assets and Difference of Opinions Liquidity and Valuation in an Uncertain Market with Multiple Risky Assets and Difference of Opinions Qi Nan Zhai FDG School of Finance and Economics, UTS Business School University of Technology, Sydney

More information

A Simple, Adjustably Robust, Dynamic Portfolio Policy under Expected Return Ambiguity

A Simple, Adjustably Robust, Dynamic Portfolio Policy under Expected Return Ambiguity A Simple, Adjustably Robust, Dynamic Portfolio Policy under Expected Return Ambiguity Mustafa Ç. Pınar Department of Industrial Engineering Bilkent University 06800 Bilkent, Ankara, Turkey March 16, 2012

More information

Information Processing and Limited Liability

Information Processing and Limited Liability Information Processing and Limited Liability Bartosz Maćkowiak European Central Bank and CEPR Mirko Wiederholt Northwestern University January 2012 Abstract Decision-makers often face limited liability

More information

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II EconS 50 - Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II. Exercise 6.E.: The purpose of this exercise is to show that preferences may not be transitive in the presence of regret. Let there be S states

More information

Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics. Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle

Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics. Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring 2006 Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle 1 Overview This lecture derives the consumption-based capital asset pricing

More information

Correlation Ambiguity

Correlation Ambiguity Correlation Ambiguity Jun Liu University of California at San Diego Xudong Zeng Shanghai University of Finance and Economics This Version 2016.09.15 ABSTRACT Most papers on ambiguity aversion in the setting

More information

Liquidity and Risk Management

Liquidity and Risk Management Liquidity and Risk Management By Nicolae Gârleanu and Lasse Heje Pedersen Risk management plays a central role in institutional investors allocation of capital to trading. For instance, a risk manager

More information

Labor Economics Field Exam Spring 2011

Labor Economics Field Exam Spring 2011 Labor Economics Field Exam Spring 2011 Instructions You have 4 hours to complete this exam. This is a closed book examination. No written materials are allowed. You can use a calculator. THE EXAM IS COMPOSED

More information

Learning and Asset Prices under Ambiguous Information

Learning and Asset Prices under Ambiguous Information Working Paper Series National Centre of Competence in Research Financial Valuation and Risk Management Working Paper No. 249 Learning and Asset Prices under Ambiguous Information Markus Leippold Fabio

More information

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria and Rational Expectations Equilibria 1 Basic Setup Two periods: 0 and 1 One riskless asset with interest rate r One risky asset which pays a normally distributed

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren October, 2013 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Online Appendix: Extensions

Online Appendix: Extensions B Online Appendix: Extensions In this online appendix we demonstrate that many important variations of the exact cost-basis LUL framework remain tractable. In particular, dual problem instances corresponding

More information

EIEF/LUISS, Graduate Program. Asset Pricing

EIEF/LUISS, Graduate Program. Asset Pricing EIEF/LUISS, Graduate Program Asset Pricing Nicola Borri 2017 2018 1 Presentation 1.1 Course Description The topics and approach of this class combine macroeconomics and finance, with an emphasis on developing

More information

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing Richard M. H. Suen University of Leicester 29 March 2018 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/86499/ MPRA Paper

More information

Toward A Term Structure of Macroeconomic Risk

Toward A Term Structure of Macroeconomic Risk Toward A Term Structure of Macroeconomic Risk Pricing Unexpected Growth Fluctuations Lars Peter Hansen 1 2007 Nemmers Lecture, Northwestern University 1 Based in part joint work with John Heaton, Nan Li,

More information

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions. Risk Aversion We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions. Assume there is no entry fee or reserve. Note: Risk aversion does not affect bidding in SPA because there,

More information

Does Ambiguity Matter for Ex Ante Regulation and Ex Post Liability? 1

Does Ambiguity Matter for Ex Ante Regulation and Ex Post Liability? 1 Does Ambiguity Matter for Ex Ante Regulation and Ex Post Liability? 1 Casey Bolt 2 and Ana Espinola-Arredondo 3 Washington State University Abstract This paper studies regulation of firms that engage in

More information

RECURSIVE VALUATION AND SENTIMENTS

RECURSIVE VALUATION AND SENTIMENTS 1 / 32 RECURSIVE VALUATION AND SENTIMENTS Lars Peter Hansen Bendheim Lectures, Princeton University 2 / 32 RECURSIVE VALUATION AND SENTIMENTS ABSTRACT Expectations and uncertainty about growth rates that

More information

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Fall 2013 D. Romer

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Fall 2013 D. Romer UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Economics 202A DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Fall 203 D. Romer FORCES LIMITING THE EXTENT TO WHICH SOPHISTICATED INVESTORS ARE WILLING TO MAKE TRADES THAT MOVE ASSET PRICES BACK TOWARD

More information

Real Options and Game Theory in Incomplete Markets

Real Options and Game Theory in Incomplete Markets Real Options and Game Theory in Incomplete Markets M. Grasselli Mathematics and Statistics McMaster University IMPA - June 28, 2006 Strategic Decision Making Suppose we want to assign monetary values to

More information

Ambiguity, Information Quality and Asset Pricing. Epstein, Larry G., and Martin Schneider. Working Paper No. 519 July 2005 UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER

Ambiguity, Information Quality and Asset Pricing. Epstein, Larry G., and Martin Schneider. Working Paper No. 519 July 2005 UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER Ambiguity, Information Quality and Asset Pricing Epstein, Larry G., and Martin Schneider Working Paper No. 519 July 2005 UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER AMBIGUITY, INFORMATION QUALITY AND ASSET PRICING Larry G.

More information

INTERTEMPORAL ASSET ALLOCATION: THEORY

INTERTEMPORAL ASSET ALLOCATION: THEORY INTERTEMPORAL ASSET ALLOCATION: THEORY Multi-Period Model The agent acts as a price-taker in asset markets and then chooses today s consumption and asset shares to maximise lifetime utility. This multi-period

More information

A Theory of Asset Prices based on Heterogeneous Information and Limits to Arbitrage

A Theory of Asset Prices based on Heterogeneous Information and Limits to Arbitrage A Theory of Asset Prices based on Heterogeneous Information and Limits to Arbitrage Elias Albagli USC Marhsall Christian Hellwig Toulouse School of Economics Aleh Tsyvinski Yale University September 20,

More information

FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management

FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management Investment Funds Topic 1: Introduction Unit Trusts: investor s funds are pooled, usually into specific types of assets. o Investors are assigned tradeable

More information

Ambiguity Aversion: Implications for the Uncovered Interest Rate Parity Puzzle

Ambiguity Aversion: Implications for the Uncovered Interest Rate Parity Puzzle Ambiguity Aversion: Implications for the Uncovered Interest Rate Parity Puzzle Cosmin L. Ilut Duke University First version: October 2008 Revised version: March 2010 Abstract High-interest-rate currencies

More information

Volume 30, Issue 1. Samih A Azar Haigazian University

Volume 30, Issue 1. Samih A Azar Haigazian University Volume 30, Issue Random risk aversion and the cost of eliminating the foreign exchange risk of the Euro Samih A Azar Haigazian University Abstract This paper answers the following questions. If the Euro

More information

Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case

Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case Kalyan Chatterjee Kaustav Das November 18, 2017 Abstract Chatterjee and Das (Chatterjee,K.,

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class March 30, 2015 1. (20 points) An agent has Y 0 = 1 to invest. On the market two financial assets exist. The first one is riskless.

More information

Index and Smart Beta when Investors are Ambiguity Averse

Index and Smart Beta when Investors are Ambiguity Averse Index and Smart Beta when Investors are Ambiguity Averse David Hirshleifer Chong Huang Siew Hong Teoh June 1, 2018 Abstract We show that in a rational expectations equilibrium model, investors who are

More information

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Consumption and Asset Pricing Consumption and Asset Pricing Yin-Chi Wang The Chinese University of Hong Kong November, 2012 References: Williamson s lecture notes (2006) ch5 and ch 6 Further references: Stochastic dynamic programming:

More information

Problem set 5. Asset pricing. Markus Roth. Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz. Juli 5, 2010

Problem set 5. Asset pricing. Markus Roth. Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz. Juli 5, 2010 Problem set 5 Asset pricing Markus Roth Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz Juli 5, 200 Markus Roth (Macroeconomics 2) Problem set 5 Juli 5, 200 / 40 Contents Problem 5 of problem

More information

Macroeconomics. Lecture 5: Consumption. Hernán D. Seoane. Spring, 2016 MEDEG, UC3M UC3M

Macroeconomics. Lecture 5: Consumption. Hernán D. Seoane. Spring, 2016 MEDEG, UC3M UC3M Macroeconomics MEDEG, UC3M Lecture 5: Consumption Hernán D. Seoane UC3M Spring, 2016 Introduction A key component in NIPA accounts and the households budget constraint is the consumption It represents

More information

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations Prof. Massimo Guidolin 20135 Theory of Finance, Part I (Sept. October) Fall 2014 Outline and objectives The backward, three-step solution

More information

Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment

Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment George Alogoskoufis, Dynamic Macroeconomic Theory, 2015 Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment In this chapter we present the main neoclassical model of investment, under convex adjustment costs. This

More information

A Note on Predicting Returns with Financial Ratios

A Note on Predicting Returns with Financial Ratios A Note on Predicting Returns with Financial Ratios Amit Goyal Goizueta Business School Emory University Ivo Welch Yale School of Management Yale Economics Department NBER December 16, 2003 Abstract This

More information

Behavioral Theories of the Business Cycle

Behavioral Theories of the Business Cycle Behavioral Theories of the Business Cycle Nir Jaimovich and Sergio Rebelo September 2006 Abstract We explore the business cycle implications of expectation shocks and of two well-known psychological biases,

More information

Return Decomposition over the Business Cycle

Return Decomposition over the Business Cycle Return Decomposition over the Business Cycle Tolga Cenesizoglu March 1, 2016 Cenesizoglu Return Decomposition & the Business Cycle March 1, 2016 1 / 54 Introduction Stock prices depend on investors expectations

More information

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS Peter Ireland Boston College Fall 2017 These lecture notes by Peter Ireland are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommerical-ShareAlike 4.0 International

More information

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS Peter Ireland Boston College Spring 2018 These lecture notes by Peter Ireland are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommerical-ShareAlike 4.0 International

More information

Ambiguity, Information Quality and Asset Pricing. Larry G. Epstein and Martin Schneider. Working Paper No. 507 May 2004 UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER

Ambiguity, Information Quality and Asset Pricing. Larry G. Epstein and Martin Schneider. Working Paper No. 507 May 2004 UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER Ambiguity, Information Quality and Asset Pricing Larry G. Epstein and Martin Schneider Working Paper No. 507 May 2004 UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER AMBIGUITY, INFORMATION QUALITY AND ASSET PRICING Larry G. Epstein

More information

Prices and Allocations in Asset Markets with Heterogeneous Attitudes Towards Ambiguity

Prices and Allocations in Asset Markets with Heterogeneous Attitudes Towards Ambiguity Prices and Allocations in Asset Markets with Heterogeneous Attitudes Towards Ambiguity Peter Bossaerts, Paolo Ghirardato, Serena Guarnaschelli and William Zame This version: February 27 Bossaerts: Caltech,

More information