Asset Pricing. Teaching Notes. João Pedro Pereira

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Asset Pricing. Teaching Notes. João Pedro Pereira"

Transcription

1 Asset Pricing Teaching Notes João Pedro Pereira Nova School of Business and Economics Universidade Nova de Lisboa jpereira/ June 18, 2015

2 Contents 1 Introduction 5 2 Choice theory Motivation The utility function Choice under certainty Choice under uncertainty Interpretation of utility numbers Risk aversion Concepts Measures of risk aversion Risk neutrality Important utility functions Certainty Equivalent Stochastic dominance First Order Stochastic Dominance Second Order Stochastic Dominance Exercises Portfolio choice Canonical portfolio problem Analysis of the optimal portfolio choice Risk aversion Wealth Canonical portfolio problem for N > Exercises Portfolio choice for Mean-Variance investors Mean-Variance preferences Quadratic utility Normal returns Conclusion Review: Mean-Variance frontier with 2 stocks

3 Contents Setup for general case Notation Brief notions of matrix calculus Frontier with N risky assets Efficient portfolio Frontier equation Global minimum variance portfolio Frontier with N risky assets and 1 risk-free asset Efficient portfolio Frontier equation Tangency portfolio Optimal portfolio Additional properties of frontier portfolios Exercises Capital Asset Pricing Model Introduction Derivation Important results Capital Market Line Security Market Line Other remarks Exercises Arbitrage Pricing Theory and Factor Models Factor Structure Example of simple factor structure: Market Model Return generating process Application: the Covariance matrix is simplified Implication: Diversification eliminates Specific risk Another interpretation of the CAPM β Pricing equation Exact factor pricing with one factor Exact factor pricing with more than one factor Approximate factor pricing How to identify the factors Overview Fama and French model Applications Fund performance Market neutral strategy Exercises

4 Contents 4 7 Pricing in Complete Markets Basic and Complex securities Computing AD prices Complete Markets Price of complex securities Quick test for market completeness Risk-Neutral Pricing Price of complex securities Fundamental theorems Conclusion Exercises Consumption-Based Asset Pricing The investor s problem Fundamental Asset Pricing Equation Relation to Arrow-Debreu Securities Relation to the Risk-Neutral measure Risk Premiums Consumption CAPM (CCAPM) The CAPM reloaded Conclusion Exercises Conclusion 99 Bibliography 100 A Background Review 102 A.1 Math Review A.1.1 Logarithm and Exponential A.1.2 Derivatives A.1.3 Optimization A.1.4 Means and Variances A.2 Undergraduate Finance Review A.2.1 Financial Markets and Instruments A.2.2 Time value of money A.2.3 Risk and Return A.2.4 Equilibrium and No Arbitrage B Solutions to Problems 112

5 Chapter 1 Introduction These notes follow Danthine and Donaldson (2005) closely, though we will use other sources as needed. We will start by analyzing individual choices and portfolio decisions. Then, we will study the prices that result from the interaction of many individuals in the market. To motivate the work to come, consider the following question: What is the role of financial markets? Answer: allowing the desynchronization of agents income and consumption. Example: buy a house now and pay for it during the next 20 years. This is achieved by trading financial securities with financial institutions. Preference for smooth consumption Financial economists see the world in two dimensions. It is useful to understand why agents want to dissociate consumption and income across these two dimensions. 1. Time Dimension. Most people prefer to smooth their consumption through their life cycle. Usually, consumption is higher than income during early years of life (buy the house), then people save during active life (y > c), finally people consume their savings after retirement (y = 0, c > 0). 2. Risk Dimension. The future is uncertain. At any point in the future, one of many states of nature will be realized. 1 Most people want to smooth consumption 1 A state of nature is a complete description of a possible scenario for the future across all the dimensions relevant for the problem at hand. 5

6 6 across the different possibilities that may arise. That s why people buy health insurance (to be able to consume even if they stop working) or fire insurance for the new house (avoid low consumption in the burned to the ground state of nature). Financial assets serve precisely to move consumption through time and across states of nature. Modelling the preference for smoothness Financial economics builds on the fact that people have a preference for smoothness, as just mentioned. How to model this preference for smoothness, also called risk aversion? Consider two assets that offer two different consumption plans: asset 1 asset 2 time/state time/state Since investors like smoothness, they must prefer asset 1. 2 Let U(c) be the utility function, i.e., it tells us how much the investor likes consumption c. The utility function must thus satisfy U(4) + U(4) > U(3) + U(5) U(4) > 1 2 U(3) U(5) What shape must U(.) have to satisfy this condition? 3 Plot it: U(c) 2 Suppose your employer offers you the following salary scheme: under scheme 1, you get $4,000 per month; under scheme 2, you get $3,000 if it rains or $5,000 if it is sunny. Which scheme would you take? 3 Answer: It must be strictly concave c

7 Chapter 2 Choice theory 1. Under certain conditions, investors preferences can be represented by a utility function, 2. Typical utility functions: x y E[U(x)] E[U(y)] U(w) = ln(w) U(w) = w 1 γ /(1 γ) U(w) = exp( αw) U(w) = aw bw 2 [CRRA] [CRRA] [CARA] 2.1 Motivation We want to find a method to choose between risky assets. Consider the following simple example: Example There are 3 assets and 2 equally likely possible states of nature in the future: t = 0 t = 1 state θ = 1 state θ = 2 asset asset asset

8 2.2. The utility function 8 Which asset would you rather have? In this case, the choice is easy. Asset 3 clearly dominates the other assets, since it pays at least as much in all states of nature, and strictly more in some states. This is an example of state-by-state dominance. State-by-state dominance is the strongest possible form of dominance. We can safely assume that all rational agents will always prefer asset 3. 1 However, the world is not that simple and we will not usually be able to use this concept to make choices. (Is it likely we will observe a market like in this example? Why not?) Suppose now that asset 3 does not exist. Do you prefer asset 1 or asset 2? The choice is not obvious... To understand the choices people make in the real world we need a better machinery utility theory. 2.2 The utility function To be able to represent agents preferences by a formal mathematical object like a function, we need to make precise assumptions about how people make choices Choice under certainty We start by postulating the existence of a preference relation. For two consumption bundles a and b (two vectors with the amount of consumption of each good), we either say that a b a is strictly preferred to b a b a is indifferent to b a b a is strictly preferred or indifferent to b (a not worse than b) We make the following economic rationality assumptions: A1: Every investor possesses a complete preference relation. I.e., he must be able to state a preference for all a and b. 1 More precisely, we are assuming agents to be nonsatiated in consumption (always like more consumption) 2 People have wasted time thinking about reformulating the canonical portfolio problem just because they were not aware of the axioms that lead to an expected utility representation.

9 2.2. The utility function 9 A2: The preference relation satisfies the property of transitivity: a, b, c, a b and b c a c A3: The preference relation is continuous. 3 Under these circumstances, we can now state the following useful theorem: Theorem Assumptions A1 3 are sufficient to guarantee the existence of a continuous function u : R N R such that, for any consumption bundles a and b, a b u(a) u(b) This real-valued function u is called a utility function. Note that the notion of consumption bundle used in the theorem is quite general. Different elements of the bundle may represent the consumption of the same good in different time periods or in different states of nature Choice under uncertainty Even thought the previous thm is quite general, we want to extend it in a way that captures uncertainty explicitly and separates utility from probabilities. Definition (Lottery). The simple lottery (x, y, π) is a gamble that offers payoff x with probability π and payoff y with probability 1 π. This notion of lottery is quite general. The payoffs x and y can represent monetary or consumption amounts. If there is no uncertainty, we can write (x, y, 1) = x The payoffs can themselves be other lotteries, leading to compound lotteries. For example, if y = (y 1, y 2, τ), we will have (x, y, π) = (x, (y 1, y 2, τ), π) We assume that the agent is able to work out the probability tree and only cares about the final outcomes. 4 Assume the following axioms: 3 Technical assumption. See Danthine and Donaldson (2005) for details on this and Huang and Litzenberger (1988) for further technical details. 4 A lottery is the simplest example of a random variable. Stock prices are random variables, so you can see where we are going.

10 2.2. The utility function 10 B1: There exists a preference relation, defined on lotteries, which is complete, transitive, and continuous. Since the consumption bundles in theorem where general enough to include consumption in different states of nature, it can be applied here to ensure that there exists a utility function U() defined on lotteries. To get an expected utility representation of preferences, we need the following crucial axiom: B2: Independence of irrelevant alternatives. Let (x, y, π) and (x, z, π) be any two lotteries. Then, y z (x, y, π) (x, z, π) In other words, x is irrelevant; including it does not change the investor s preferences about y and z. This axiom is not trivial and has been strongly contested. One well know violation is the Allais Paradox. 5 This and other violations have lead to the exploration of alternatives to the expected utility framework, namely to the growing field of Behavioral Finance. Despite this, recall that the goal of financial economics is to understand the aggregate market behavior and not individual behavior. At this point, expected utility is the most useful framework. We now get to the punchline: Theorem (Expected Utility Theorem). If axioms B1 2 hold, then there exists a real-valued function U, defined on the space of lotteries, such that the preference relation can be represented as an expected utility, that is, for any lotteries x and y, x y E[U(x)] E[U(y)] The function U(), defined over lotteries, is called a von Neumann-Morgenstern (vnm) utility function. 6 5 Allais Paradox. Given the four lotteries defined below, most people show the following preferences: and L1 = ($10000, $0, 0.10) L2 = ($15000, $0, 0.09) L3 = ($10000, $0, 1.00) L4 = ($15000, $0, 0.90) However, given that L1 = (L3, $0, 0.1) and L2 = (L4, $0, 0.1), with $0 the irrelevant alternative, the independence axiom would imply L3 L4 L1 L2! 6 This designation is sometimes confusing. Some people define U := E[U()] and call this U the vnm utility function, while others call vnm to the u() defined on sure things. Nonetheless, it is always used in the context of preferences that have an expected utility representation theorem 2.2.2

11 2.2. The utility function 11 Note that x and y can be lotteries with multiple outcomes. outcome in state s that occurs with probability π s, 7 we have Denoting by x s the { s E[U(x)] = U(x s)π s x is a discrete r.v. s U(x s)π s ds x is a continuous r.v. Example Let U(x) = x. Choose between assets 1 and 2 in example Example Now consider another investor with U(x) = x 1 2 /(1 2) = 1/x. (It will soon become clear that this investor is very similar to the previous one, though a little bit more risk averse). Check that this investor prefers the other asset Interpretation of utility numbers The numbers returned by the utility function do not have any meaning per se, as the following proposition makes clear. Proposition If U(x) is a vnm utility function for a given preference relation, then V (x) = au(x) + b, a > 0, is also a vnm utility function for the same preference relation, that is, E[U(x)] E[U(y)] E[V (x)] E[V (y)] Proof. E[U(x)] E[U(y)] ae[u(x)] + b ae[u(y)] + b, since a > 0 E[aU(x) + b] E[aU(y) + b] E[V (x)] E[V (y)] Example Suppose a different investor has utility V (x) = 1+2 x. His choice between assets 1 and 2 (from example 2.1.1) will be the same as the choice of the investor with U(x) = x. (Check it!) Hence, the utility function serves only to rank the choices under consideration. The precise magnitude of the number does not have any meaning. 7 More often, especially in probability classes, the state of nature is denoted by ω Ω, and the probability measure by P (ω).

12 2.3. Risk aversion Risk aversion Concepts Consider an investor with wealth Y. Consider also the fair gamble, or lottery, L = (+h, h, 1/2). Definition (Risk aversion). An investor displays risk aversion if he wishes to avoid a fair gamble, i.e., Y Y + L. This implies that the utility function of a risk-averse agent must satisfy E[U(Y )] > E[U(Y + L)] U(Y ) > 1 2 U(Y + h) + 1 U(Y h) 2 This inequality is satisfied for all wealth levels if the utility function is strictly concave. 8 Plot it: U(Y ) Y For twice differentiable utility functions, the sufficient condition for concavity is that U (Y ) < 0. This means that U (Y ) is decreasing in wealth. This important economic concept is called decreasing marginal utility. As wealth increases, the utility from additional consumption decreases. When I am starving, a sandwich tastes great, while when I am almost satiated I don t care about another sandwich. 8 This is formally justified by Jensen s inequality: E[g(X)] g(e[x]), for concave g. If g is strictly concave, the inequality is strict. For the utility function in particular, E[U(Y + L)] < U(E[Y + L]) = U(E[Y ] + E[L]) = U(Y + 0) = U(Y )

13 2.3. Risk aversion Measures of risk aversion We would like to compare utility functions and say which one is more risk averse. Toward this end, we define the following measures of risk aversion: Absolute Risk Aversion: ARA(Y ) U (Y ) U (Y ) Relative Risk Aversion: RRA(Y ) Y U (Y ) U (Y ) Interpretation of ARA. Let π(y, h) be the probability of the favorable outcome at which the investor with wealth Y is indifferent between accepting or rejecting the lottery L = (+h, h, π()). Note that h is an amount of money. It can be shown that π(y, h) = h ARA(Y ) (2.1) 4 The favorable odds requested increase with the amount at stake h. More importantly, the higher the ARA, the more favorable odds the investor demands to accept the lottery. Example A commonly used utility function is U(Y ) = exp( γy ), which is known for having constant ARA, ie, ARA = γ. 9 For this investor, π(y, h) = hγ The higher the degree of ARA (parameter γ), the higher the favorable odds requested (π). However, π does not depend on the level of wealth Y. Is this particular utility function U(Y ) = exp( γy ) a good description of human behavior? We now derive equation (2.1). Proof. π(y, h) must be such that π : Y Y + L E[U(Y )] = E[U(Y + L)] U(Y ) = πu(y + h) + (1 π)u(y h) 9 This is the only utility function with constant ARA. To see this, write U (Y ) U (Y ) = γ U (Y )+γu (Y ) = 0, which is a homogeneous linear differential equation of the second order with constant coefficients. The two special solutions are U 1 = 1 and U 2 = exp( γy ) and the general solution is thus U(Y ) = c 1 + c 2 exp( γy ). This is a linear transformation of U(Y ) = exp( γy ), therefore representing the same preferences. Thanks to Diogo Bessam for pointing this out.

14 2.3. Risk aversion 14 Expanding U(Y + h) and U(Y h) in Taylor series around Y, we get 10 U(Y + h) = U(Y ) + hu (Y ) h2 U (Y ) + O(h 2 ) U(Y h) =... Ignoring terms of higher order, replacing both these approximations in the previous equation, and canceling terms, we get equation (2.1). Interpretation of RRA. Now we define a gamble in terms of a proportion of the investor s initial wealth. Specifically, we set h = θy, and the lottery becomes L = (θy, θy, π()). π(y, θ) is the probability of the favorable outcome at which the investor is indifferent between accepting or rejecting the lottery. It can be shown that π(y, θ) = θ RRA(Y ) (2.2) 4 The favorable odds requested increase with the proportion of wealth at stake θ. More importantly, the higher the RRA, the more favorable odds the investor demands to accept the lottery. Example An important utility function is U(Y ) = Y 1 γ /(1 γ), which is known for having constant RRA, ie, RRA = γ. 11 For this investor, π(y, θ) = θγ (2.3) 4 The higher the degree of RRA (parameter γ), the higher the favorable odds requested (π). Again, π does not depend on the level of wealth Y. It depends only on the proportion of wealth θ at stake. We do like this! Historically, stock returns look stationary (same mean through time), while aggregate wealth has been increasing. Thus, investors must require an expected return that cannot depend on the amount of wealth at risk. (Note that the expected return is determined by π.) The utility function with constant 10 Taylor series: f(x) = f(a) + f (a)(x a) f (a)(x a) n! f (n) (a)(x a) n This is the only utility function with constant RRA. To see this, write Y U (Y ) U (Y ) = γ U (Y ) + γ Y U (Y ) = 0, which is a homogeneous linear differential equation of the second order. One specific solution is U 1 = Y 1 γ /(1 γ) (check that it satisfies the equation). The second exp{ γ/y dy } linearly independent solution is given by U 2 = U 1 (U 1) dy = 1. The general 2 solution is thus U(Y ) = c 1 Y 1 γ /(1 γ) c 2, a linear transformation of U(Y ) = Y 1 γ /(1 γ), therefore representing the same preferences. Again, thanks to Diogo Bessam for pointing this out.

15 2.4. Important utility functions 15 RRA (RRA = γ only, Y does not show up) is consistent with these empirical facts. 12 The proof of equation (2.2) is left as an exercise Risk neutrality Risk-neutral investors don t care about risk. Their utility function is linear: U(Y ) = a + by, b > 0 Check that ARA = 0 and RRA = 0, which implies π(y, h) = π(y, θ) = 1/2. Hence, risk neutral investors are indifferent to fair games (i.e., symmetrical games with chances). They will always choose the asset with highest expected payoff, regardless of its risk. 2.4 Important utility functions The most common utility functions are the following: Name U(Y ) = Restrictions ARA RRA on parameters Log ln(y ) na Power Y 1 γ /(1 γ) Exponential exp( αy ) Quadratic ay by 2

16 2.5. Certainty Equivalent 16 Complete the table. In particular, define the restrictions on parameters s.t. the functions are proper utility functions, i.e., U > 0 and U < 0. Note that the quadratic utility function also needs a restriction on the domain (Y <... ). Also, compute the ARA and RRA functions, and classify the corresponding utility as increasing, decreasing, or constant ARA/RRA. As mentioned above, the power (and log) utility are considered good utility functions. Typical values for the degree of risk-aversion are γ = 1, 2, 3, 5. The other two utility functions are not so good descriptors of human behavior (as you can see by the ARA and RRA functions you got). As we will see in later sections, the exponential utility is used because it simplifies the calculations when asset returns are normally distributed, and the quadratic utility simplifies them even further for any distribution. 2.5 Certainty Equivalent Consider an investor with initial wealth Y. Consider a gamble Z = (Z 1, Z 2, π). How much is this risky asset worth? Definition (Certainty Equivalent). CE(Y, Z), the certainty equivalent of the risky investment Z, is the certain amount of money which provides the same utility as the gamble, i.e., E[U(Y + Z)] = U(Y + CE) The investor is indifferent between receiving CE(Y, Z) for sure and playing the gamble Z. In other words, if the investor owns the asset, he is willing to sell it at a price equal to the certainty equivalent. The CE is useful to compare different assets in more intuitive terms (money, instead of utility numbers). Note that a risk-averse agent will always value an asset at something less than its expected payoff: CE < E[Z] Thinking about the cross section of assets, note that (2.3) allows different assets to have different expected returns: π increases with θ, and thus the expected return also increases with θ. Does this make sense? Think about risk! 13 Let Z be any random variable. Since U is strictly concave (U < 0), from Jensen s inequality, Hence, from the definition of CE, Since U is increasing (U > 0), we must have E[U(Y + Z)] < U(E[Y + Z]) = U(Y + E[Z]) U(Y + CE) < U(Y + E[Z]) Y + CE < Y + E[Z] CE < E[Z]

17 2.5. Certainty Equivalent 17 Example The investor has log utility and initial wealth Y = The risky investment is Z = (200, 0, 0.5). Compute the CE: E[U(Y + Z)] = U(Y + CE)... CE = Why is the investor willing to accept less than the expected value of the gamble, ie, why is CE = < E[Z] = 100? Risk aversion. Plot the utility function, marking the points Y + Z 1, Y + Z 2, Y + EZ, Y + CE. U(Y ) Y Consider now a fair gamble: Example The investor has log utility and initial wealth Y = 100. The risky prospect is Z = (20, 20, 0.5). We get: E[U(Y + Z)] = U(Y + CE) 1/2 ln(120) + 1/2 ln(80) = ln(100 + CE) CE = 2.02 What does it mean the CE to be negative? Plot the utility function, marking the points Y + Z 1, Y + Z 2, Y + EZ, Y + CE.

18 2.6. Stochastic dominance Stochastic dominance We now reverse gears and look for circumstances where the ranking among random variables is preference free, that is, where we do not need to specify a utility function. We will develop two concepts of dominance that are weaker, thus more broadly applicable, than state-by-state dominance First Order Stochastic Dominance Consider two assets, X 1, X 2, with the following payoffs: Payoff State (s) Prob(s) X 1 X Clearly, all rational investors prefer X 2 : probability of exceeding it. it at least matches X 1 and has a positive To formalize this intuition, let F i (x) denote the cumulative distribution function of X i, that is, F i (x) = Prob[X i x]. Definition (1SD). F a (x) 1SD F b (x) F a (x) F b (x), x Plot the two distribution functions in the example and check that F 2 (x) F 1 (x), x. Note that if the distribution of X 2 is always below X 1, then the probability of X 2 exceeding a given payoff is always larger, that is, F 2 (x) F 1 (x) 1 F 2 (x) 1 F 1 (x) Prob[X 2 x] Prob[X 1 x], x The usefulness of this concept comes from the following theorem: Theorem F a (x) 1SD F b (x) E a [U(x)] E b [U(x)] for all nondecreasing U where E i is the expectation under the distribution of i, E i [U(x)] = U(x) df i (x) = U(x)fi (x) dx. Hence, all nonsatiable investors prefer asset X 2. Note that 1SD is not the same as state-by-state dominance. Danthine and Donaldson (2005). See exercise 4.8 in

19 2.6. Stochastic dominance Second Order Stochastic Dominance 1SD is still a very strong condition, thus not applicable to most situations. If we add the assumption of risk aversion, we get the much more useful concept of Second Order Stochastic Dominance (2SD). Consider the following investments: X 3 X 4 Payoff Prob Payoff Prob Plot the two distribution functions. Even though no investment 1SD the other, intuitively X 3 looks better. To make this precise: Definition (2SD). F a (x) 2SD F b (x) x F a(s) ds x F b(s) ds, x x [F b(s) F a (s)] ds 0, x That is, at any point the accumulated difference between F b and F a must be positive. Note that 1SD implies 2SD, but the converse is not true. In the plot of the previous example, this basically means that the area of the difference where F 3 > F 4 is small. To make this a bit more precise, we can compute the integrals at all relevant jump points. x x F 3 (x) 0 F x 3(s)ds F 4 (x) 0 F 4(s)ds x 0 F 4(s)ds x 0 F 3(s)ds / / /3 4/3 13/ /3 5/3 2/ / / The last columns shows that x [F 4(s) F 3 (s)] ds 0, x. (After x = 9, the difference between the two integrals will always be ) All risk averse investors will prefer X 3, as the following theorem shows. Theorem F a (x) 2SD F b (x) E a [U(x)] E b [U(x)] for all nondecreasing and concave U Note that risk aversion is enough, i.e., we do not have to assume a specific utility function.

20 2.7. Exercises 20 Mean preserving spread. The concept of 2SD is even more useful to understand the tradeoff between risk and return. Definition. Suppose there exists a random variable Z s.t. X b = X a +Z, with E[Z X a ] = 0 for all values of X a. Then, we say that X b is a mean preserving spread of X a. (Or F b or f b is a m.p.s. of F a or f a ). Note that X b has the same mean as X a, but it is more noisy, i.e., risky. Intuitively, all risk averse investors should prefer the payoff with less risk, X a. The following theorem justifies this intuition: Theorem Let F a (x) and F b (x) be two distribution functions with identical means. Then, F a (x) 2SD F b (x) F b is a mean preserving spread of F a Mean-Variance criterion. This popular investment criterion states that: (i) for two investments with the same mean, investors prefer the one with smaller variance; (ii) for two investments with the same variance, investors prefer the one with higher mean. We will discuss later the exact conditions for this criterion to be true. For now, note that theorem helps to explain part (i). 2.7 Exercises Ex. 1 (This is problem 3.1. in Danthine and Donaldson (2005)) Utility function. Under certainty, any increasing monotone transformation of a utility function is also a utility function representing the same preferences. Under uncertainty, we must restrict this statement to linear transformations if we are to keep the same preference representation. Check it with this example. Assume an initial utility function attributes the following values to 3 perspectives: B u(b) = 100 M u(m) = 10 P u(p) = 50 a. Check that with this initial utility function, the lottery L = (B, M, 0.50) P. b. The proposed transformations are f(x) = a + bx, a 0, b > 0 and g(x) = ln(x). Check that under f, L P, but that under g, P L.

21 2.7. Exercises 21 Ex. 2 (This is problem 3.3. in Danthine and Donaldson (2005)) Inter-temporal consumption. Consider a two-date economy and an agent with utility function over consumption: U(c) = c1 γ 1 γ, γ > 0 at each period. Define the inter-temporal utility function as V (c 1, c 2 ) = U(c 1 ) + U(c 2 ). Show that the agent will always prefer a smooth consumption stream to a more variable one with the same mean, that is, U( c) + U( c) > U(c 1 ) + U(c 2 ), if c = c 1 + c Start by showing that the utility function U is concave. 2. Then, show the required relation geometrically. 3. Finally, do the proof formally. Hint: use the following definition of a concave function. A function f : R N R 1 is concave if f(ax + (1 a)y) af(x) + (1 a)f(y), x, y R N and a [0, 1] Ex. 3 An agent with wealth = 100 is faced with the following game: with probability 1/2 his wealth will increase to 200; with probability 1/2 it will decrease to 0. Complete the following sentence: If the agent is a risk- he is willing to pay some money to play this game, whereas if he is risk- he is willing to pay some money to avoid the game. Ex. 4 The ARA and RRA measures have the first derivative of the utility function in the denominator. Why? Hint: read Danthine and Donaldson (2005) Ex. 5 Prove equation (2.2). Ex. 6 Ex. 7 Complete the table in section 2.4 and plot the utility functions. The CRRA utility function is usually presented as { ln(w ), γ = 1 U(W ) = W 1 γ /(1 γ), γ > 1 because ln(w ) is almost the limiting case as γ 1. More precisely, the true limit is lim γ 1 W 1 γ 1 1 γ = ln(w ). 1. Explain why U 1 (W ) = W 1 γ 1 γ preferences. and U 2 (W ) = W 1 γ 1 1 γ represent exactly the same

22 2.7. Exercises Prove that Hint: L Hôpital s rule. W 1 γ 1 lim = ln(w ) γ 1 1 γ Ex. 8 Consider the utility function U(Y ) = Y 2. What does it imply in terms of risk-taking behavior? Would it be economically reasonable to model an investor s behavior with this utility function? Ex. 9 An investor has an initial wealth of Y = 10. To play a game where he could win or loose 5% of his wealth, he demands π = 0.6, where π is the probability of the favorable outcome (winning 5%). Nonetheless, if his wealth were Y = 1000, he would still demand the same π = 0.6 to play the game. 1. What can you say about the risk characteristics of this investor? (One sentence answer). 2. Give an example of an utility function consistent with this behavior. Ex. 10 The risk-aversion characteristics of an investor can be described by two functions: ARA and RRA. 1. Give a very brief definition in words of these two measures. 2. What does it mean to say that an investor has increasing ARA? Does it make intuitive sense? Give an example of an utility function with this characteristic. 3. Give an example of an utility function with constant RRA (compute the actual coefficient of RRA). Ex. 11 An investor with initial wealth Y 0 = 100 is faced with the following lottery: win 20 with 0.3 probability; loose 20 with 0.7 probability. The utility function is U(W ) = ln(w ). What is the Certainty Equivalent of this lottery? What does this number mean? Ex. 12 Consider the following risky investment: Z = (100, 0, 0.5). The investor has log utility, U = ln(y ). 1. If the initial wealth is Y = 100, what is the certainty equivalent of the gamble? 2. If the initial wealth is Y = 1, what is the certainty equivalent of the gamble? 3. Explain in simple terms the change in CE. Ex. 13 Exercise 4.5 in Danthine and Donaldson (2005, p.354) Ex. 14 Exercise 4.7 in Danthine and Donaldson (2005, p.355). They meant to refer to table 4.2. Ex. 15 Exercise 4.8 in Danthine and Donaldson (2005, p.355). Be careful in distinguishing between states of nature and distributions defined over payoffs.

23 2.7. Exercises 23 Ex. 16 Consider two assets with returns r a N(0.1, 0.2) and r b N(0.1, 0.3). An investor has the utility function U(W ) = exp( γw ). Which asset does the investor prefer?

24 Chapter 3 Portfolio choice 1. The investor s typical problem is maximize a E[U(Y )] 2. It can be solved explicitly if we assume either: 1. Quadratic utility, or 2. CARA utility and normal returns. 3.1 Canonical portfolio problem This section analyzes the problem of an investor that must decide how much to invest in a risky asset. Consider the following notation 1 a amount (in $) to invest in a risky portfolio r uncertain rate of return on the risky portfolio r f risk-free (certain) rate of return Y 0 initial wealth Ỹ 1 terminal wealth = a(1 + r) + (Y 0 a)(1 + r f ) = Y 0 (1 + r f ) + a( r r f ) The investor s problem is maximize a E[U(Ỹ1)] (3.1) 1 Tildes denote random variables. We ll drop them when it is clear which variables are random. 24

25 3.1. Canonical portfolio problem 25 The (necessary) first order condition for a maximum is [ ] d du(.) foc: da E[U(Ỹ1)] = 0 E ( r r f ) = 0 dỹ1 and the (sufficient) second order condition is [ d 2 soc: da 2 E[U(Ỹ1)] < 0 E which is true if the investor is risk averse (U < 0). ] d 2 U(.) ( r r f ) 2 < 0 dỹ 2 1 Example Assume U = 11Y 5Y 2, with Y 0 = $1. Let r f = 0, E[r] = 0.1, Var[r] = Recall Var[x] = E[x 2 ] E[x] 2. Use the foc to get the optimal amount invested in the risky asset: foc:... a = $0.2 Use the soc to check that this is indeed a maximum: soc: The analysis of the optimality conditions produces the following important theorem: Theorem Let â denote the solution to problem (3.1) and assume the investor is nonsatiable (U > 0) and risk-averse (U < 0). Then â > 0 E[r] > r f â = 0 E[r] = r f â < 0 E[r] < r f

26 3.2. Analysis of the optimal portfolio choice 26 The theorem says that a risk-averse investor will only invest in the risky asset (stocks) if its expected return is higher than the risk-free rate. Conversely, if this is the case ( E[r] > r f ), then the investor will always participate in the stock market (even if with just a tiny amount of money). Example Suppose U(Y ) = ln(y ). For simplicity, assume the risky return is the simple lottery (r 2, r 1, π). Further assume r 2 > r f > r 1 (why?). The problem is thus maximize E[ln(Ỹ1)] a The foc is [ ] r r f E = 0 Y 0 (1 + r f ) + a(r r f ) or, given the two possible states, r 2 r f r 1 r f π + (1 π) Y 0 (1 + r f ) + a(r 2 r f ) Y 0 (1 + r f ) + a(r 1 r f ) = 0 which after some algebra is a = (1 + r f )( E[r] r f ) Y 0 (r 1 r f )(r 2 r f ) Check that the sign of the rhs depends on the sign of E[r] r f. In particular, if E[r] r f > 0, we get a/y 0 > 0, as in theorem Note also the following intuitive results: 1) The fraction of wealth invested in the risky asset (a/y 0 ) increases with the return premium ( E[r] r f ); 2) The fraction of wealth invested in the risky asset (a/y 0 ) decreases with the return dispersion around r f, ( (r 1 r f )(r 2 r f )). Lastly, note that the fraction of wealth invested in the risky asset (a/y 0 ) does not depend on the level of wealth (there is no Y 0 on the rhs). This result is specific to the CRRA utility function as described in a theorem below Analysis of the optimal portfolio choice Risk aversion We now relate the portfolio decision to the risk aversion of the investor. The follwoing theorem states, quite intuitively, that a more risk averse individual will invest less in the stock market: 2 See the numerical examples in Danthine and Donaldson (2005) for further interpretation.

27 3.2. Analysis of the optimal portfolio choice 27 Theorem Let â denote the solution to problem (3.1). Y > 0, ARA inv1 (Y ) > ARA inv2 (Y ) = â inv1 < â inv2 Furthermore, since ARA inv1 (Y ) > ARA inv2 (Y ) RRA inv1 (Y ) > RRA inv2 (Y ), we also have Y > 0, RRA inv1 (Y ) > RRA inv2 (Y ) = â inv1 < â inv2 Lets check this result: Example Assume r f = 0.05 and r = (r 2 = 0.4, r 1 = 0.2, 1/2). For U(Y ) = ln(y ), we can use the results in the last example to get â/y 0 = 0.6 Now consider the power utility function U(Y ) = Y 1 γ /(1 γ), with γ = 3. Note that it has both higher RRA (3 > 1) and ARA (3/Y > 1/Y ). Check (end-of-chapter exercise 18) that the optimal portfolio decision for this utility function is â/y 0 = Hence, this more risk-averse agent invests a smaller percentage of his wealth in the risky asset. The initial wealth (Y 0 ) is the same for both investors, so the money invested (â) is also smaller, as the theorem stated Wealth We now analyze the portfolio decision as the initial wealth changes. We might expect wealthier investors to put more money in the stock market. However, the result is not so simple; it depends on the characteristics of the specific utility function. Absolute Risk Aversion Theorem Let â = â(y 0 ) denote the solution to problem (3.1). Then, (Decreasing ARA) ARA (Y ) < 0 â (Y 0 ) > 0 (Constant ARA) ARA (Y ) = 0 â (Y 0 ) = 0 (Increasing ARA) ARA (Y ) > 0 â (Y 0 ) < 0

28 3.2. Analysis of the optimal portfolio choice 28 DARA. If the investor has decreasing absolute risk aversion (DARA), he is willing to put more money at risk as he becomes wealthier. Recall that power utility has DARA (ARA(Y ) = γ/y ). (Is this reasonable behavior?) CARA. The second case, constant absolute risk aversion (CARA) is also important because the exponential utility satisfies this condition. Recall that U(Y ) = exp( αy ) ARA(Y ) = α ARA (Y ) = 0 The theorem states that this investor will put the same amount of money in the risky asset regardless of how much wealth he has. (Is this a reasonable description of investors behavior?) Illustration: solving the problem for CARA Lets verify the CARA case of the theorem. The portfolio problem is with Y 1 = Y 0 (1 + r f ) + a(r r f ). The foc is maximize {E[ exp( αy 1 )]} (3.2) a E [α(r r f ) exp( αy 1 )] = 0 (3.3) which cannot be solved explicitly for a without further assumptions! To proceed, we consider two alternatives. 1. Implicit Function Theorem Even though we cannot explicitly solve the problem, we can still describe the optimal solution using a very useful trick in economics: the Implicity Function Theorem. 3 Intuitively, this theorem says the following. Suppose the (implicity) function y = y(x) is the solution to some equation, that is, f(x, y) = 0. More 3 Implicit Function Theorem. Consider the equation f(y, x 1,..., x m ) = 0 and the solution (ȳ, x 1,..., x m ). If f(ȳ, x)/ y 0, then there exists an implicit function y = y(x 1,..., x m ) that satisfies the equation for every (x 1,..., x m ) in the neighborhood of ( x 1,..., x m ), i.e., f(y(x 1,..., x m ), x 1,..., x m ) = 0. Furthermore, the partial derivatives are given by y( x 1,..., x m ) x i = f(ȳ, x 1,..., x m )/ x i f(ȳ, x 1,..., x m )/ y

29 3.2. Analysis of the optimal portfolio choice 29 precisely, as we change x, y(x) adjusts to keep f at 0, f(x, y) 0. We can thus conclude that f does not change, ie, its total differential is zero. Therefore, df(x, y) = 0 f f dx + x y dy = 0 dy dx = f/ x f/ y Going back to the maximization problem, â = â(y 0 ) is the implicit function that guarantees that the lhs of (3.3) is always zero. We can thus take the total differential of the foc and get dâ(y 0 ) = E[... ]/ Y 0 dy 0 E[... ]/ a =0 (foc) {}}{ = (1 + r f )α E[α(r r f )e αy 1 ] E[α 2 (r r f ) 2 e αy 1] }{{} >0 = 0 Hence, the amount invested in the risky asset does not change with the investor s wealth, as the theorem claimed. Furthermore, the implicit function theorem allowed us to check this without solving the maximization problem explicitly. 2. Normal returns To get an explicit closed-form solution to problem (3.2) we need an additional assumption. It is this assumption that justifies the wide use of exponential utility. Assume the return on the risky asset is normally distributed, r N(µ, σ 2 ). Then, next period s wealth is also normally distributed, Y 1 N(Y 0 (1 + r f ) + a(µ r f ), a 2 σ 2 ). Using the moment generating function for the normal distribution 4, we can simplify the portfolio problem: max a { ( {E[ exp( αy 1 )]} = max exp α[y0 (1 + r f ) + a(µ r f )] + 1/2α 2 a 2 σ 2)} a that is, the rhs does not have E[.]. We can thus solve the maximization problem and get a closed-form solution for a. Exercise 24 asks you to do these final steps. Check that the final expression for a does not depend on Y 0, as the theorem stated. To summarize, even though the exponential utility is not the best intuitive description of human behavior, it is very useful if we assume that returns are normally distributed. 4 If X N(m, s 2 ), then E [ e γx] = exp ( γm γ2 s 2), for any γ.

30 3.2. Analysis of the optimal portfolio choice 30 Relative Risk Aversion We can also characterize the optimal portfolio choice in terms of the relative risk aversion measure, RRA. Define ŵ â/y 0, the optimal proportion of wealth invested in the risky asset, or the optimal portfolio weight in the risky asset. Theorem Express the solution to problem (3.1) as a fraction of wealth, ŵ(y 0 ) â(y 0 )/Y 0. Then, (Decreasing RRA) RRA (Y ) < 0 ŵ (Y 0 ) > 0 (Constant RRA) RRA (Y ) = 0 ŵ (Y 0 ) = 0 (Increasing RRA) RRA (Y ) > 0 ŵ (Y 0 ) < 0 For example, if the investor has decreasing RRA, he will invest a higher proportion of wealth in the risk asset as he becomes wealthier. The most interesting case is perhaps the constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) case, as it characterizes the power and log utility functions. These investors always invest the same fraction of their wealth in the stock market, regardless of their initial wealth. 5 Example Consider U = ln(y ). Define w a/y 0, the fraction of wealth invested in the risky asset. The investor s problem is to maximize w E[ln(Y 1 )] with Y 1 = Y 0 (1 + r f ) + wy 0 (r r f ). Writing the foc and using the implicit function theorem, we can show that (end-of-chapter exercise 19) dŵ dy 0 = 0 That is, the optimal fraction does not change with wealth. 5 This theorem can also be expressed in terms of η dâ/â dy 0/Y 0, the wealth elasticity of the investment in the risky asset: (Decreasing RRA) RRA (Y ) < 0 η > 1 (Constant RRA) RRA (Y ) = 0 η = 1 (Increasing RRA) RRA (Y ) > 0 η < 1 To see that increasing ŵ(y 0 ) â(y 0 )/Y 0 is the same as η > 1, note d [ŵ(y 0 )] = d [â(y0 ] ) > 0 dâ 1 â/y0 2 > 0 dâ/ dy 0 > â/y 0 dâ/â > 1 dy 0 dy 0 Y 0 dy 0 Y 0 dy 0 /Y 0 and similarly for the other cases.

31 3.3. Canonical portfolio problem for N > Canonical portfolio problem for N > 1 Now we generalize the portfolio choice problem. There are N risky assets and 1 risk-free asset. Terminal wealth is The investor s problem is thus maximize {a 1,...,a N } E Ỹ 1 = Y 0 (1 + r f ) + [ U ( N a i ( r i r f ) i=1 Y 0 (1 + r f ) + )] N a i ( r i r f ) i=1 It will be convenient to choose weights instead of $ values. We thus define w i a i /Y 0 and write Y 1 = Y 0 (1 + r f ) + N i=1 w iy 0 ( r i r f ). The investor s problem can thus be rewritten as [ [ ])] N maximize E U (Y 0 (1 + r f ) + w i ( r i r f ) {w 1,...,w N } Define r p to be the return on the portfolio: r p := w f r f + i=1 N w i r i Imposing the constraint that the weights must add up to one, we have that ( ) N N N r p = 1 w i r f + w i r i = r f + w i ( r i r f ) i=1 i=1 i=1 Hence, the portfolio problem can also be written as i=1 maximize E [ U (Y 0(1 + r p ))] {w 1,...,w N } Unfortunately, this problem is hard to solve without some simplifying assumptions. 3.4 Exercises Ex. 17 State the investor s problem (expression 3.1) in words.

32 3.4. Exercises 32 Ex. 18 Check the results in example The final expression is in the book; you just need to do the intermediate calculations. Caution: the expression in the book is correct, but the number is not (at least I get a different answer: a/y = instead of 0.24). Ex. 19 Check the results in example 3.2.2, ie, do the intermediate computations. Ex. 20 Consider the standard portfolio choice between a risk-free asset and a risky stock. An investor with initial wealth $1000 makes an optimal choice to allocate $400 to the stock. We know that if the same investor had an initial wealth larger than $1000, he would allocate more than $400 to the stock. 1. This investor has (decreasing / constant / increasing) ARA. 2. Give an example of a utility function consistent with this behavior. Consider the utility function U(Y ) = e gy, where g is a constant param- Ex. 21 eter. 1. Compute the ARA and RRA coefficients. 2. Interpret in words the result obtained for ARA (relate it to a simple lottery and to the portfolio choice problem). Ex. 22 Consider the canonical portfolio choice problem with 1 risky asset (with random return r) and 1 risk-free asset (with return r f ). The investor chooses the amount of money (a) to invest in the risky asset. 1. Write the problem explicitly for an investor with U(Y ) = exp( αy ), where Y is the wealth. 2. If the risk-free rate increases, what should happen to the amount invested in the risky asset? Explain intuitively (5 lines). 3. Show it explicitly. Hint: compute da dr f and determine its sign. Ex. 23 There is a risk-free and a risky asset. The investor chooses the amount invested in the risky asset, a, to maximize a EU(Y 1 ), where Y 1 is next period s wealth. Assume a regular utility function (U > 0, U < 0). 1. In general, what can you say about the sign of da/dy 0? 2. Assume U(Y ) = e αy. Compute da/dy 0. Ex. 24 Consider the standard portfolio choice problem maximize E[ exp( γy 1 )] a where next-period s wealth is Y 1 = Y 0 (1 + r f ) + a(r r f ), and the return on the risky asset is normally distributed, r N(µ, σ 2 ). Compute the explicit optimal amount to

33 3.4. Exercises 33 invest in the risky asset (a). Hint. Use the following property of the normal distribution (called moment generating function): If X N(m, s 2 ), then E [ e γx] = exp ( γm γ2 s 2), for any γ. Ex. 25 Computing returns with dividends. Consider the following daily closing prices and dividends (D) for two stocks (in $): Stock A Stock B day t P t D t P t D t fri mon tue wed thu fri Note that when a stock pays dividends, the return should be computed as r t = Pt+Dt P t Compute daily returns for these two stocks. Compute also the weekly returns assuming that the dividends are reinvested in the stock. This is a standard assumption, so use the standard formula, 1+r 0,T = (1+r 0,1 )(1+r 1,2 )... (1+r T 1,T ). Note: this is usually called Holding Period Return in databases such as CRSP or DataStream. 2. Suppose you invested $4,000 in A and $6,000 in B in the beginning of the week. Compute the portfolio return over this week. (Use the weekly returns already computed and apply the standard formula for the portfolio return). 3. Since we assume that dividends are reinvested in the stock, we may end up with more shares than we started with. How many shares of each stock do you have at the beginning of the week? How many shares do you have at the end of the week? Note: to check that you have the right answer, compute the terminal value of the portfolio by doing V 5 = P A,5 N A,5 + P B,5 N B,5, where N is the number of shares that you got. It should imply the same weekly return as in the previous question. 4. Again, the way weekly returns were computed assumes that dividends are reinvested in the stock. Hence, while for the stock without dividends (A) we have r A,week = P 5 /P = 12/10 1 the same is no longer true for the dividend-paying stock (stock B) r B,week P 5 /P /10 1

34 3.4. Exercises 34 Hence, databases usually also show an adjusted price, P a, that can be used to compute returns without having to know the dividends. The true return from market closes plus dividends must equal the return with adjusted closes: P t + D t P t 1 1 = P t a Pt 1 a 1 Fix the last price P a 5 = P 5 = 12. Compute the adjusted prices for the previous days for both stocks. (Check my website for an exercise with data from finance.yahoo.com)

35 Chapter 4 Portfolio choice for Mean-Variance investors 1. Quadratic utility or Normal returns imply mean-variance preferences, E[U] = f(µ p, σ 2 p). 2. The optimal investment opportunities are described by the meanvariance frontier. 3. The investor s portfolio choice problem with N > 1 risky assets can be solved explicitly. These concepts were developed by Harry Markowitz in 1952 and they are still the benchmark for optimal portfolio allocation. 4.1 Mean-Variance preferences The general portfolio problem (N > 1) is hard to solve unless we make one of the simplifying assumptions below. Either one of these assumptions will lead to meanvariance preferences, that is, to investors that care only about the first two moments of Y 1 or r p. 1 Expand U(Ỹ1) around E(Ỹ1). To simplify the notation, let Y Y 1. U(Y ) = U( EY ) + U ( EY ) (Y EY ) + 1/2 U ( EY ) (Y EY ) 2 + remainder 1 Note that the two are related: E[Y 1 ] = Y 0 (1 + E[r p ]) and Var[Y 1 ] = Y 2 0 Var[r p ]. 35

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION Szabolcs Sebestyén szabolcs.sebestyen@iscte.pt Master in Finance INVESTMENTS Sebestyén (ISCTE-IUL) Choice Theory Investments 1 / 65 Outline 1 An Introduction

More information

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected utility and risk aversion 1/ 58 Introduction Expected utility is the standard framework for modeling investor choices. The following topics will be covered:

More information

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko ECON 581. Decision making under risk Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko 1 / 36 Outline Expected utility Risk aversion Certainty equivalence and risk premium The canonical portfolio allocation problem 2 / 36 Suggested

More information

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral.

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral. Risk aversion For those preference orderings which (i.e., for those individuals who) satisfy the seven axioms, define risk aversion. Compare a lottery Ỹ = L(a, b, π) (where a, b are fixed monetary outcomes)

More information

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions Shuoxun Hellen Zhang WISE & SOE XIAMEN UNIVERSITY March, 2015 1 / 50 Outline Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation Portfolios, Risk Aversion,

More information

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty Prof. Massimo Guidolin Prep Course in Quant Methods for Finance August-September 2017 Outline and objectives Axioms of choice under

More information

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice Prof. Massimo Guidolin Portfolio Management Spring 2017 Outline and objectives Choice under uncertainty: dominance o Guidolin-Pedio, chapter 1, sec. 2 Choice under

More information

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Pierre Chaigneau pierre.chaigneau@hec.ca June 14, 2011 Finance: the economics of risk and uncertainty In financial markets, claims associated with random future

More information

Characterization of the Optimum

Characterization of the Optimum ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 5. Portfolio Allocation with One Riskless, One Risky Asset Characterization of the Optimum Consider a risk-averse, expected-utility-maximizing

More information

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty We always need to make a decision (or select from among actions, options or moves) even when there exists

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty Chapter 7 Choice under Uncertainty 1. Expected Utility Theory. 2. Risk Aversion. 3. Applications: demand for insurance, portfolio choice 4. Violations of Expected Utility Theory. 7.1 Expected Utility Theory

More information

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions ; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions Prof. Massimo Guidolin Portfolio Management Spring 2016 Outline and objectives Utility functions The expected utility theorem and the axioms

More information

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk Preliminaries We treat, for convenience, money as a continuous variable when dealing with monetary outcomes. Strictly speaking, the derivation

More information

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty Introduction to Microeconomics Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty The Five Axioms of Choice Under Uncertainty We can use the axioms of preference to show how preferences can be mapped into measurable

More information

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Choice under risk and uncertainty Choice under risk and uncertainty Introduction Up until now, we have thought of the objects that our decision makers are choosing as being physical items However, we can also think of cases where the outcomes

More information

ECON 6022B Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions Fall 2011

ECON 6022B Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions Fall 2011 ECON 60B Problem Set Suggested Solutions Fall 0 September 7, 0 Optimal Consumption with A Linear Utility Function (Optional) Similar to the example in Lecture 3, the household lives for two periods and

More information

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1 ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1 Kjetil Storesletten Department of Economics University of Oslo 15 January 2018 Kjetil Storesletten, Dept. of Economics, UiO ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1 15 January

More information

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty Paulo Brito 1 pbrito@iseg.ulisboa.pt University of Lisbon March 9, 2018 Topics covered Contingent goods Comparing contingent goods Decision under

More information

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS 1 2 UTILITY ANALYSIS Motivating Example: Your total net worth = $400K = W 0. You own a home worth $250K. Probability of a fire each yr = 0.001. Insurance cost = $1K. Question:

More information

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria and Rational Expectations Equilibria 1 Basic Setup Two periods: 0 and 1 One riskless asset with interest rate r One risky asset which pays a normally distributed

More information

u (x) < 0. and if you believe in diminishing return of the wealth, then you would require

u (x) < 0. and if you believe in diminishing return of the wealth, then you would require Chapter 8 Markowitz Portfolio Theory 8.7 Investor Utility Functions People are always asked the question: would more money make you happier? The answer is usually yes. The next question is how much more

More information

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY LECTURE 5 MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY Choice under Uncertainty (MWG chapter 6, sections A-C, and Cowell chapter 8) Lecturer: Andreas Papandreou 1 Introduction p Contents n Expected utility theory

More information

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations Shuoxun Hellen Zhang WISE & SOE XIAMEN UNIVERSITY March, 2015 1 / 57 Questions to Answer How financial risk is defined and measured How an investor

More information

FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management

FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management Investment Funds Topic 1: Introduction Unit Trusts: investor s funds are pooled, usually into specific types of assets. o Investors are assigned tradeable

More information

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key 1. Exercises from MWG (Chapter 6): (a) Exercise 6.B.1 from MWG: Show that if the preferences % over L satisfy the independence axiom, then for all 2 (0; 1) and

More information

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class March 30, 2015 1. (20 points) An agent has Y 0 = 1 to invest. On the market two financial assets exist. The first one is riskless.

More information

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion Expected Utility And Risk Aversion Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 12, October 4 Outline 1 Risk Aversion 2 Certainty Equivalent 3 Risk Premium 4 Relative Risk Aversion 5 Stochastic Dominance Notation From

More information

Lecture 8: Asset pricing

Lecture 8: Asset pricing BURNABY SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY BRITISH COLUMBIA Paul Klein Office: WMC 3635 Phone: (778) 782-9391 Email: paul klein 2@sfu.ca URL: http://paulklein.ca/newsite/teaching/483.php Economics 483 Advanced Topics

More information

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing THE UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHAMPTON Paul Klein Office: Murray Building, 3005 Email: p.klein@soton.ac.uk URL: http://paulklein.se Economics 3010 Topics in Macroeconomics 3 Autumn 2010 Lecture 8: Introduction

More information

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance Risk preferences and stochastic dominance Pierre Chaigneau pierre.chaigneau@hec.ca September 5, 2011 Preferences and utility functions The expected utility criterion Future income of an agent: x. Random

More information

FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION. Lecture 5: Dynamic Programming and a Visit to the Soft Side

FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION. Lecture 5: Dynamic Programming and a Visit to the Soft Side FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION Lecture 5: Dynamic Programming and a Visit to the Soft Side Copyright c Philip H. Dybvig 2008 Dynamic Programming All situations in practice are more complex than the simple examples

More information

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models Jack Meyer Department of Economics Michigan State University East Lansing, MI 48824 jmeyer@msu.edu SCC-76: Economics and Management

More information

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract Linear risk tolerance and mean variance preferences Andreas Wagener University of Vienna Abstract We translate the property of linear risk tolerance (hyperbolical Arrow Pratt index of risk aversion) from

More information

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013 STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013 Model Structure EXPECTED UTILITY Preferences v(c 1, c 2 ) with all the usual properties Lifetime expected utility function

More information

E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space.

E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space. 1 E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space. A. Overview. c 2 1. With Certainty, objects of choice (c 1, c 2 ) 2. With

More information

Financial Mathematics III Theory summary

Financial Mathematics III Theory summary Financial Mathematics III Theory summary Table of Contents Lecture 1... 7 1. State the objective of modern portfolio theory... 7 2. Define the return of an asset... 7 3. How is expected return defined?...

More information

Topic 3 Utility theory and utility maximization for portfolio choices. 3.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion

Topic 3 Utility theory and utility maximization for portfolio choices. 3.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion MATH362 Fundamentals of Mathematics Finance Topic 3 Utility theory and utility maximization for portfolio choices 3.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion 3.2 Axiomatic approach

More information

Macroeconomics Sequence, Block I. Introduction to Consumption Asset Pricing

Macroeconomics Sequence, Block I. Introduction to Consumption Asset Pricing Macroeconomics Sequence, Block I Introduction to Consumption Asset Pricing Nicola Pavoni October 21, 2016 The Lucas Tree Model This is a general equilibrium model where instead of deriving properties of

More information

Period State of the world: n/a A B n/a A B Endowment ( income, output ) Y 0 Y1 A Y1 B Y0 Y1 A Y1. p A 1+r. 1 0 p B.

Period State of the world: n/a A B n/a A B Endowment ( income, output ) Y 0 Y1 A Y1 B Y0 Y1 A Y1. p A 1+r. 1 0 p B. ECONOMICS 7344, Spring 2 Bent E. Sørensen April 28, 2 NOTE. Obstfeld-Rogoff (OR). Simplified notation. Assume that agents (initially we will consider just one) live for 2 periods in an economy with uncertainty

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY PART ± I CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 Foundations of Finance I: Expected Utility Theory Foundations of Finance II: Asset Pricing, Market Efficiency,

More information

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations Prof. Massimo Guidolin 20135 Theory of Finance, Part I (Sept. October) Fall 2014 Outline and objectives The backward, three-step solution

More information

ECON Financial Economics

ECON Financial Economics ECON 8 - Financial Economics Michael Bar August, 0 San Francisco State University, department of economics. ii Contents Decision Theory under Uncertainty. Introduction.....................................

More information

PORTFOLIO THEORY. Master in Finance INVESTMENTS. Szabolcs Sebestyén

PORTFOLIO THEORY. Master in Finance INVESTMENTS. Szabolcs Sebestyén PORTFOLIO THEORY Szabolcs Sebestyén szabolcs.sebestyen@iscte.pt Master in Finance INVESTMENTS Sebestyén (ISCTE-IUL) Portfolio Theory Investments 1 / 60 Outline 1 Modern Portfolio Theory Introduction Mean-Variance

More information

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Jin Yong Jung We analyze how the wealth of an agent and its distribution affect the profit of the principal by considering the simple

More information

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude Duan LI Department of Systems Engineering & Engineering Management The Chinese University of Hong Kong http://www.se.cuhk.edu.hk/

More information

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions, Modern Portfolio Theory

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions, Modern Portfolio Theory Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions, Modern Portfolio Theory Shuoxun Hellen Zhang WISE & SOE XIAMEN UNIVERSITY April, 2015 1 / 95 Outline Modern portfolio theory The backward induction,

More information

AMS Portfolio Theory and Capital Markets

AMS Portfolio Theory and Capital Markets AMS 69.0 - Portfolio Theory and Capital Markets I Class 5 - Utility and Pricing Theory Robert J. Frey Research Professor Stony Brook University, Applied Mathematics and Statistics frey@ams.sunysb.edu This

More information

Investment and Portfolio Management. Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds

Investment and Portfolio Management. Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds Types of managed funds: Unit trusts Investors funds are pooled, usually into specific types of assets Investors are assigned

More information

Topic Four Utility optimization and stochastic dominance for investment decisions. 4.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion

Topic Four Utility optimization and stochastic dominance for investment decisions. 4.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion MATH4512 Fundamentals of Mathematical Finance Topic Four Utility optimization and stochastic dominance for investment decisions 4.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion 4.2 Axiomatic

More information

SAC 304: Financial Mathematics II

SAC 304: Financial Mathematics II SAC 304: Financial Mathematics II Portfolio theory, Risk and Return,Investment risk, CAPM Philip Ngare, Ph.D April 25, 2013 P. Ngare (University Of Nairobi) SAC 304: Financial Mathematics II April 25,

More information

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I) Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16 (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I) Dealing with Uncertainty 2 Preferences over risky choices (Section 7.1) One simple model: Expected Utility How can old tools be applied to analyze

More information

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models IEOR E4707: Foundations of Financial Engineering c 206 by Martin Haugh Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models These notes develop the theory of martingale pricing in a discrete-time,

More information

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance University of Exeter Recap Last class we looked at the axioms of expected utility, which defined a rational agent as proposed by von Neumann and Morgenstern. We then proceeded to look at empirical evidence

More information

Consumption- Savings, Portfolio Choice, and Asset Pricing

Consumption- Savings, Portfolio Choice, and Asset Pricing Finance 400 A. Penati - G. Pennacchi Consumption- Savings, Portfolio Choice, and Asset Pricing I. The Consumption - Portfolio Choice Problem We have studied the portfolio choice problem of an individual

More information

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty 1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty 1.1 Modelling uncertainty As in the deterministic case, we keep assuming that agents live for two periods. The novelty here is that their earnings in the second

More information

CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL JANUARY 19, 2018

CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL JANUARY 19, 2018 CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL JANUARY 19, 018 Stochastic Consumption-Savings Model APPLICATIONS Use (solution to) stochastic two-period model to illustrate some basic results and ideas in Consumption research

More information

1. Expected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance

1. Expected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance . Epected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance. Epected utility.. Description o risky alternatives.. Preerences over lotteries..3 The epected utility theorem. Monetary lotteries and risk aversion..

More information

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion.

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion. IDEA Economics of Risk and Uncertainty List of Exercises Expected Utility, Risk Aversion, and Stochastic Dominance. 1. Prove that, for every pair of Bernouilli utility functions, u 1 ( ) and u 2 ( ), and

More information

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E. Microeconomic Theory -1- Uncertainty Choice under uncertainty A Introduction to choice under uncertainty B Risk aversion 11 C Favorable gambles 15 D Measures of risk aversion 0 E Insurance 6 F Small favorable

More information

B. Online Appendix. where ɛ may be arbitrarily chosen to satisfy 0 < ɛ < s 1 and s 1 is defined in (B1). This can be rewritten as

B. Online Appendix. where ɛ may be arbitrarily chosen to satisfy 0 < ɛ < s 1 and s 1 is defined in (B1). This can be rewritten as B Online Appendix B1 Constructing examples with nonmonotonic adoption policies Assume c > 0 and the utility function u(w) is increasing and approaches as w approaches 0 Suppose we have a prior distribution

More information

ECMC49F Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Oct 26, 2005 Duration: 1 hour 50 mins Total Marks: 100. [1] [25 marks] Decision-making under certainty

ECMC49F Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Oct 26, 2005 Duration: 1 hour 50 mins Total Marks: 100. [1] [25 marks] Decision-making under certainty ECMC49F Midterm Instructor: Travis NG Date: Oct 26, 2005 Duration: 1 hour 50 mins Total Marks: 100 [1] [25 marks] Decision-making under certainty (a) [5 marks] Graphically demonstrate the Fisher Separation

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Theory

Advanced Microeconomic Theory Advanced Microeconomic Theory Lecture Notes Sérgio O. Parreiras Fall, 2016 Outline Mathematical Toolbox Decision Theory Partial Equilibrium Search Intertemporal Consumption General Equilibrium Financial

More information

Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1

Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1 Session 9: The expected utility framework Susan Thomas http://www.igidr.ac.in/ susant susant@mayin.org IGIDR Bombay Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1 Questions How do humans make decisions

More information

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. FINC3023 Behavioral Finance TOPIC 1: Expected Utility Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. A normative theory based on rational utility maximizers

More information

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS SEPTEMBER 13, 2010 BASICS. Introduction

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS SEPTEMBER 13, 2010 BASICS. Introduction STOCASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODE: CANONICA APPICATIONS SEPTEMBER 3, 00 Introduction BASICS Consumption-Savings Framework So far only a deterministic analysis now introduce uncertainty Still an application

More information

Mathematics of Finance Final Preparation December 19. To be thoroughly prepared for the final exam, you should

Mathematics of Finance Final Preparation December 19. To be thoroughly prepared for the final exam, you should Mathematics of Finance Final Preparation December 19 To be thoroughly prepared for the final exam, you should 1. know how to do the homework problems. 2. be able to provide (correct and complete!) definitions

More information

ECON Micro Foundations

ECON Micro Foundations ECON 302 - Micro Foundations Michael Bar September 13, 2016 Contents 1 Consumer s Choice 2 1.1 Preferences.................................... 2 1.2 Budget Constraint................................ 3

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives CHAPTER Duxbury Thomson Learning Making Hard Decision Third Edition RISK ATTITUDES A. J. Clark School of Engineering Department of Civil and Environmental Engineering 13 FALL 2003 By Dr. Ibrahim. Assakkaf

More information

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty Economics 101 Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty 1 Intertemporal Setting Consider a consumer who lives for two periods, say old and young. When he is young, he has income m 1, while when

More information

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II EconS 50 - Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II. Exercise 6.E.: The purpose of this exercise is to show that preferences may not be transitive in the presence of regret. Let there be S states

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 The Consumer Problem Consider an agent choosing her consumption of goods 1 and 2 for a given budget. This is the workhorse of microeconomic theory. (Notice

More information

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck! Name Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck! 1) For each of the following statements, state whether it is true or false. If it is true, prove that it is true.

More information

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS 247 16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS Let us associate each state S with a numeric utility U(S), which expresses the desirability of the state A nondeterministic action A will have possible outcome states Result

More information

Financial Economics Field Exam January 2008

Financial Economics Field Exam January 2008 Financial Economics Field Exam January 2008 There are two questions on the exam, representing Asset Pricing (236D = 234A) and Corporate Finance (234C). Please answer both questions to the best of your

More information

Analytical Problem Set

Analytical Problem Set Analytical Problem Set Unless otherwise stated, any coupon payments, cash dividends, or other cash payouts delivered by a security in the following problems should be assume to be distributed at the end

More information

Lecture 2 General Equilibrium Models: Finite Period Economies

Lecture 2 General Equilibrium Models: Finite Period Economies Lecture 2 General Equilibrium Models: Finite Period Economies Introduction In macroeconomics, we study the behavior of economy-wide aggregates e.g. GDP, savings, investment, employment and so on - and

More information

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers. Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel)

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers. Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel) All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel) First Name: Waterloo, April 2013. Last Name: UW ID #:

More information

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2013 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Mock Examination 2010

Mock Examination 2010 [EC7086] Mock Examination 2010 No. of Pages: [7] No. of Questions: [6] Subject [Economics] Title of Paper [EC7086: Microeconomic Theory] Time Allowed [Two (2) hours] Instructions to candidates Please answer

More information

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Uncertainty in Equilibrium Uncertainty in Equilibrium Larry Blume May 1, 2007 1 Introduction The state-preference approach to uncertainty of Kenneth J. Arrow (1953) and Gérard Debreu (1959) lends itself rather easily to Walrasian

More information

Problem set 5. Asset pricing. Markus Roth. Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz. Juli 5, 2010

Problem set 5. Asset pricing. Markus Roth. Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz. Juli 5, 2010 Problem set 5 Asset pricing Markus Roth Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz Juli 5, 200 Markus Roth (Macroeconomics 2) Problem set 5 Juli 5, 200 / 40 Contents Problem 5 of problem

More information

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery? ECON4260 Behavioral Economics 2 nd lecture Cumulative Prospect Theory Expected utility This is a theory for ranking lotteries Can be seen as normative: This is how I wish my preferences looked like Or

More information

Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics. Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle

Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics. Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring 2006 Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle 1 Overview This lecture derives the consumption-based capital asset pricing

More information

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the open text license amendment to version 2 of the GNU General

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 9, 2015 Review of Last Week Consumer choice problem General equilibrium Contingent claims Risk aversion The optimal choice, x = (X, Y ), is

More information

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS 4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS Marek Rutkowski School of Mathematics and Statistics University of Sydney Semester 2, 2016 M. Rutkowski (USydney) Slides 4: Single-Period Market Models 1 / 87 General Single-Period

More information

Transactions with Hidden Action: Part 1. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Transactions with Hidden Action: Part 1. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Transactions with Hidden Action: Part 1 Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Transactions with hidden action A risk-neutral principal (P) delegates performance of a task to an agent (A) Key features

More information

Review Session. Prof. Manuela Pedio Theory of Finance

Review Session. Prof. Manuela Pedio Theory of Finance Review Session Prof. Manuela Pedio 20135 Theory of Finance 12 October 2018 Three most common utility functions (1/3) We typically assume that investors are non satiated (they always prefer more to less)

More information

1.12 Exercises EXERCISES Use integration by parts to compute. ln(x) dx. 2. Compute 1 x ln(x) dx. Hint: Use the substitution u = ln(x).

1.12 Exercises EXERCISES Use integration by parts to compute. ln(x) dx. 2. Compute 1 x ln(x) dx. Hint: Use the substitution u = ln(x). 2 EXERCISES 27 2 Exercises Use integration by parts to compute lnx) dx 2 Compute x lnx) dx Hint: Use the substitution u = lnx) 3 Show that tan x) =/cos x) 2 and conclude that dx = arctanx) + C +x2 Note:

More information

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel) AFFI, Lyon, May 2013. Carole Bernard All Investors are

More information

Slides III - Complete Markets

Slides III - Complete Markets Slides III - Complete Markets Julio Garín University of Georgia Macroeconomic Theory II (Ph.D.) Spring 2017 Macroeconomic Theory II Slides III - Complete Markets Spring 2017 1 / 33 Outline 1. Risk, Uncertainty,

More information

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Consumption and Asset Pricing Consumption and Asset Pricing Yin-Chi Wang The Chinese University of Hong Kong November, 2012 References: Williamson s lecture notes (2006) ch5 and ch 6 Further references: Stochastic dynamic programming:

More information

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies Harris Schlesinger Department of Finance, University of Alabama, USA Center of Finance & Econometrics, University of Konstanz, Germany E-mail: hschlesi@cba.ua.edu

More information

Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes

Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes A Simple Martingale Method Approach Frank Thomas Seifried University of Kaiserslautern March 20, 2009 F. Seifried (Kaiserslautern) Deferred Capital

More information

NOTES ON ATTITUDE TOWARD RISK TAKING AND THE EXPONENTIAL UTILITY FUNCTION. Craig W. Kirkwood

NOTES ON ATTITUDE TOWARD RISK TAKING AND THE EXPONENTIAL UTILITY FUNCTION. Craig W. Kirkwood NOTES ON ATTITUDE TOWARD RISK TAKING AND THE EXPONENTIAL UTILITY FUNCTION Craig W Kirkwood Department of Management Arizona State University Tempe, AZ 85287-4006 September 1991 Corrected April 1993 Reissued

More information

AMH4 - ADVANCED OPTION PRICING. Contents

AMH4 - ADVANCED OPTION PRICING. Contents AMH4 - ADVANCED OPTION PRICING ANDREW TULLOCH Contents 1. Theory of Option Pricing 2 2. Black-Scholes PDE Method 4 3. Martingale method 4 4. Monte Carlo methods 5 4.1. Method of antithetic variances 5

More information

MACROECONOMICS. Prelim Exam

MACROECONOMICS. Prelim Exam MACROECONOMICS Prelim Exam Austin, June 1, 2012 Instructions This is a closed book exam. If you get stuck in one section move to the next one. Do not waste time on sections that you find hard to solve.

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information