1 Preferences. Completeness: x, y X, either x y or y x. Transitivity: x, y, z X, if x y and y z, then x z.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "1 Preferences. Completeness: x, y X, either x y or y x. Transitivity: x, y, z X, if x y and y z, then x z."

Transcription

1 1 Preferences We start with a consumption set X and model people s tastes with preference relation. For most of the class, we will assume that X = R L +. The preference relation may or may not satisfy the following properties. Completeness: x, y X, either x y or y x. Transitivity: x, y, z X, if x y and y z, then x z. Reasons for violation include framing effects, social choice, just-perceptible differences Monotonicity More of everything is better Strong monotonicity More of something is better Local non-satiation Continuity Convexity: y x, z x αy + (1 α)z x Strict convexity: y x, z x αy + (1 α)z x We also define x y x y but not y x. : x y x y and y x. If satisfies completeness and transitivity, we say that it is rational. Show that if is rational, then is transitive and irreflexive (there is no x such that x x). 1

2 is transitive, reflexive (x x), and symmetric (x y means y x) This shows that our explicit assumptions imply some other, implicit ones. For another exercise, show that is is strongly monotone, then it is monotone. Show also that if is monotone, then it is locally nonsatiated. Thus, strong monotonicity implies monotonicity implies local nonsatiation. Strong monotonicity is the strongest assumption; monotonicity is weaker one; and local nonsatiation is the weakest one. (E.g., tall fat man implies tall man implies man. Tall fat man puts the most restrictions on our individual and is therefore the strongest assumption.) 1.1 Examples of Preferences Leontief, perfect substitutes, log, etc. 1.2 Utility representation Ultimately, we want to model our preferences with utility function. Definition 1. u : X R represents if x y u(x) u(y). The following proposition shows that not all preferences can be modeled: Proposition 1. If has a utility representation, then it is rational. Question: do rational preferences always have a utility representation? No! Lexicographic preferences are a counterexample. Theorem 1. If is rational and continuous, then it is represented by a continuous utility function. There is an easy proof for the case where is also monotone. Exercise: show that lexicographic preferences are not continuous. 2

3 2 Revealed Preference Economists model behavior as constrained optimization. Question: what restrictions does this put on choice? Typically, we observe (chosen) consumption bundles together with (vectors of) prices. Let s say we are given observations (x 1, p 1 ),..., (x T, p T ). Definition 2. u rationalizes these observations if u(x t ) u(x) for every x R L + such that p t x t p t x. If the preferences (x 1, p 1 ),..., (x T, p T ) are rationalized by a locally nonsatiated utility function, then the following must hold: 1. The consumer s income at time t is p t x t. 2. u(x t ) u(x) for every x R L + such that p t x t p t x. 3. u(x t ) > u(x) for every x R L + such that p t x t > p t x. (2) and (3) imply that if p t x s p t x t then p s x t p s x s. The property in red is called the Generalized Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference (GWARP). Choices must satisfy it in order to be rationalizable. Is GWARP sufficient for rationalizability? No! Write x t Rx if p t x t p t x and x t Rx if p t x t > p t x. We can now restate GWARP as x t Rx s not x s P x t. Utility representation requires that for any subset of observations {t 1, t 2,..., t n }, x t1 Rx t2, x t2 Rx t3,..., x tn 1 Rx tn not x tn P x t1. This is called the Generalized Axiom of Revealed Preference (GARP). These axioms are generalizations of the following: WARP: x t Rx s and x t x s not x s Rx t. 3

4 SARP: x t1 Rx t2, x t2 Rx t3,..., x tn 1 Rx tn and x t1 x tn not x tn Rx t1. For an exercise, show that WARP implies GWARP and SARP implies GARP. 2.1 Andreoni and Miller Basic idea: individuals exhibit social preferences. Can these preferences be explained by a reasonable utility function? Experimental design: π s +p π o = m. Money allocated to self and other with different budget sets. Divide 60 tokens, hold X at 1 point each, pass Y at 2 points each. Points converted to dollars. Several treatments (see Table 1). 176 subjects, 18 violated one more of the revealed preference axioms. 43% of subjects behaviors could be explained by one of the following three preferences: Leontief (50,50), selfish, perfect substitutes. 3 Demand Theory The utility maximization problem (UMP) is given by s.t. max x u(x) px w x 0 The problem above has a solution if p >> 0 and u is continuous. We denote the solution by x(p, w). It s called the Walrasian Demand Correspondence. Walrasian demand has the following properties: x(αp, αw) = x(p, w) for all α > 0 4

5 px = w for all x x(p, w) If u represents preferences that are convex, then x(p, w) is a convex set. If there preferences are strictly convex, then x(p, w) is a singleton. The UMP can be characterized by its first order conditions (FOCs). 3.1 Kuhn-Tucker Conditions Consider the problem max f(x) x R N s.t. g 1 (x) = b 1... g M (x) = b M h 1 (x) c 1... h K (x) c M Theorem: if x is a local maximum satisfying the constrains then there are multipliers λ m R, one for each equality constraint, and λ k R, one for each inequality constraint, such that: 1. f(x ) x n = M λ m g m(x ) x n + K λ k h k (x ) x n for all n 2. λ k (h k (x ) c k ) = 0 for all k In words, the second condition says that λ k = 0 for each inequality constraint that does not bind. Sometimes, the conditions above are stayed in terms of a Lagrangian function. Define L(x, λ) = f(x) M λ m ( b m g m (x)) K λ K ( c k h k (x)). Then, (1) is equivalent to L(x,λ) x n = 0 for all n. 5

6 It is common for one of the constraints to take the form of x l 0. In this case, the FOC for x l changes to L(x,λ) x n 0 (show this). Example: maximize f(x, y) = xy subject to x + y 2 2 and x, y FOCs for UMP If u is continuously differentiable, then u(x ) x l λp l (= if x l > 0). If the solution is interior, then u l (x ) u k (x ) = p l p k. This is the familiar condition that the ratio of prices is equal to the Marginal Rate of Substitution (MRS). In the UMP, λ has a nice interpretation: this is the marginal utility obtained from relaxing the budget constraint a little bit. For an exercise, show that u(x ) w = λ. Another exercise: Solve the utility maximization problem for u(x 1, x 2 ) = x α 1 x 1 α Indirect Utility We will find it useful to work with the indirect utility function given by v(p, w) = u(x(p, w)). Suppose preferences are l.n.s. and u is continuous. Then the indirect utility function has the following properties: Homogeneity of degree 0 Strictly increasing in w and non-increasing in p l for any l Continuous in p and w Properties (1) and (2) are easy to verify. Do it! 6

7 3.4 Expenditure Minimization The expenditure minimization problem (EMP) is given by min x 0 px s.t. u(x) u Theorem: Suppose u is a continuous function representing l.n.s. preference on R L + and p >> 0. Then 1. If x is optimal for UMP, then it is optimal for EMP with u = v(x ). Moreover, px = w. 2. If x is optimal for EMP, then it is optimal for UMP with w = x p. Moreover, the maximized utility is given by u. The solution to the EMP, denoted as h(p, u) is the Hicksian Demand Correspondence. The function e(p, u) = ph(p, u) is called the Expenditure Function. These objects have the following properties: h is homogenous of degree 0 in prices e is homogenous of degree 1 in prices e is a concave function of prices If e id differentiable at (p, u) and h is single valued then D p e(p, u) = h(p, u). 3.5 Slutsky It can be shown that h l (p, u) p k = x l(p, w) p k + x l(p, w) w x l(p, w) or equivalently x l (p, w) p k = h l(p, u) p k x l(p, w) w x l(p, w) 7

8 4 Uncertainty So far, we have considered a world without uncertainty. Now, let X = {x 1,..., x N } denote a set if uncertain outcomes. A lottery (p 1,..., p N ) with p n 0 for all n and n p n = 1 is an assignment of probabilities to outcomes. Given simple lotteries (p 1,..., p K ), a compound lottery (L 1,..., L K ; α 1,..., α K ) with α k 0 for all k and k α k = 1 yields lottery L k with probability α k. We are interested utility representations for preferences over the space of lotteries L. The preference relation on the space of lotteries is continuous if L, L, L L, the sets {α [0, 1] : αl + (1 α)l L } and {α [0, 1] : αl + (1 α)l L } are closed. Note: a set A is closed if and only if for every sequence x n x with x n A for every n, x A. Proposition: If is continuous, there exists a utility representation for. 4.1 Independence satisfies independence if for all L, L, L L and α (0, 1) we have L L αl + (1 α)l αl + (1 α)l Exercise: show that if satisfy independence, then for all L, L, L L and α (0, 1), L L αl + (1 α)l αl + (1 α)l 8

9 4.2 Expected Utility A utility function U : L R has an expected utility form if there is an assignment of numbers {u 1,..., u N } such that every simple lottery U(L) = p 1 u p N u N. A utility function U with an expected utility form is called a von Neumann-Morgenstern (vnm) expected utility function. Proposition: U : L R has an expected utility form if and only if it is linear. Proposition: Suppose U : L R is a vnm utility representing. Then Ũ : L R is another vnm utility representing if and only if β > 0 and γ such that Ũ = βu + γ. Exercise: Show that if α is represented by a vnm utility function, then is continuous and satisfies the independence axiom. Theorem (Expected Utility Theorem): If satisfies continuity and independence, then it is represented by a vnm utility function. 4.3 Risk Aversion We now denote money by a random variable x with F ( x) = P rob(x x). This generalizes the analysis so far. E.g., consider a lottery with three outcomes P (x = 1) = 1, P (x = 4) = 1, P (x = 6) = 1. Then, if x < 1 1 if x [0, 4) 4 F (x) = 3 if x [4, 6) 4 1 if x 6 Expected utility is defined as U(F ) = u(x)df (x), where u is the Bernoulli utility, as before. We can now define risk aversion. An individual is risk averse if E(u(x)) u(e(x)). 9

10 An individual is strictly risk averse if E(u(x)) < u(e(x)) for all non-degenerate F. An individual is risk neutral if E(u(x)) = u(e(x)). Risk aversion is equivalent to concavity of the Bernoulli utility function u( ). This is intuitive. Decreasing marginal utility a gain of 1 is worse than a loss of 1, so a bet that gives a gain of 1 and a loss of 1 with equal probability is not worth taking. Commonly used u(x) s include: Linear: u(x) = x Constant absolute risk aversion (CARA): u(x) = e αx for α > 0 Quadratic: u(x) = (α x) 2 for x < α Constant relative risk aversion (CRRA): u(x) = x1 γ 1 γ for γ > 0 One useful concept for studying risk aversion is the certainty equivalent, denoted c(f, u). This is amount of money that gives the agent the same utility as the gamble F : u(c(f, u)) = u(x)df (x) all F. For an exercise, show that if an agent is risk averse, then c(f, u) xdf (x) for Another useful concept is the probability premium. If a agent is offered a gamble that gives ɛ and ɛ > 0 with some probabilities, the probability premium π(w, ɛ, u) is the amount by which the probability of winning must be larger for the agent to be indifferent between the gamble and a certain outcome w: u(w) = ( π(w, ɛ, u)) u(w + ɛ) + ( 1 2 π(w, ɛ, u)) u(w ɛ) w, ɛ. For an exercise, show that if the agent is risk averse then π(w, ɛ, u) 0 for all 10

11 4.4 Arrow-Pratt We can use the following measures to compare risk aversion of different utility functions: The Arrow-Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion A(x) = u (x) u(x) The Arrow-Pratt measure of relative risk aversion R(x) = u (x) u(x) x Exercise: Let u 1 and u 2 be two utility functions. Show that A 1 (x) A 2 (x) for every value of x if and only if there exists and increasing concave function ψ such that u 2 (x) = ψ(u 1 (x)) at all x. I.e., u 2 is more concave than u Insurance We can use the concepts above to study insurance. Let an agent start with an asset level w. There is a probability π of a loss D. The agent can purchase insurance at price q. If the agent buys α units of insurance, then his payoff is w αq with probability 1 π w αq D + α with probability π This means his expected wealth is w πd + α(π q). Imagine that the price of insurance is acturially fair, which means q = π. Then the expected wealth of the agent is w πd no matter how much insurance he buys. He therefore sets α = D to reach this amount with certainty. I.e., the agent insures himself fully. 11

12 4.6 Asset Selection Consider the problem of buying a portfolio of assets (α 1,..., α N ) with returns (z 1,..., z N ). The utility of holding the portfolio of assets is U(α 1,..., α N ) = u(α 1 z α N z N )df (z 1,..., z N ). If these assets have prices (p 1,..., p N ), we can use what we learned about utility maximization to study demand of these assets, use revealed preference theory to see if such a utility function can explain the observations, etc. 12

13 5 Paradoxes We consider two paradoxes to illustrate some difficulties in applying expected utility theorem 5.1 Newcomb s Paradox This paradox shows that sometimes states should be defined as functions from actions to outcomes. I.e., assuming that your choice has no effect on the state can be a mistake. It starts with the following problem: There are two boxes. A clear box, which has 1000 dollars, and an opaque box, which may have dollars and may have nothing. You are asked to choose between both boxes and the opaque box only. There is a caveat: you observed 1000 people choose before you. 500 choose both boxes and found the opaque box empty. 500 chose the opaque box and they are now millionaires. Expected utility predicts that you should choose both boxes, since regardless of the state (there is money in the opaque box, there is no money in the opaque box), you are better off. This ignores the apparent relationship between states and actions. Construct a state space as follows: {(1, 1), (1, 0), (0, 1), (0, 0)}. The numbers are 1=the money is there, 0=the money is not. The first number is what happens if you re greedy, and the second number is what happens if you re modest. Now, there is no apparent dominance. (1,1) (1,0) (0,1) (0,0) Greedy Modest In some states it s better to be greedy, and in some states better to be modest. 13

14 5.2 Monty Hall This paradox shows that the way in which information is attained sometimes matters. In this case, the state space should reflect how information is attained. In this problem, you are at a game show. There are three doors: A, B, and C. Two doors contain a goat and one door contains a car. The probability of the prize being behind each of the doors is 1. You get to choose a door, then the host opens 3 one of the doors with a goat. Assume you choose door A and the host opened door B (which contains a goat). Do you change your decision or not? The answer is: yes, you should change your decision. This is because the host s decision contains information. Intuitively, modify the problem in the following way. There are 100 doors, one with a prize. You choose a door. Then the host opens 98 doors with goats. Do you change your mind now or not? The problem with the usual way of thinking about the problem is that you think of the state space as where the prize is. To think about it correctly, the state is (a) where the prize is and (b) what door the host opened. Assume that you chose door A. Then the probability of the prize being behind each of the doors for every state can be illustrated in the following matrix: OA OB OC A B C The 0 s on the diagonal reflect that the host doesn t open the door with a prize. The 0 s in the first column reflect that the door will not open the door you chose (door A). Since the unconditional probability of the prize being behind each of the doors is 1, this leaves us no choice in the bottom two rows. Conditional on the prize 3 beind in A, it is equally likely that the host opens door B and door C. It is easy to calculate that P (A OB) = 1 and P (C OB) = 2. Thus, if the host opens door B, you 3 3 should switch. 14

15 6 Prospect Theory Preference for Certainty Consider the following pair of choices. Problem 1 : Choose between (A) 2500 with probability 0.33, 2400 with probability 0.66, 0 with probability 0.01 (B) 2400 with certainty. Problem 2 : Choose between (C) 2500 with probability 0.33, 0 with probability 0.67 (D) 2400 with probability 0.34, 0 with probability 0.66 Typically, subjects choose B in Problem 1 and C in Problem 2. This is called Allais paradox because it is a violation of expected utility. Here is another problem: Problem 1 : Choose between (A) 50% chance of winning a 3 week tour of England, France, and Italy (B) A one week tour of England with certainty. Problem 2 : Choose between (C) 5% chance of winning a 3 week tour of England, France, and Italy (D) 10% chance of winning a one week tour of England And another: Problem 1 : Choose between (A) 45% chance of winning 6000, and 65% chance of winning nothing (B) 90% chance of winning 3000, and 10% chance of winning nothing Problem 2 : Choose between (C) 0.1% chance of winning 6000 and 99.9% chance of winning nothing (D) 0.2% chance of winning 3000 and 99.8% chance of winning nothing 15

16 In the latter two problems, people usually chose B in the first choice and C in the second, which also violated expected utility. Kahneman and Tversky (1979) considered all three of these violations to be a generalization of the same phenomenon: If (y, pq) is equivalent to (x, p), then (y, pqr) is preferred to (x, pr). The Reflection Effect Kahneman and Tversky (1979) observed that risk aversion in the domain of gains is accompanied by risk seeking in the domain of losses. For example, the majority of subjects accept a risk of 80% of losing 4000 in preference to a sure loss of 3000 although the gamble has lower expected value. Moreover, just like in the positive domain, outcomes with are obtain with certainty are overweighed relative to uncertain outcomes. For example, consider the following pair of problems. Problem 1 : Choose between (A) 45% chance of losing 6000, and 65% chance of losing nothing (B) 90% chance of losing 3000, and 10% chance of losing nothing Problem 2 : Choose between (C) 0.1% chance of losing 6000 and 99.9% chance of losing nothing (D) 0.2% chance of losing 3000 and 99.8% chance of losing nothing Subjects typically choose A in problem 1 and D in problem 2. Note that this violates expected utility! This violation can be explained by the following principle: If ( y, pq) is equivalent to ( x, p), then ( y, pqr) is worse than ( x, pr). Gain-Loss Asymmetry This is the final piece of the puzzle. Consider the following pair of problems. Problem 1 : In addition to what you own, you have been given 1000 dollars. between Choose 16

17 (A) 50% chance of winning 1000, and 50% chance of winning nothing (B) 500 with certainty. Problem 2 : In addition to what you own, you have been given Choose between (C) 50% chance of losing 1000 and 50% chance of losing nothing (D) -500 with certainty. People typically choose B in the first problem and C in second. But the problems are the same! Evidently, subjects didn t take the bonus into account when making their decisions. This led Kahneman and Tversky to conclude that the relevant variables of interest are changes in wealth rather than absolute wealth levels (which is what matters in the expected utility world). Theory Kahneman and Tversky hypothesized that utility from a regular gamble (x, p; y, q) is evaluated in the following way: U(x, p; y, q) = π(p)v(x) + π(q)v(y). A regular gamble is a gamble where either p + q < 1 or x 0 y or y 0 x. v is called the value function and π is called the decision weight. Kahneman and Tversky emphasize that a decision weight is different from your belief about the event because in general it does not satisfy the probability axioms. For strictly positive and strictly negative gambles (p + q = 1 and x > y > 0 or 0 > y > x), utility is evaluated differently. Subjects take the less extreme of these amounts and factor it out of the problem. Then, U(x, p; y, q) = v(y) + π(p)(v(x) v(y)) The thing to notice above is that the decision weight is only applied to the uncertain part of the gamble. Thus, your utility is what you get for sure plus (or minus) the difference in utility due to the uncertain component. 17

18 Properties of the value function Kahneman and Tversky use some experimental data to argue that: v is concave for gains but convex for losses v has a steeper slope in the loss domain than in the gain domain (loss aversion) To see the first argument, consider the following pair of problems. Problem 1 : Choose between (A) 25% chance of winning 6000, and 75% chance of winning nothing (B) 25% chance of winning 4000, 25% chance of winning 2000, and 50% chance of winning nothing Problem 2 : In addition to what you own, you have been given Choose between (C) 25% chance of losing 6000, and 75% chance of losing nothing (D) 25% chance of losing 4000, 25% chance of losing 2000, and 50% chance of losing nothing The typical pattern of choices is B and C. Applying Kahneman and Tversky s utility function for regular gambles, we get π(.25)v(6000) > π(.25)v(4000) + π(.25)v(2000) and π(.25)v( 6000) < π(.25)v( 4000) + π(.25)v( 2000) We can rewrite this as and v(6000) v(4000) < v(2000) v( 6000) v( 4000) > v( 2000) which is consistent with the hypothesis that v is concave for gains and convex for losses. To argue for loss aversion, Kahneman and Tversky note that if x > y 0, (y,.5; y,.5) is typically preferred to (x,.5; x,.5). 18

19 Therefore, v(y) + v( y) > v(x) + v( x) or v( y) v( x) > v(x) v(y) Letting y approach x, this implies that v ( x) > v(x). Properties of the decision weights Kahneman and Tversky argue that: π(p) > p for small probabilities (overweighting) π(p) + π(1 p) < 1 generally (subcertainty) or Recall that people prefer (6000, 0.1) to (3000, 0.2). Hence, π(0.1)v(6000) > π(0.2)v(3000) π(0.1) π(0.2) > v(3000) v(6000) > 1 2, where the last inequality follows from the concavity of v. Thus π(p) > p, at least for small probabilities. What Kahneman and Tversky call subcertainty follows from their specification of the utility function and the Allais paradox. 7 Cautious Expected Utility The discussion below follows a recent paper (Cerreia-Vioglio, Dillenberger, Ortoleva 2014) that provides an alternative to prospect theory. The paper considers lotteries over an interval [w, b] R. Let δ x denote the lottery that pays you x [w, b] for sure, and the space of all lotteries. This paper takes the certainty effect as a starting point and asks the question of what axiom can capture it. The axiom that the authors come up with is the following. 19

20 Negative Certainty Independence: For any p, q, x [w, b], and λ [0, 1], p δ x λp + (1 λ)q λδ x + (1 λ)q. In words, if p is better than a certain thing, introducing the same amount of additional uncertainty on both sides still makes p a better thing. Homework: Show that NCI implies Kahneman and Tversky s definition of the certainty effect: If (y, q) is equivalent to (x, 1), then (y, qr) is preferred to (x, r). Show that NCI implies convexity. CDO show that together with some simple basic axioms (rationality, continuity, monotonicity), we get what s called a Caution Expected Utility representation. Cautious Expected Utility: Let be a preference relation over, and let c(p, v) denote the certainty equivalent of p with Bernoulli utility v. We say that has a CEU representation if there exists a set W of strictly increasing and continuous utility functions on [w, b] such that p q V (p) V (q), where V (p) = inf v W c(p, v). In words, the agent here doesn t know what her utility function over [w, b]. She only knows it is contained in W. To compute her utility from a lottery p, she considers all possible (expected utility) valuations E p (v) and takes the lowest possible ones. It is in this sense that agent is cautious. Note that Cautious Expected Utility contains the usual kind of Expected Utility as a special case. This is true if the set W has one element. Note also that Prospect Theory contains expected utility as a special case, as well! This is true if π(p) = p. Thus, there as a point (and this point is Expected Utility) at which Prospect Theory and Cautious Expected Utility coincide. On the other hand, CEU is rich enough to also accommodate violations of Expected Utility such as the Allais Paradox. 20

21 Homework: Let [w, b] = R +, and W = {u 1, u 2 }, where u 1 (x) = exp( βx), β > 0; and u 2 (x) = x α, α (0, 1). Let α = 0.8 and β = and consider two problems. Problem 1: a choice between A = δ and B = 0.8δ δ 0. Problem 2: a choice between C = 0.25δ δ 0 and D = 0.2δ δ 0. Show if the agent has a Cautious Expected Utility representation with the set W, then A B and D C. The main result of CDO is the following. Theorem: Let be a preference relation on. The following statements are equivalent: 1. The relation satisfies rationality, continuity, weak monotonicity, and NCI. 2. There exists a CEU representation of. 21

22 8 Time Preferences Assume now that there are t = 1, 2,..., T periods, so that a consumption bundle is given by (x 1, x 2,..., x T ). Note that we can use what we learned above at preference relations to study the consumer s preferences and choices! Economists typically assume that preferences are additively separable over time, so that U(x 1,..., x T ) = T u t (x t ). t=0 We typically assume even more structure, i.e. that u t (x t ) = β t u(x t ), where β (0, 1) is the agent s discount factor. This captures the intuition that preferences don t change over time and that people are impatient. Note that E[U(x 1,..., x T )] = T β t E(u(x t )). t=0 Example: Let U(x 1, x 2 ) = log(x 1 )+βlog(x 2 ). Assume that the consumer receives income m 1 in period 1 and m 2 in period 2. Assume further that the consumer can borrow and lend at an interest rate r. Derive the consumer s consumption bundle (x 1, x 2 ) as a function of β, r, m 1, andm 2. Derive the conditions on β, r, m 1, andm 2 under which the consumer is a borrower, and provide an intuitive explanation. 8.1 Hyperbolic Discounting There is a lot of experimental evidence showing that a better way of modeling time preferences is: T U(x 1,..., x T ) = u(x 0 ) + β β t E(u(x t )). This is sometimes called the β δ model. Here, there is more discounting between today and tomorrow than between any other two adjacent periods. One type of experiment to show this asks people to choose between an apple now and two apples tomorrow, and also between an apple a year from now and two apples 22 t=1

23 a year from now and one day. People typically choose one apple now and two apples a year and a day from now. (Show that this is inconsistent with the exponential discounting model.) 8.2 Rubinstein, 2003 This paper shows that while it s easy to construct experiments that reject exponential discounting, one can also construct experiments that reject both exponential and hyperbolic discounting. Rubinstein considers a more general model of hyperbolic discounting, where U(x 0,..., x T ) = u(x 0 ) + T ( δ s )u(x t ). t=1 s=1,...,t Experiment 1 of Rubinstein, 2003 Q1 Imagine that you have to choose between the following two options: A) Receiving $ on June 17th B) Receiving $ on June 17th What will be your choice? Q2 Imagine that you have to choose between the following two options: A) Receiving $ on June 16th B) Receiving $ on June 17th What will be your choice? Homework: Show that Delay in Q1 and No delay in Q2 is not consistent with either exponential and hyperbolic discounting. 8.3 Risk Preferences Are Not Time Preferences Andreoni and Sprenger is an interesting paper that explores the possibility that risk and time preferences are intertwined. This is because what happens in the future is uncertain. Consider expected utility from a prospect that gives consumption c t at time t 23

24 with probability p 1 and 0 otherwise, and c t+k at time t + k with probability p 2 and 0 otherwise. Then, U = p 1 δ t u(c t ) + p 2 δ t+k u(c t+k ) + ((1 p 1 )δ t + (1 p 2 )δ t+k )u(c 0 ). Suppose that utility is maximized subject to the constraint (1 + r)c t + c t+k = m. The first order conditions give u (c t ) δ k u (c t+k ) = (1 + r)p 2 p 1. Notice that the optimal consumption bundle depends on the ratio of probabilities and not what the actual probabilities are. I.e., intertemporal allocation depend only on relative risk. For example, if a sooner payment is made 80 percent of the time and a later payment 40 percent of the time, the optimal consumption bundle should be the same as if a sooner payment is made 40 percent of the time and a later payment 20 percent of the time Experiment Subjects choose between allocating tokens to a sooner payment (7 days from now) and a later payment (28, 56 days) by allocating tokens out of 100 between sooner and later payments. a t+k =20 cents per token, a t =from 0.14 to 0.20 cents per token. Note that this plays around with interest rates. (p 1, p 2 ) {(1, 1), (0.5, 0.5), (1, 0.8), (0.5, 0.4), (0.8, 1), (0.4, 0.5)}. In conditions 1 and 2, both expected utility theory and prospect theory predict the same choice In conditions 3 and 4, expected utility predicts the same choice but prospect theory does not In conditions 3 and 4, expected utility predicts the same choice but prospect theory does not 24

25 9 Strategic Decisions We start with a mathematical definition of what a game it is. A normal form game is ((A i ) i=1,...,n, (u i ) i=1,...,n ), where i A i A = n i=1 Ai, and u i : A R i. is an action set, Sexes. I = {1,..., n} is the set of players. Assume A i is finite for all i. Examples: Coordination, Matching pennies, Prisoner s dilemma, Battle of the Let S i = (A i ) = {(s(a i 1),..., s(a i k i )) : i, s(a i ) 0, A i s(a i ) = 1}. A mixed extension of a normal form game is ((S i ) i=1,...,n, (u i ) i=1,...,n ), where S i = (A i ), S = n i=1 Si and u i : S R is defined by u i (s 1,..., s n ) = a A u i (a) We write P r s (a) = n i=1 si (a i ) A. n s i (a i ). We will now study three important solution concepts in game theory: dominance, rationalizability, and probably the most famous one of all, Nash Equilibrium. i=1 9.1 Mixed vs. Correlated Strategies Imagine there are two other players, player 1 with actions (L,R) and player 2 with actions (T,B). What are the beliefs we can have about the players actions? If we take a as a state, then the possible states from our perspective are (L,T),(L,B),(R,T),(R,B). Then the set of possible beliefs is the set of all possible probability distributions over these states. We denote this set by (A) and let µ (A) denote generic elements. Another possibility is to recognize that the probabilities of actions are induced by mixed strategies s = (s 1, s 2 ). Then {(P r s (a)) a A : s S} 25

26 is the set of probabilities on A induced my the mixed strategies. Notice that {(P r s (a)) a A : s S} is NOT equal to (A). Here is a belief that cannot be generated by mixed strategies: L R T B This belief is reasonably though if players are allowed to correlate their behavior. I.e., they both flip a SINGLE coin. If it s heads they choose (T,L) and if it s heads they chose (B,R). This kind of strategy is called a correlated strategy. 9.2 Dominance Example: Show that in the game below, the player can get a better payoff by mixing T and M than by playing B, no matter what his belief is about what his partner is doing. L R T 3 0 M 0 3 B 1 1 We say s i S i strictly dominates a i A i iff for all a i u i (s i, a i ) > u i (a i, a i ). Alternatively, or s i D 2 a i s i S i u i (s i, s i ) > u i (a i, s i ) s i D 3 a i µ (A i ) u i (s i, µ) > u i (a i, µ) Exercise: s i D 3 a i s i D 2 a i s i D 1 a i. Example: Note that T and L are both dominated in the game below. L R T -2,-2-10,-1 B -1,-10-5,-5 26

27 This leads to the counter-intuitive prediction of playing (B,R). Of course this doesn t happen in real life. 9.3 IESDA We illustrate this with examples: L R T 0,-2-10,-1 B -1,-10-5,-5 L R T 3,0 0,1 M 0,0 3,1 B 1,1 1,0 Related concept: IEWDA. Example: Using the game below, show that the set of actions surviving IEWDA is not unique. L R T 1,1 0,0 M 1,1 2,1 B 0,0 2,1 9.4 Rationalizability We start with an example: L R T 3 0 M 0 3 B x x If x < 3/2, B is never a best response. Dually, you can find a mix that strictly dominates B. At x = 3/2, B is a best response. Dually, you cannot find a mix that strictly 27

28 dominates B. This example suggests that an action is never a best response if and only if it is strictly dominated by a strategy. Definition: An action a i A i is never a best response if there is no µ (A i ) such that u i (a i, µ) u i (b i, µ) for all b i. Theorem: An action a i A i is strictly dominated if it is never a best response. (Show it!) In fact, this is an if and only if in 2 person games... but we skip the proof here. Thus, eliminating strategies that are never a best response eliminates at least as many strategies as the number of strategies that are strictly dominated. Moreover, as with IESDA, we can iterate the process of eliminated NBR strategies. Once I eliminate mine, you can take into account the remaining ones and eliminate yours, etc. The strategies that survive are called the rationalizable strategies. Example: find the rationalizable strategies of the game below. b 1 b 2 b 3 b 4 a 1 0,7 2,5 7,0 0,1 a 2 5,2 3,3 5,2 0,1 a 3 7,0 2,5 0,7 0,1 a 4 0,0 0,-2 0,0 10,-1 Exercise: show that the rationalizable strategies are a 1, a 2, a 3 for player 1 and b 1, b 2, b 3 for player 2. Note that for each of the rationalizable strategies a player can construct a chain of reasoning that justifies is. I play b 2 because I believe that player 1 will play a 2 which is reasonable if he thinks I play b 2 etc. 9.5 Nash Equilibrium We first define what it means to be a best response. We already talked about this informally, but here is the formal definition. 28

29 Definition (Pure Best Reply) P BR i (s) = {a i A i : b i A i u i (b i, P r s i)}. u i (a i, P r s i) Above, P r s i (A i ) with P r s i(a i ) = j i sj (a j ). Definition (Best Reply) BR i (s) = {s i S i : a i A i u i (s i, P r s i) u i (a i, P r s i)}. Example: find the BR correspondences of the game below. L R T 3,1 0,0 B 0,0 1,3 Proposition: For every s, BR i (s) is closed, convex, nonempty, and equal to the mixed strategies concentrated on P RB i (s). Definition: BR(s) = n i=1 BRi (s). Note that this is a correspondence from S to S. It is closed, convex, and nonempty. Definition: A Nash Equilibrium of a normal form game is a strategy profile ŝ such that ŝ BR(ŝ). That is, i Example: find NE of the game below. L R T 1,1 0,0 B 0,0 0,0 Example: find NE of the game below. L R T 3,1 0,0 B 0,0 1,3 ŝ i BR i (ŝ). 29

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION Szabolcs Sebestyén szabolcs.sebestyen@iscte.pt Master in Finance INVESTMENTS Sebestyén (ISCTE-IUL) Choice Theory Investments 1 / 65 Outline 1 An Introduction

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance University of Exeter Recap Last class we looked at the axioms of expected utility, which defined a rational agent as proposed by von Neumann and Morgenstern. We then proceeded to look at empirical evidence

More information

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY LECTURE 5 MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY Choice under Uncertainty (MWG chapter 6, sections A-C, and Cowell chapter 8) Lecturer: Andreas Papandreou 1 Introduction p Contents n Expected utility theory

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, MsC Economics List of Problems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO September 25, 2015 A Brief Look at General Equilibrium Asset Pricing Last week, we saw a general equilibrium model in which banks were irrelevant.

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty Chapter 7 Choice under Uncertainty 1. Expected Utility Theory. 2. Risk Aversion. 3. Applications: demand for insurance, portfolio choice 4. Violations of Expected Utility Theory. 7.1 Expected Utility Theory

More information

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty Pierre Chaigneau pierre.chaigneau@hec.ca June 14, 2011 Finance: the economics of risk and uncertainty In financial markets, claims associated with random future

More information

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key 1. Exercises from MWG (Chapter 6): (a) Exercise 6.B.1 from MWG: Show that if the preferences % over L satisfy the independence axiom, then for all 2 (0; 1) and

More information

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck! Name Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck! 1) For each of the following statements, state whether it is true or false. If it is true, prove that it is true.

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

Midterm #2 EconS 527 [November 7 th, 2016]

Midterm #2 EconS 527 [November 7 th, 2016] Midterm # EconS 57 [November 7 th, 16] Question #1 [ points]. Consider an individual with a separable utility function over goods u(x) = α i ln x i i=1 where i=1 α i = 1 and α i > for every good i. Assume

More information

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours YORK UNIVERSITY Faculty of Graduate Studies Final Examination December 14, 2010 Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics S. Bucovetsky time=2.5 hours Do any 6 of the following 10 questions. All count

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk Preliminaries We treat, for convenience, money as a continuous variable when dealing with monetary outcomes. Strictly speaking, the derivation

More information

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Choice under risk and uncertainty Choice under risk and uncertainty Introduction Up until now, we have thought of the objects that our decision makers are choosing as being physical items However, we can also think of cases where the outcomes

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to GAME THEORY PROBLEM SET 1 WINTER 2018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to andrey.zhukov@aalto.fi. Materials from Osborne and Rubinstein

More information

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the open text license amendment to version 2 of the GNU General

More information

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2013 *********************************************** COVER SHEET ***********************************************

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion Expected Utility And Risk Aversion Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 12, October 4 Outline 1 Risk Aversion 2 Certainty Equivalent 3 Risk Premium 4 Relative Risk Aversion 5 Stochastic Dominance Notation From

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 9, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria

More information

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2013 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. FINC3023 Behavioral Finance TOPIC 1: Expected Utility Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality. A normative theory based on rational utility maximizers

More information

Game Theory - Lecture #8

Game Theory - Lecture #8 Game Theory - Lecture #8 Outline: Randomized actions vnm & Bernoulli payoff functions Mixed strategies & Nash equilibrium Hawk/Dove & Mixed strategies Random models Goal: Would like a formulation in which

More information

Lecture 5. Varian, Ch. 8; MWG, Chs. 3.E, 3.G, and 3.H. 1 Summary of Lectures 1, 2, and 3: Production theory and duality

Lecture 5. Varian, Ch. 8; MWG, Chs. 3.E, 3.G, and 3.H. 1 Summary of Lectures 1, 2, and 3: Production theory and duality Lecture 5 Varian, Ch. 8; MWG, Chs. 3.E, 3.G, and 3.H Summary of Lectures, 2, and 3: Production theory and duality 2 Summary of Lecture 4: Consumption theory 2. Preference orders 2.2 The utility function

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 13, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Decisions, Utility Maximization Games and Strategies Best Responses

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected utility and risk aversion 1/ 58 Introduction Expected utility is the standard framework for modeling investor choices. The following topics will be covered:

More information

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Uncertainty in Equilibrium Uncertainty in Equilibrium Larry Blume May 1, 2007 1 Introduction The state-preference approach to uncertainty of Kenneth J. Arrow (1953) and Gérard Debreu (1959) lends itself rather easily to Walrasian

More information

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty Introduction to Microeconomics Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty The Five Axioms of Choice Under Uncertainty We can use the axioms of preference to show how preferences can be mapped into measurable

More information

14.03 Fall 2004 Problem Set 2 Solutions

14.03 Fall 2004 Problem Set 2 Solutions 14.0 Fall 004 Problem Set Solutions October, 004 1 Indirect utility function and expenditure function Let U = x 1 y be the utility function where x and y are two goods. Denote p x and p y as respectively

More information

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion Uncertainty Outline Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion 2 Simple Lotteries 3 Simple Lotteries Advanced Microeconomic Theory

More information

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty We always need to make a decision (or select from among actions, options or moves) even when there exists

More information

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d EXTRA PROBLEMS (1) In the following matching problem, each college has the capacity for only a single student (each college will admit only one student). The colleges are denoted by A, B, C, D, while the

More information

ECON 5113 Microeconomic Theory

ECON 5113 Microeconomic Theory Test 1 January 30, 2015 Time Allowed: 1 hour 20 minutes phones or calculators are allowed. Please write your answers on the answer book provided. Use the right-side pages for formal answers and the left-side

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Theory

Advanced Microeconomic Theory Advanced Microeconomic Theory Lecture Notes Sérgio O. Parreiras Fall, 2016 Outline Mathematical Toolbox Decision Theory Partial Equilibrium Search Intertemporal Consumption General Equilibrium Financial

More information

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions ; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions Prof. Massimo Guidolin Portfolio Management Spring 2016 Outline and objectives Utility functions The expected utility theorem and the axioms

More information

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009 MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 14.123 Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. MIT 14.123 (2009) by

More information

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average) Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, 2016 1. In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average) cost. To investigate the consequences of markup pricing,

More information

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam Summer 2018 Microeconomics Qualifying Exam There are 100 points possible on this exam, 50 points each for Prof. Lozada s questions and Prof. Dugar s questions. Each professor asks you to do two long questions

More information

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations Shuoxun Hellen Zhang WISE & SOE XIAMEN UNIVERSITY March, 2015 1 / 57 Questions to Answer How financial risk is defined and measured How an investor

More information

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice Prof. Massimo Guidolin Portfolio Management Spring 2017 Outline and objectives Choice under uncertainty: dominance o Guidolin-Pedio, chapter 1, sec. 2 Choice under

More information

Problem Set 3 Solutions

Problem Set 3 Solutions Problem Set 3 Solutions Ec 030 Feb 9, 205 Problem (3 points) Suppose that Tomasz is using the pessimistic criterion where the utility of a lottery is equal to the smallest prize it gives with a positive

More information

Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts. Game in strategic form has following elements. Player set N. (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i.

Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts. Game in strategic form has following elements. Player set N. (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i. Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts Game in strategic form has following elements Player set N (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i. Payoff function f i for player i f i : S R, where S is product of S i s.

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 The Consumer Problem Consider an agent choosing her consumption of goods 1 and 2 for a given budget. This is the workhorse of microeconomic theory. (Notice

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, Spring 2011 List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, Spring 2011 List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, Spring 2011 List of Prolems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

UNIT 1 THEORY OF COSUMER BEHAVIOUR: BASIC THEMES

UNIT 1 THEORY OF COSUMER BEHAVIOUR: BASIC THEMES UNIT 1 THEORY OF COSUMER BEHAVIOUR: BASIC THEMES Structure 1.0 Objectives 1.1 Introduction 1.2 The Basic Themes 1.3 Consumer Choice Concerning Utility 1.3.1 Cardinal Theory 1.3.2 Ordinal Theory 1.3.2.1

More information

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium Draft chapter from An introduction to game theory by Martin J. Osborne. Version: 2002/7/23. Martin.Osborne@utoronto.ca http://www.economics.utoronto.ca/osborne Copyright 1995 2002 by Martin J. Osborne.

More information

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory Leslie Reinhorn Durham University Business School October 2014 What is Economics? Typical De nitions: "Economics is the social science that deals with the production,

More information

Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals.

Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals. Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals. We will deal with a particular set of assumptions, but we can modify

More information

What are the additional assumptions that must be satisfied for Rabin s theorem to hold?

What are the additional assumptions that must be satisfied for Rabin s theorem to hold? Exam ECON 4260, Spring 2013 Suggested answers to Problems 1, 2 and 4 Problem 1 (counts 10%) Rabin s theorem shows that if a person is risk averse in a small gamble, then it follows as a logical consequence

More information

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty Economics 101 Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty 1 Intertemporal Setting Consider a consumer who lives for two periods, say old and young. When he is young, he has income m 1, while when

More information

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014 HARVARD UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014 You have FOUR hours. Answer all questions Those taking the FINAL have THREE hours Part A (Glaeser): 55

More information

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017 Problem Set Theory of Banking - Academic Year 06-7 Maria Bachelet maria.jua.bachelet@gmai.com March, 07 Exercise Consider an agency relationship in which the principal contracts the agent, whose effort

More information

Expected Utility Theory

Expected Utility Theory Expected Utility Theory Mark Dean Behavioral Economics Spring 27 Introduction Up until now, we have thought of subjects choosing between objects Used cars Hamburgers Monetary amounts However, often the

More information

Econ205 Intermediate Microeconomics with Calculus Chapter 1

Econ205 Intermediate Microeconomics with Calculus Chapter 1 Econ205 Intermediate Microeconomics with Calculus Chapter 1 Margaux Luflade May 1st, 2016 Contents I Basic consumer theory 3 1 Overview 3 1.1 What?................................................. 3 1.1.1

More information

Part I. The consumer problems

Part I. The consumer problems Part I The consumer problems Individual decision-making under certainty Course outline We will divide decision-making under certainty into three units: 1 Producer theory Feasible set defined by technology

More information

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko ECON 581. Decision making under risk Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko 1 / 36 Outline Expected utility Risk aversion Certainty equivalence and risk premium The canonical portfolio allocation problem 2 / 36 Suggested

More information

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY PART ± I CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 Foundations of Finance I: Expected Utility Theory Foundations of Finance II: Asset Pricing, Market Efficiency,

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 9, 2015 Review of Last Week Consumer choice problem General equilibrium Contingent claims Risk aversion The optimal choice, x = (X, Y ), is

More information

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty Paulo Brito 1 pbrito@iseg.ulisboa.pt University of Lisbon March 9, 2018 Topics covered Contingent goods Comparing contingent goods Decision under

More information

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Problem Set 1 These questions will go over basic game-theoretic concepts and some applications. homework is due during class on week 4. This [1] In this problem (see Fudenberg-Tirole

More information

January 26,

January 26, January 26, 2015 Exercise 9 7.c.1, 7.d.1, 7.d.2, 8.b.1, 8.b.2, 8.b.3, 8.b.4,8.b.5, 8.d.1, 8.d.2 Example 10 There are two divisions of a firm (1 and 2) that would benefit from a research project conducted

More information

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS 1 2 UTILITY ANALYSIS Motivating Example: Your total net worth = $400K = W 0. You own a home worth $250K. Probability of a fire each yr = 0.001. Insurance cost = $1K. Question:

More information

ECON 5113 Advanced Microeconomics

ECON 5113 Advanced Microeconomics Test 1 February 1, 008 carefully and provide answers to what you are asked only. Do not spend time on what you are not asked to do. Remember to put your name on the front page. 1. Let be a preference relation

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 13, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Decisions, Utility Maximization Games and Strategies Best Responses

More information

that internalizes the constraint by solving to remove the y variable. 1. Using the substitution method, determine the utility function U( x)

that internalizes the constraint by solving to remove the y variable. 1. Using the substitution method, determine the utility function U( x) For the next two questions, the consumer s utility U( x, y) 3x y 4xy depends on the consumption of two goods x and y. Assume the consumer selects x and y to maximize utility subject to the budget constraint

More information

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E. Microeconomic Theory -1- Uncertainty Choice under uncertainty A Introduction to choice under uncertainty B Risk aversion 11 C Favorable gambles 15 D Measures of risk aversion 0 E Insurance 6 F Small favorable

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory 3a. More on Normal-Form Games Dana Nau University of Maryland Nau: Game Theory 1 More Solution Concepts Last time, we talked about several solution concepts Pareto optimality

More information

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives CHAPTER Duxbury Thomson Learning Making Hard Decision Third Edition RISK ATTITUDES A. J. Clark School of Engineering Department of Civil and Environmental Engineering 13 FALL 2003 By Dr. Ibrahim. Assakkaf

More information

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing THE UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHAMPTON Paul Klein Office: Murray Building, 3005 Email: p.klein@soton.ac.uk URL: http://paulklein.se Economics 3010 Topics in Macroeconomics 3 Autumn 2010 Lecture 8: Introduction

More information

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty Prof. Massimo Guidolin Prep Course in Quant Methods for Finance August-September 2017 Outline and objectives Axioms of choice under

More information

Characterization of the Optimum

Characterization of the Optimum ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 5. Portfolio Allocation with One Riskless, One Risky Asset Characterization of the Optimum Consider a risk-averse, expected-utility-maximizing

More information

PhD Qualifier Examination

PhD Qualifier Examination PhD Qualifier Examination Department of Agricultural Economics May 29, 2014 Instructions This exam consists of six questions. You must answer all questions. If you need an assumption to complete a question,

More information

Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam

Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam June 2009 Instructions: (1) Please answer each of the four questions on separate pieces of paper. (2) When finished, please arrange your answers alphabetically (in the

More information

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I) Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16 (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I) Dealing with Uncertainty 2 Preferences over risky choices (Section 7.1) One simple model: Expected Utility How can old tools be applied to analyze

More information

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015 Best-Reply Sets Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis This version: May 2015 Introduction The best-reply correspondence of a game the mapping from beliefs over one s opponents actions to

More information

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010 May 19, 2010 1 Introduction Scope of Agent preferences Utility Functions 2 Game Representations Example: Game-1 Extended Form Strategic Form Equivalences 3 Reductions Best Response Domination 4 Solution

More information

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6 Non-Zero Sum Games R&N Section 17.6 Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games m 11 m 12 m 21 m 22 m ij = Player A s payoff if Player A follows pure strategy i and Player B follows pure strategy j 1 Results so far

More information

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem Jin Yong Jung We analyze how the wealth of an agent and its distribution affect the profit of the principal by considering the simple

More information

Mock Examination 2010

Mock Examination 2010 [EC7086] Mock Examination 2010 No. of Pages: [7] No. of Questions: [6] Subject [Economics] Title of Paper [EC7086: Microeconomic Theory] Time Allowed [Two (2) hours] Instructions to candidates Please answer

More information

Game Theory Lecture Notes

Game Theory Lecture Notes Game Theory Lecture Notes Sérgio O. Parreiras Economics Department, UNC at Chapel Hill Spring, 2015 Outline Road Map Decision Problems Static Games Nash Equilibrium Pareto Efficiency Constrained Optimization

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 07. (40 points) Consider a Cournot duopoly. The market price is given by q q, where q and q are the quantities of output produced

More information

Their opponent will play intelligently and wishes to maximize their own payoff.

Their opponent will play intelligently and wishes to maximize their own payoff. Two Person Games (Strictly Determined Games) We have already considered how probability and expected value can be used as decision making tools for choosing a strategy. We include two examples below for

More information

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I Homework 1, due in recitation on 10/18/2018. 1. Consider the following strategic game: player 1/player 2 L R U 1,1 0,0 D 0,0 3,2 Any NE can be

More information

Strategies and Nash Equilibrium. A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory

Strategies and Nash Equilibrium. A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory Strategies and Nash Equilibrium A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory (Mostly from Fudenberg & Tirole) Players choose actions, receive rewards based on their own actions and those of the other players. Example,

More information

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Consumption and Asset Pricing Consumption and Asset Pricing Yin-Chi Wang The Chinese University of Hong Kong November, 2012 References: Williamson s lecture notes (2006) ch5 and ch 6 Further references: Stochastic dynamic programming:

More information

Game theory for. Leonardo Badia.

Game theory for. Leonardo Badia. Game theory for information engineering Leonardo Badia leonardo.badia@gmail.com Zero-sum games A special class of games, easier to solve Zero-sum We speak of zero-sum game if u i (s) = -u -i (s). player

More information

Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section 1-2: Uncompensated and Compensated Elasticities; Static and Dynamic Labor Supply

Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section 1-2: Uncompensated and Compensated Elasticities; Static and Dynamic Labor Supply Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section -2: Uncompensated and Compensated Elasticities; Static and Dynamic Labor Supply Matteo Paradisi September 3, 206 In today s section, we will briefly review the

More information

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version)

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) July 4, 2017 1. Person A lexicographically prefers good x to good y, i.e., when comparing two bundles of x and y, she strictly prefers

More information

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games University of Illinois Fall 2018 ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games Due: Tuesday, Sept. 11, at beginning of class Reading: Course notes, Sections 1.1-1.4 1. [A random

More information

Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1

Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1 Session 9: The expected utility framework Susan Thomas http://www.igidr.ac.in/ susant susant@mayin.org IGIDR Bombay Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1 Questions How do humans make decisions

More information

Lecture 4 - Utility Maximization

Lecture 4 - Utility Maximization Lecture 4 - Utility Maximization David Autor, MIT and NBER 1 1 Roadmap: Theory of consumer choice This figure shows you each of the building blocks of consumer theory that we ll explore in the next few

More information

Practice Problems. w U(w, e) = p w e 2,

Practice Problems. w U(w, e) = p w e 2, Practice Problems nformation Economics (Ec 55) George Georgiadis Problem. Static Moral Hazard Consider an agency relationship in which the principal contracts with the agent. The monetary result of the

More information

Imprecise Probabilities in Non-cooperative Games

Imprecise Probabilities in Non-cooperative Games Imprecise Probabilities in Non-cooperative Games Robert Nau Fuqua School of Business Duke University ISIPTA 11 Innsbruck July 2011 1 Historically there has been tension between game theory and subjective

More information

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models IEOR E4707: Foundations of Financial Engineering c 206 by Martin Haugh Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models These notes develop the theory of martingale pricing in a discrete-time,

More information

Time, Uncertainty, and Incomplete Markets

Time, Uncertainty, and Incomplete Markets Time, Uncertainty, and Incomplete Markets 9.1 Suppose half the people in the economy choose according to the utility function u A (x 0, x H, x L ) = x 0 + 5x H.3x 2 H + 5x L.2x 2 L and the other half according

More information

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS Peter Ireland Boston College April 3, 2018 These lecture notes by Peter Ireland are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommerical-ShareAlike 4.0 International

More information

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2 Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2 Jörgen Weibull February 4, 2010 Two topics today: 1. Existence of Nash equilibria (Lecture notes Chapter 10 and Appendix A) 2. Relations between equilibrium and rationality

More information