Revenue Maximization in the Dynamic Knapsack Problem

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Revenue Maximization in the Dynamic Knapsack Problem"

Transcription

1 Revenue Maximization in the Dynamic Knapsack Problem Deniz Dizar, Alex Gershkov an Benny Molovanu Abstract We characterize the revenue maximizing policy in the ynamic an stochastic knapsack problem here a given capacity nees to be allocate by a given ealine to sequentially arriving agents. Each agent is escribe by a toimensional type that re ects his capacity requirement an his illingness to pay per unit of capacity. Types are private information. We rst characterize implementable policies. Then e solve the revenue maximization problem for the special case here there is private information about per-unit values, but eights are observable. After that e erive to sets of aitional conitions on the joint istribution of values an eights uner hich the revenue maximizing policy for the case ith observable eights is implementable, an thus optimal also for the case ith to-imensional private information. Finally, e analyze a simple policy for hich per-unit prices vary ith requeste eight but o not vary ith time. Its implementation requirements are similar to those of the optimal policy an it turns out to be asymptotically revenue maximizing hen available capacity/ time to the ealine both go to in nity. 1 Introuction The knapsack problem is a classic combinatorial optimization problem ith numerous practical applications: several objects ith given, knon capacity requests (or eights) an given, knon, values must be packe in a "knapsack" of given capacity in orer to maximize the value of the inclue objects. In the ynamic an stochastic version (see Ross an Tsang [22]) objects sequentially arrive over time an their eight/value combination is stochastic but becomes knon to the esigner at arrival times. In the present paper e a incomplete information to the ynamic an stochastic setting: there is a nite number of perios, an at each perio a request for capacity We are grateful to the German Science Founation for nancial support. Dizar, Gershkov, Molovanu: Department of Economics, University of Bonn, Lennestr. 37, Bonn Germany; izar@uni-bonn.e, alex.gershkov@uni-bonn.e, mol@uni-bonn.e 1

2 arrives from an agent that is privately informe about both his valuation per unit of capacity an the neee capacity 1. Each agent erives positive utility if he gets the neee capacity (or more), an zero utility otherise. The esigner accepts or rejects the requests in orer to maximize the revenue obtaine from the allocation. The ynamic an stochastic knapsack problem ith complete information about values an requests has been analyze by Papastavrou, Rajagopalan an Kleyegt [18] an by Kleyegt an Papastavrou [13]. These authors have characterize optimal policies in terms of threshols. Kincai an Darling [11], an Gallego an van Ryzin [7] look at a moel that can be re-interprete as having (one imensional) incomplete information about values, but in their frameorks all requests have the same knon eight 2. In particular, Gallego an van Ryzin sho that revenue is concave in capacity in the case of equal eights. Kleyegt an Papastavrou have examples shoing that total value may not be concave in capacity if the eight requests are heterogeneous. Gershkov an Molovanu [8] generalize the Gallego-van Ryzin moel to incorporate objects ith the same eight but ith several qualities that are equally ranke by all agents, inepenently of their types (hich are also one-imensional). The theory of multiimensional mechanism esign is relatively complex: the main problem is that incentive compatibility - hich in the one-imensional case often reuces to a monotonicity constraint - imposes, besies a monotonicity requirement, an integrability constraint that is not easily inclue in maximization problems (see examples in Rochet [2], Armstrong [2], Jehiel, Molovanu an Stacchetti [1], an the survey of Rochet an Stole [21]). Our implementation problem is special though because useful eviations in the eight imension can only be one-sie (upars). This feature allos us a less cumbersome characterization of implementable policies that can be embee in the ynamic analysis uner certain conitions on the joint istribution of values an eights of the arriving agents. Other multiimensional mechanism esign problems ith restricte eviations in one or more imensions have been stuie by Blackorby an Szalay [4], Iyengar an Kumar [9], Kittsteiner an Molovanu [12], an Pai an Vohra [17]. Our main results characterize the revenue maximizing policy for the knapsack problem in several cases. The logic of the construction is as follos: We rst characterize implementable policies, as explaine above. Then e solve the revenue maximization problem for the special case here there is private information about per-unit values, but eights are observable: uner a stanar monotonicity assumption on virtual values, e sho that this policy is Markovian, eterministic, an has a threshol property. It is important to emphasize that the resulting optimal policy nee not be implementable for the case here both values an eights are unobservable, unless aitional conitions are impose. We then erive to sets of aitional conitions 1 The results are easily extene to the setting here arrivals are stochastic an/or time is continuous. 2 We refer the reaer to the book by Talluri an Van Ryzin [23] for references to the large literature on revenue (or yiel) management that aopts variations on these moels. 2

3 on the joint istribution of values an eights uner hich the revenue maximizing policy for the case ith observable eights is implementable, an thus optimal also for the case ith to-imensional private information. These conitions - hich are satis e in a variety of intuitive settings - involve a form of positive correlation beteen eights an values expresse by a hazar rate orering of conitional values, an a eakening of the rst set of su cient conitions in combination ith the non-primitive assumption of concave revenues respectively. Finally, e analyze a simple policy for hich per-unit prices vary ith requeste eight but not ith time. Its implementation requirements are similar to those of the optimal policy an it turns out to be asymptotically revenue maximizing hen available capacity/ time to the ealine both go to in nity. This is particularly valuable since policies hich lea to prices that sometimes ecrease in time create incentive issues if agents are strategic ith respect to their arrival times. We also point out that a policy that varies ith time but not ith requeste eight (hose asymptotic optimality in the complete information case has been establishe by Lin, Lu an Yao [14]) is usually not optimal uner incomplete information. The paper is organize as follos: In Section 2 e present the ynamic moel an the informational assumptions about values an eights. In Section 3 e characterize incentive compatible allocation policies. In Section 4 e focus on ynamic revenue maximization. We rst characterize the revenue maximizing policy for the case here values are private information but eight requests are observable. We then o er to results that exhibit conitions uner hich the above policy is incentive compatible, an thus optimal also for the case here both values an eights are private information. In Section 5 e introuce a simpler time-inepenent policy as escribe above, analyze the limit case here the capacity an time to ealine become very large an emonstrate asymptotic optimality. 2 The Moel The esigner has a "knapsack" of given capacity C 2 R that he ants to allocate in a revenue-maximizing ay to several agents in at most T < 1 perios. In each perio, an impatient agent arrives ith a eman for capacity characterize by a eight or quantity request an by a per-unit value v 3 : While the vector (; v) is private information to the arriving agent, the esigner is assume to kno the istribution of the ranom vector (; v) hich is given by the joint cumulative istribution function F (; v), ith continuously i erentiable ensity f(; v), e ne on [; 1) 2. Demans are inepenent across i erent perios. In each perio, the esigner ecies ho much capacity to allocate to the arriving agent (possibly none) an on a monetary payment. Type (; v) s utility is given by v p if at price p he is allocate a capacity an by p if he is assigne 3 It is an easy extension to assume that the arrival probability per perio is given by p < 1: 3

4 an insu cient capacity <. Each agent observes the remaining capacity of the esigner. 4 Finally, e assume strict monotonicity of the conitional virtual values, 1 F (vj) more precisely: for all, ^v(v; ) := v is increasing in v ith strictly f(vj) positive erivative. 3 Incentive Compatible Policies In this section, e characterize incentive compatible allocation policies. Without loss of generality, e restrict attention to irect mechanisms here every agent, upon arrival, reports a type (; v) an here the mechanism then speci es an allocation an a payment. The schemes e evelop also have an obvious an immeiate interpretation as inirect mechanisms, here the esigner sets a time- an capacity-epenent menu of per-unit prices, one for each eight eman. An allocation policy is calle eterministic an Markovian if, at any perio t = 1; :::; T an for any possible type of agent arriving at t, it uses a non-ranom allocation rule that only epens on the arrival time t, on the eclare type of the arriving agent, an on the still available capacity at perio t, enote by c. The restriction to these policies is innocuous as shon in Section 4. We can assume ithout loss of generality that a eterministic Markovian allocation policy for time t ith remaining capacity c has the form c t : [; +1) 2! f1; g here 1 () means that the reporte capacity eman is satis e (not satis e). Inee, it never makes sense to allocate an insu cient quantity < < because iniviually rational agents are not illing to pay for this. On the other han, allocating more capacity than the reporte eman is useless as ell: Such allocations o not further increase agents utility hile they may ecrease continuation values for the esigner. Let q c t : [; +1) 2! R be the associate payment rule. Proposition 1 A eterministic, Markovian allocation policy f c tg t;c is implementable if an only if for every t an every c it hols that: 1. 8 (; v); v v; c t(; v) = 1 ) c t(; v ) = The function p c t() is non-ecreasing in ; here p c t() = inffv = c t(; v) = 1g 5 Proof. See Appenix. The threshol property emboie in conition 1 of the above Proposition is stanar, an is a natural feature of elfare maximizing rules uner complete information. When there is incomplete information in the value imension, this conition imposes 4 Alternatively, e can assume that each agent observes the entire history of the previous allocations. 5 We set p c t() = 1 if the set fv= c t(; v) = 1g is empty. 4

5 limitations on the payments that can be extracte in equilibrium. Conition 2 is ne: it re ects the limitations impose in our moel by the incomplete information in the eight imension. 4 Dynamic Revenue Maximization In this section, e rst emonstrate ho the ynamic revenue maximization problem may be solve if is observable. Hence e rst assume that there is incomplete information only about v. We then ientify a set of conitions ensuring that the corresponing optimal policy is implementable even if is not observable. The logic of the erivation for solving the revenue maximization problem is somehat involve, an e no etail it belo: 1. Without loss of generality, e can restrict attention to Markovian policies. The optimality of Markovian, possibly ranomize, policies is stanar for all moels here, as is the case here, the per-perio rears an transition probabilities are history-inepenent - see for example Theorem in Puterman [19] hich shos that, for any history-epenent policy, there is a Markovian, possibly ranomize, policy ith the same payo. 2. If there is incomplete information about v; but complete information about the eight requirement, then Markovian, eterministic an implementable policies are characterize for each t an c by the threshol property of Conition 1 in Proposition Naturally, in the given revenue maximization problem ith complete information about e nee to restrict attention to interim iniviually-rational policies here no agent ever pays more than the utility obtaine from her actual capacity allocation. It is easy to see that, for any Markov, eterministic an implementable allocation policy c t, the maximal, iniviually-rational payment function hich supports it is given by q c t (; v) = p c t () if c t(; v) = 1 if c t(; v) = here p c t() = inffv = c t(; v) = 1g as e ne in the above section. Otherise, the esigner pays some positive subsiy to the agent, an this cannot be revenuemaximizing. 4. At each perio t, an for each remaining capacity c; the esigner s problem uner complete information about is equivalent to a simpler, one-imensional static problem here a knon capacity nees to be allocate to the arriving agent, an here the seller has a salvage value for each remaining capacity: the 5

6 salvage values in the static problem correspon to the continuation values in the ynamic version. Analogously to the analysis of Myerson [16], each static revenue-maximization problem has a monotone (in the sense of Conition 1 in Proposition 1), non-ranomize solution as long as, for any eight ; the agent s 1 F (vj) f(vj) conitional virtual valuation v is increasing in v. Inee, the expecte revenue R(c; T + 1 t) if per-unit prices are set at p c t() in perio t T ith remaining capacity c an if the optimal Markovian policy is folloe from time t + 1 onars can be ritten as: R(c; T + 1 t) = + p c t() (1 F (p c t()j)) f () [(1 F (p c t()j))r (c ; T t) + F (p c t()j)r (c; T t)] f () ; here f enotes the marginal ensity in, an here R enotes optimal revenues ith R (c; ) = for all c. The rst-orer conitions for the revenuemaximizing unit prices p c t() are given by: p c t() 1 F (p c t()j) f(p c t()j) = R (c; T t) R (c ; T t): 5. By backar inuction, an by the above reasoning, the seller has a Markov, nonranomize optimal policy in the ynamic problem ith complete information about. Note also that, by a simple uplication argument, R (c; T +1 t) must be monotone non-ecreasing in c: Points 1, 4 an 5 above imply that the restriction to the eterministic an Markovian allocation problems is ithout loss of generality. If the above solution satis es the incentive compatibility constraint in the eight imension, i.e. if p c t() happens to be monotone as require by Conition 2 of Proposition 1, then the associate allocation here c t(; v) = 1 if an only if v p c t() is also implementable in the original problem ith incomplete information about both v an. It then constitutes the revenue maximizing scheme that e are after. The next example illustrates that Conition 2 of Proposition 1 can be bining. Example 1 Assume that T = 1. The istribution of the agents types is given by the folloing stochastic process. First, the eight request is realize accoring to an exponential istribution ith parameter. Next, the per-unit value of the agent is sample from the folloing istribution here > an 2 (; c). F (vj) = ( 1 e v if > 1 e v if 6

7 In this case, for an observable eight request, the seller charges the take-it-or-leaveit o er of 1 ( 1 ) per unit if the eight request is smaller (larger) than or equal to : This implies that ( p c if > t() = if. an therefore, p c t() is not monotone. We next procee to ientify conitions on the istribution of types ensuring the monotonicity of p c t(). 4.1 The Hazar Rate Stochastic Orering A key conition guaranteeing implementability is a stochastic orering of the conitional istributions of per-unit values: the conitional istribution given a higher eight shoul be (eakly) statistically higher in the hazar rate orer than the conitional istribution given a loer eight. Theorem 1 For each c; t; an let p c t() enote the solution to the revenue maximizing problem uner complete information about, etermine recursively by the Bellman equation p c t() Assume that the folloing conitions hol: 1 F (p c t()j) = R (c; T t) R (c ; T t): (1) f(p c t()j) 1. For any ; the conitional hazar rate f(vj) 1 F (vj) is non-ecreasing in v6 : 2. For any, an for any v; f(vj) 1 F (vj) f(vj ) 1 F (vj ). Then, p c t() is non-ecreasing in ; an, consequently, the unerlying allocation here c t(; v) = 1 if an only if v p c t() is implementable. In particular, equations (1) characterize the revenue maximizing scheme uner incomplete information about both values an eights. Proof. See Appenix. An important special case for hich the conitions of the above Theorem hol is the one here the istribution of per-unit values is inepenent of the istribution of eights, an has an increasing hazar rate. 6 Note that this conition alreay implies the neee monotonicity in v of the conitional virtual value for all : 7

8 4.2 Concavity of Expecte Revenue in Capacity A major result for the case here capacity comes in iscrete units, an here all eights are equal is that expecte revenue is concave in capacity (see Gallego an van Ryzin [7] for a continuous time frameork ith Poisson arrivals an Bitran an Monschein [3] for a iscrete time setting). This is a very intuitive property since it says that aitional capacity is more valuable to the esigner hen capacity itself is scarce. Due to the more complicate combinatorial nature of the knapsack problem ith heterogenous eights, concavity nee not generally hol (see Papastavrou, Rajagopalan an Kleyegt [18] for examples here concavity of expecte elfare in the frameork ith complete information fails). Our main result in this subsection ienti es a conition on the istribution of types that, together ith concavity of the expecte revenue in the remaining capacity, ensures that, for each t an c, p c t() is increasing, hence renering the unerlying istribution implementable. Afterars e provie conitions on the moels primitives that are su cient for the concavity of the expecte revenue. Theorem 2 Assume that 1. The expecte revenue R (c; T + 1 t) is a concave function of c for all times t: 2. For any ; v 1 F (vj) f(vj) v 1 F ( v j ). f( v j ) For each c; t; an let p c t() enote the solution to the revenue maximizing problem uner complete information about ; etermine recursively by equations (1). Then p c t() is non-ecreasing in ; an hence the unerlying allocation here c t(; v) = 1 if an only if v p c t() is implementable. In particular, equation (1) characterizes the revenue maximizing scheme uner incomplete information about both values an eights. Proof. See Appenix. Remark 1 The su cient conitions for implementability use in Theorem 1 are, taken together, stronger than Conition 2 in Theorem 2. To see this, assume that, for any ; the conitional hazar rate is increasing in v; an that for any an for all v, v f(vj) f(vj ) 1 F (vj) 1 F (vj ) 1 F (vj) f(vj) f(vj) 1 F (vj). This yiels: v 1 F ( v j) f( v v 1 F ( v j ) j) f( v j ) here the rst inequality follos by the monotonicity of the hazar rate, an the secon by the stochastic orer assumption. Theorem 2 an in particular its Conition 2 ill also be useful hen iscussing the implementability of the simple policy in Section 5.2. Note also that Conition 2 of are non- Theorem 2 can be formulate as requiring that the functions v ecreasing in. 8 1 F (vj ) f(vj )

9 Our next result ienti es conitions on the joint istribution F (; v) that imply concavity of expecte revenue ith respect to c for all perios, as require by the above Theorem. It is convenient to introuce the joint istribution of eight an total valuation u = v, hich e enote by G(; u) ith ensity g(; u). By means of a transformation of variables, the ensities f an g are relate by g(; v) = f(; v): In particular, marginal ensities in coincie, i.e. f () = f(; v) v = g(; u) u = g (): An increasing virtual value implies that the virtual total value is increasing in u ith strictly positive erivative for any given : ^u(u; ) := u 1 G(uj) g(uj) = v 1 F (vj) f(vj)= = ^v(v; ) We rite ^u 1 (^u; ) for the inverse of ^u(u; ) ith respect to u an e ne a istribution ^G(^u; ) by both ^G(^uj) := G(^u 1 (^u; )j) for all an ^g () := g (). On the level of ^v, this correspons to ^F (^vj) = F (^v 1 (^v; )j) an ^f () = f (). Theorem 3 Assume that the conitional istribution ^G(j^u) is concave in for all ^u; that both ^g(j^u) an ^g(j^u) are boune, an that the total virtual value ^u has a nite mean. Then, in the revenue maximization problem here the esigner has complete information about ; the expecte revenue R (c; T + 1 t) is concave as a function of c for all times t: Proof. See Appenix. Example 2 A simple example here the conitions of Theorem 2 are satis e is obtaine by assuming that G(u; ) is such that u an are inepenent, u u(u) 1 G g u(u) is i erentiable ith strictly positive erivative, an G is concave 7. Conition 1 in that Theorem is satis e by Theorem 3, hile Conition 2 is satis e since by inepenence v ^v( ; ) = ^u(v; ) = ^u(v; ) = ^v(v; ) an by assumption. 5 Simple, Asymptotically Optimal Policies The optimal policy characterize above seems too sensitive to be use in practice since it requires price ajustments in every perio, an for any quantity request. Our main result in the present section suggests that hile exploiting epenency beteen an v - if there is any - may be important for revenue maximization, carefully chosen ynamics are super uous if both capacity an time go to in nity. As above, e start by focusing on the case of observable eights. We then sho that the su cient conitions 7 We also assume that the other very mil technical conitions of Theorem 3 are satis e. 9

10 ienti e in Theorem 1 are also applicable here, ensuring the implementability of the obtaine policy. Instea of solving the stochastic problem, e rst solve a simpler, suitably chosen eterministic maximization problem. The revenue obtaine in the solution to that problem provies an upper boun for the optimal expecte revenue of the stochastic problem, an suggests the use of per-unit prices that epen on, but that are constant in time. We next sho that the erive policy is asymptotically optimal also in the original stochastic problem here both capacity an time go to in nity: the ratio of expecte revenue from folloing the consiere policy over expecte revenue from the optimal Markovian policy converges to one. Moreover, there are various ays to quantify this ratio for moerately large capacities an time horizons. The basic logic hence follos a suggestion mae by Gallego an van Ryzin [7]. Hoever, our knapsack problem ith a general istribution F (; v) is substantially more complex than the moel tackle in their paper. Let us rst recall some assumptions, an introuce further notation. The marginal ensity f () an the conitional ensities f(vj) pin on the istribution of (inepenent) arriving types ( t ; v t ) T. Given, the emane per-unit price p an the probability of a request being accepte are relate by (p) = 1 F (pj). Let p () be the inverse of, an note that this is ell e ne on (; 1]. Because of monotonicity of conitional virtual values, the instantaneous (expecte) per-unit revenue functions r () := p () are strictly concave, an each one attains a unique interior maximum. Inee, p () = F (j) 1 (1 ) an hence r () = p 1 () f(p ()j) = 1 F (p ()j) p () f(p ()j) 2 r () ^v (p 1 (); ) f(p ()j) < : = ^v(p (); ); Consequently, r is strictly concave, strictly increasing up to the ; that satis es ^v(p ( ; ); ) = an strictly ecreasing from there on. 5.1 The Deterministic Problem We no formulate an auxiliary eterministic problem. Let Cap : (; 1)! (; 1) ; 7! Cap() be a measurable function. Consier the problem: Z! 1 TX max max r ( Cap() ( t ) t ) f () ; (2) ;:::;T subject to TX t f () Cap() a.s. an In ors, e analyze a problem here: 1 Cap() C: (3)

11 1. The capacity C nees to be ivie into capacities Cap(), one for each : 2. In each - subproblem, a eterministic quantity request of f () arrives in each perio, an t etermines a share (not a probability!) of this request that is accepte an sol at per-unit price p ( t ). 3. In each sub-problem, the allocate capacity over time cannot excee Cap(), an total allocate capacity in all sub-problems R 1 Cap(), cannot excee C. 4. The esigner s goal is to maximize total revenue. We call the revenue at the solution R (C; T ). As r is strictly concave an increasing up to ;, it is straightforar to verify that, given a choice Cap(); the solution to the - subproblem,! TX max r ( ( t ) t ) TX f () such that t f () Cap() ;:::;T is given by: t ; := ( ; Cap() T f () if ; else Cap() T f () Accoringly, the revenue in the -subproblem is r ( ; )T f (). (4) Proposition 2 The solution to the eterministic problem given by (2) an (3) is characterize by : 1. ^v(p ( ; ); ) = (C; T ) = const 2. t = ; = Cap() 3. T f (), R 1 Cap() = min(c; T R 1 ; f () ) Proof. See Appenix. To get an intuition for the above result, observe that the marginal increase of the optimal revenue for the -subproblem from marginally increasing Cap() is: Cap() r T f () = ^v(p ( ; ); ) if ; > Cap() T f () ; an else. Proposition 2 says that, optimally, the capacity shoul be split in such a ay that the marginal revenue from increasing Cap() is the same for all. Actually solving the problem amounts to the simple static exercise of etermining the constant (C; T ) in accorance ith the integral feasibility constraint. 11

12 The above construction is justi e by the folloing result, shoing that the optimal revenue in the eterministic problem bouns from above the optimal revenue in our original stochastic problem. Since e assume here that eights are observable, a Markovian policy for the original stochastic problem is characterize by the acceptance probabilities t t [c t ] contingent on current time t, remaining capacity c t an eight request t. Expecte revenue from policy at the beginning of perio t (i.e. hen there are (T t + 1) perios left) ith remaining capacity c t is given by: R (c t ; T t + 1) = E s=t s p s ( s s [c s ]) I fvsp s ( s s [cs])g s:t: TX s=t s I fvsp s ( s s [cs])g c t : Here, the constraint must hol almost surely hen folloing. As before, e rite R (c t ; T t+1) for the optimal revenue, i.e. the supremum of expecte revenues taken over all feasible Markovian policies. Theorem 4 For any capacity C an ealine T, it hols that R (C; T ) R (C; T ). Proof. See Appenix. 5.2 A Simple Policy for The Stochastic Problem Theorem 4 above suggests that a -contingent yet time-inepenent pricing policy may be able to yiel close to optimal revenues in the stochastic problem. To construct such a Markovian time-inepenent policy for the stochastic problem, T I ; e procee as follos: 1. Given C an T, solve the eterministic problem to obtain (C; T ), ; an thus p ; := p ( ; ) = ^v 1 ((C; T ); ). 2. In the stochastic problem charge these eight-contingent prices p ; for the entire time horizon, provie that the quantity request oes not excee the remaining capacity. Else, charge a price equal to +1 (i.e., reject the request). An important observation is that, uner the conitions of Theorem 1, the time inepenent policy T I e ne above is implementable also for the case that interests us, here eights are not observable. This follos immeiately by recalling that the eight-contingent prices p ; satisfy the equation ^v(p ( ; ); ) = (C; T ): Inee, uner the conitions of Theorem 1, the solution to this equation is monotonic in ; an hence p ; is also monotonic in ; as require for implementability. Moreover, 12

13 implementability is even satis e uner the strictly eaker Conition 2 of Theorem 2, since setting all virtual valuation threshols equal to a constant is like setting them optimally for linear an hence concave salvage values. We no etermine ho ell the time-inepenent policy constructe above performs compare to the optimal Markovian policy. We o this by comparing its expecte revenue, R T I (C; T ); ith the optimal revenue in the eterministic problem, R (C; T ); hich, as e kno by Theorem 4, provies an upper boun for the optimal revenue in the stochastic problem, R (C; T ). Theorem 5 1. For any joint istribution of values an eights, R T I (C; T ) lim C;T!1; C T =const R (C; T ) = 1 2. Assume that an v are inepenent. Then, R T I (C; T ) R (C; T ) 1 In particular, lim min(c;t )!1 R T I (C;T ) R (C;T ) = 1 p E[2 ]=E[] 2 p min(c; E[]T ) Proof. See Appenix. We have chosen to focus on these to general limit results. Various others coul be proven by similar techniques at the expense of slightly more technical e ort an possibly some further assumptions on F. As e inicate in the introuction, an interesting remark is that, since the policy T I is stationary, it oes not generate incentives to postpone arrivals even in a more complex moel here buyers are patient an can choose their arrival time. Remark 2 In a complete information knapsack moel, Lin, Lu an Yao [14] stuy policies hich start by accepting only high value requests, an then sitch-over to accepting also loer values as time goes by. They establish asymptotic optimality of such policies (ith carefully chosen sitch-over times) as available capacity an time go to in nity. In other ors, their prices are time-epenent but o not conition on the eight request. It is easy to sho that, in our incomplete information moel such policies are, in general, suboptimal. Consier rst a one-perio example here the seller has capacity 2, an here the arriving agent has either a eight request of 1 or 2 (equally likely). If the eight request is 1(2), the agent s per-unit value istributes uniformly beteen an 1 (beteen 1 an 2). The optimal mechanism in this case is as follos: if the buyer requests one unit, the seller sells it for a price of.5, an if the buyer requests to units, the seller sells each unit at a price of 1. Note that this policy is implementable since the requeste per-unit price is monotonically increasing in the eight request. The expecte revenue is 9/8. If, hoever, the seller is force to sell 13! :

14 all units at the same per-unit price ithout conitioning on the eight request, he ill charge the price of 1 for each unit, yieling an expecte revenue of 1, an thus loose 1/8 versus the optimal policy. Replicate no this problem so that there are T perios an capacity C=2T. Then, the expecte revenue from the optimal mechanism is 9/8T, hile the expecte revenue from the constraine mechanism is only T. Obviously, the constraine mechanism is not asymptotically optimal. 6 Appenix Proof of Proposition 1. an e ne for any t; c: I) =) So assume that conitions 1 an 2 are satis e q c t (; v) = ( p c t () if c t(; v) = 1 if c t(; v) = Consier then an arrival of type (; v) in perio t ith remaining capacity c: There are to cases: a) c t(; v) = 1: In particular, v p c t(). Then, truth-telling yiels utility (v p c t()). Assume that the agent reports instea ( b; bv): If c t( b; bv) = ; then the agent s utility is zero an the eviation is not pro table. Assume then that c t( b; bv) = 1: By the form of the utility function, a report of b < is never pro table. But, for b, the agent s utility is v bp c t( b) (v p c t()), here e use conition 2. Therefore, such a eviation is also not pro table. b) c t(; v) = : In particular, v p c t(). Truth-telling yiels here utility of zero. Assume that the agent reports instea ( b; bv): If c t( b; bv) = ; then the agent s utility remains zero, an the eviation is not pro table. Assume then that c t( b; bv) = 1: By the form of the utility function, a report of b < is never pro table. Thus, consier the case here b. In this case, the agent s utility is v bp c t( b) (v p c t()) ; here e use conition 2. Therefore, such a eviation is also not pro table. II) (= Consier no an implementable, eterministic an Markovian allocation policy f c tg t;c. Assume rst, by contraiction, that conition 1 in the statement of the Proposition is not satis e. Then, there exist (; v) an (; v ) such that v > v, c t(; v) = 1 an c t(; v ) = : We obtain the chain of inequalities v qt c (; v) > v qt c (; v) qt c (; v ) here the secon inequality follos by incentive compatibility for type (; v). This shos that a eviation to a report (; v) is pro table for type (; v ); a contraiction to implementability. Therefore, conition 1 must hol. In particular, note that for any to types ho have the same eight request, (; v) an (; v ), if both are accepte, i.e. c t(; v) = c t(; v ) = 1; the payment must be the same (otherise the type hich nees to make the higher payment oul eviate an report the other type). Denote this payment by rt(). c Note also that any to types (; v) an ( ; v ) such that c t(; v) = c t( ; v ) = must also make the same 14

15 payment (otherise the type that nees to make the higher payment oul eviate an report the other type) an enote this payment by s. Assume no, by contraiction, that conition 2 oes not hol. Then there exist an such that > but p c t( ) < p c t(): In particular, p c t( ) < 1; an therefore p c t( ) < 1: Assume rst that p c t() < 1. We have p c t( ) rt( c ) = p c t() rt() c = s because, by incentive compatibility, both types (; p c t()) an ( ; p c t( )) must be ini erent beteen getting their request an not getting it. Since by assumption p c t( ) < p c t(); e obtain that rt( c ) < rt(): c Consier no a type (; v) for hich v > p c t(). By reporting truthfully, this type gets utility v rt(); c hile by eviating to ( ; v) he gets utility v rt( c ) > v rt(); c a contraiction to incentive compatibility. Assume no that p c t() is in nite, an therefore p c t() is in nite. Consier a type ( ; v) here v > p c t( ): The utility of this type is v rt( c ) > p c t( ) rt( c ) = s. In particular, rt( c ) must be nite. By reporting truthfully, a type (; v) gets utility s, hile by eviating to a report of ( ; v) he gets v rt( c ): For v large enough, e obtain v rt( c ) > s; a contraiction to implementability. Thus, conition 2 must hol an, in particular, the payment rt() c is monotonic in : Proof of Theorem 1. Let <. We nee to sho that p c t() p c t( ) : If p c t() p c t( ) the result is clear. Assume then that p c t() > p c t( ): We obtain the folloing chain of inequalities: 1 F (p c t ()j) f(p c t()j) 1 F (p c t ()j) f(p c t()j) 1 F (p c t ( )j) f(p c t( )j) 1 F (p c t ( )j ) f(p c t( )j ) 1 F (p c t( )j ) f(p c t( )j ) 1 F (p c t( )j ) f(p c t( )j ) ; here the secon inequality follos by the monotonicity of the hazar rate, an the thir by the hazar rate orering conition. Since R (c ; T t) is monotonically ecreasing in, e obtain that p c t() 1 F (p c t()j) p c f(p t( 1 F (p c ) t( )j ), c t()j) f(p c t( )j ) 1 F (p p c t() p c t( c ) t ()j) 1 F (p c t ( )j ) f(p c t()j) f(p c t( )j ) here the last inequality follos by the erivation above. Hence p c t() p c t( ) as esire. 15

16 Proof of Theorem 2. For any concave function, an for any x < y < z in its omain, the ell knon "Three Chor Lemma" asserts that (y) y (x) x (z) z (x) x (z) z (y) y Consier then < an let x = c < y = c < z = c: For the case of a concave revenue, the Lemma yiels then: R (c ; T t) R (c ; T t) We obtain in particular R (c; T t) R (c ; T t) R (c; T t) R (c ; T t) : hich yiels p c t( ) 1 F (p c t( )j ) f(p c t( )j ) R (c; T t) R (c ; T t) = R (c; T t) R (c ; T t) = p c t() 1 F (p c t()j) ; f(p c t()j) p c t( ) 1 F (p c t( )j ) f(p c t( )j ) p c t() 1 F (p c t()j) f(p c t()j) pc t() 1 F ( p c t()j ) f( p c t()j ) here the last inequality follos by the conition in the statement of the Theorem. Since virtual values are increasing, this yiels p c t( ) p c t(), p c t( ) p c t() as esire. For the proof of Theorem 3, e rst nee a Lemma on maximization of expecte elfare uner complete information. The result appears (ithout proof) in Papastavrou, Rajagopalan an Kleyegt [18]. Lemma 1. Assume that the total value u has nite mean, an that both g(ju) an g(ju) are boune an continuous. Consier the allocation policy that maximizes expecte elfare uner complete information (i..e, upon arrival the agent s type is reveale to the esigner). If G(ju) is concave in for all u; then the optimal expecte elfare, enote Ut c is tice continuously i erentiable an concave in the remaining capacity c for all perios t T. Proof. Note that, for notational convenience throughout this proof, e inex optimal expecte elfare by the current time t an not by perios remaining to ealine. By stanar arguments, the optimal policy for this unconstraine ynamic optimization problem is eterministic an Markovian, an Ut c is non-ecreasing in remaining capacity c by a simple strategy uplication argument. Moreover, the optimal policy can be characterize by eight threshols t(u) c c : If c remains at time t an a 16

17 request hose acceptance oul generate value u arrives, then it is accepte if an only if c t(u). If U c t+1 u, then the eight threshol must satisfy the ini erence conition u = U c t+1 U c c t (u) t+1 : (5) Otherise, e have t(u) c = c. We no prove the Lemma by backar inuction. At time t = T, i.e. in the ealine perio, it hols that U c T = G(cju)u g u (u) u: This is concave in c because all G(cju) are concave by assumption, because u g u (u) is positive, an because the istribution of u has a nite mean. Since both g(ju) an g(ju) are boune an continuous, U c T is also tice continuously i erentiable. Suppose no that the Lemma has been proven on to time t + 1. The optimal expecte elfare at t provie that capacity c remains may be ritten as: " U c t = ug( c t(u)ju) + Z c t (u) U c t+1 g(ju) + (1 G( c t(u)ju))u c t+1 g u (u) u: (6) We procee to sho concavity ith respect to c of the term in brackets, for all u. This in turn implies concavity of Ut c an hence, ith a short aitional argument for i erentiability, is su cient to conclue the inuction step. We istinguish the cases u > Ut+1 c for hich the ini erence conition (5) oes not hol, an u Ut+1 c for hich it oes. For both cases, e emonstrate that the secon erivative (one-sie if necessary) of the bracket term ith respect to c is non-positive, an thus establish global concavity. Case 1: u > Ut+1. c The bracket term becomes ug(cju) + R c U c t+1 g(ju) + (1 G(cju))Ut+1. c By continuity of Ut+1, c this representation also hols in a small interval aroun c. We n c ug(cju) + = ug(cju) + U c t+1 g(ju) + (1 G(cju))U c t+1 c U t+1 c g(ju) + Ut+1 g(cju) g(cju) U c t+1 + (1 G(cju)) c U c t+1 = (u U c t+1)g(cju) + c U t+1 c g(ju) + (1 G(cju)) c U t+1 c 17

18 an 2 ug(cju) + c 2 U c t+1 g(ju) + (1 G(cju))U c t+1 = (u U c t+1)g (cju) g(cju) c U c t U t+1 2 c U c 2 t+1 g(ju) = g(cju) g(cju) c U c t+1 + (1 G(cju)) 2 c 2 U c t+1: (7) The last term is non-positive by the concavity of U c t+1, the rst term is non-positive because u > U c t+1 an because G(cju) has a non-increasing ensity by assumption. In aition, g(cju) c U c t+1 is non-negative, an hence (7) is boune from above by 2 c U c 2 t+1 g(ju) + g(cju) U t+1 = But R c 2 U c c 2 t+1 g(ju) may be boune from above by g(cju) R c of the ecreasing ensity an because 2 U c c 2 t+1. Thus, 2 ug(cju) + U c c 2 t+1 g(ju) + (1 G(cju))Ut+1 c 2 g(cju) c U c 2 t+1 + U t+1 2 = g(cju) U c 2 t+1 + U t+1 = = c U t+1 c : 2 U c c 2 c U t+1 c c U t+1 c t+1 because = : (8) Case 2: u U c t+1. Here u = U c t+1 U c c t (u) t+1. Consequently, the bracket term in (6) becomes U c t+1 U c c t (u) t+1 G( c t(u)ju) + Z c t (u) U c t+1 g(ju) : (9) Before computing its rst an secon erivatives, e i erentiate the ientity u = Ut+1 c U c c t (u) t+1 to obtain an expression for c c t(u) (erivative from the right if u = U c t+1): = c U c t+1 U t+1 =c c t (u) 1 c c t(u) : Since inee U t+1 > in our setup ith strictly positive ensities, this implies c c t(u) = U t+1 U c =c c t (u) c t+1 : (1) U t+1 =c By concavity of U c t+1, its erivative is non-increasing an hence the ientity (1) yiels c t (u) 18

19 in particular c c t(u). We no compute the erivatives of (9): " Ut+1 c U c c t (u) t+1 G( c c t(u)ju) + = c U c t+1 U t+1 =c c t (u) Z c t (u) U c 1 + U c c t (u) t+1 g( c t(u)ju) c c t(u) + (1) = c U c t+1 c U t+1 c G(t(u)ju) c + = c U c t+1(1 G( c t(u)ju)) + Thus, " 2 U c c 2 t+1 U c c t (u) t+1 G(t(u)ju) c + Z c t (u) Z c t (u) t+1 g(ju) c c t(u) Z c t (u) Z c t (u) U c G( c t(u)ju) U c c t (u) t+1 g( c t(u)ju) c c t(u) c U t+1 c g(ju) c U t+1 c g(ju) c U t+1 c g(ju) : t+1 g(ju) = 2 c U t+1(1 c G( c t(u)ju)) 2 c U t+1 c g(t(u)ju) c c c t(u) + U t+1 =c c t (u) g(c t(u)ju) Z c t (u) 2 c c t(u) + c U c 2 t+1 g(ju) g(t(u)ju) c Z c c t(u) U t+1 c =c c t (u) c U t+1 c t (u) 2 + U c 2 t+1 g(ju) : For the nal inequality e use concavity of Ut+1, c as ell as 2 t+1 = 2 t+1. Noting that (1) implies that c c t(u) 1 an once more using concavity of Ut+1, c e may boun the rst term from above. Since g(ju) is non-increasing in, e can also boun the secon term to obtain: " 2 Z c U c c 2 t+1 U c c t (u) t+1 G(t(u)ju) c t (u) + Ut+1 c g(ju) (11) g( c t(u)ju) U t+1 =c c t (u) Z c c U t+1 c t (u) + 2 c 2 U c 2 U c t+1! 2 U c = : Taken together, (8) an (11) establish concavity of the integran in (6) ith respect to c. This implies that Ut c is concave. Having a secon look at the computations just one reveals that the integran in (6) has a kink in the secon erivative at u = Ut+1. c Hoever, this event has measure zero for any given c, so that e also get that Ut c is tice continuously i erentiable. This completes the inuction step. Proof of Theorem 3. The main iea of the proof is to translate the problem of setting revenue-maximizing prices hen is observable into the problem of maximizing 19

20 elfare ith respect to virtual values (rather than the values themselves), an then to use Lemma 1. To begin ith, note that there is a ual ay to escribe the policy that maximizes expecte elfare uner complete information. In the proof of Lemma 1, e characterize it by optimal eight threshols t(u). c Alternatively, given any requeste quantity, (not greater than the remaining c) e may set a valuation per unit threshol vt c (). Requests above this valuation are accepte, those belo are not. Optimal such threshols are characterize by the Bellman-type conition: v c t () = U c t+1 U c t+1 : (12) Thus, one ay of riting the optimal expecte elfare uner complete information is: U c t = + vf(vj) v f () vt c() (1 F (v c t ()j))ut+1 c + F (vt c ()j)ut+1 c f () : (13) In contrast, the optimal expecte revenue ith complete information about but incomplete information about v satis es: R (c; T + 1 t) = + p c t() (1 F (p c t()j)) f () (14) [(1 F (p c t()j))r (c ; T t) + F (p c t()j)r (c; T t)] f () ; here p c t() are the per-unit prices from (1). We rephrase this in terms of ^F, hose e nition require monotonicity of virtual values. Setting ^v c t () := ^v(p c t(); ) e have on the one han: F (p c t()j) = ^F (^v c t ()j): On the other han: p c t() (1 F (p c t()j)) = = = p c t () [v f(vj) (1 F (vj))] v ^v(v; ) ^f(^v(v; )j) ^v(v; ) v p c t () v ^v c t () ^v ^f(^vj) ^v: Plugging this an the ientities for the marginal ensities in into (14), e obtain: R (c; T + 1 t) = ^v ^f(^vj) ^v ^f () ^v t () 1 h + (1 ^F (^v c t ()j))r (c ; T t) + ^F (^v t c ()j)r (c; T t)i ^f () : 2

21 Comparing this ith (13), it follos that maximizing expecte revenue hen is observable is equivalent to maximizing expecte elfare ith respect to the istribution of eight an conitional virtual valuation (note the ientical zero bounary values at T + 1). Invoking Lemma 1 applie to ^G, e see that R (c; T + 1 t) is concave ith respect to c for all t (note that the fact that the support of virtual valuations contains also negative numbers oes not matter for the argument of Lemma 1). Proof of Proposition 2. The Proposition is an immeiate consequence of the characterization (4) of optimal solutions for the -subproblems given Cap(), an of a straightforar variational argument ensuring that marginal revenues from marginal increase of Cap() must be constant almost surely in. Proof of Theorem 4. We nee to istinguish to cases: Case 1: Assume that C > T R 1 ; f (). In this case, (C; T ) = an R (C; T ) = T R 1 r ( ; )f (). We also kno that R (C; T ) R (+1; T ); here R (+1; T ) enotes the optimal expecte revenue from a stochastic problem ithout any capacity constraint. But, for such a problem, the optimal Markovian policy maximizes at each perio the instantaneous expecte revenue upon observing t, t r t (): That is, the optimal policy sets t [+1] = ;. Thus, R (C; T ) R (+1; T ) = T t r ( ; ) f () = R (C; T ): Case 2: Assume no that C T R 1 ; f (). For, consier the unconstraine maximization problem max Cap() r Cap() T f () The Euler-Lagrange equation is T f () + r Cap() T f () C Cap() =. Hence, if e rite R (C; T; ) for the optimal value of the above problem, an if e let = (C; T ) here (C; T ) is the constant from Proposition 2, then the solution equals the one of the constraine eterministic problem. In particular R 1 Cap() = C, an R (C; T; (C; T )) = R (C; T ). Recall that for the stochastic problem, an for any Markovian policy e have an e ne R (C; T ) = E t p t ( t t [c t ]) I fvtp t( t t [c t])g R (C; T; (C; T )) = R (C; T ) + (C; T ) C E t I fvtp t( t t [c t])g Since for any policy that is amissible in the original problem, it hols that TX t I fvtp t( t t [c t])g C a:s:; 21 ;! :

22 e have R (C; T ) R (C; T; (C; T )). We ill sho belo that, for arbitrary (hich satis es the capacity constraint or not), it hols that: R (C; T; (C; T )) R (C; T; (C; T )): (15) This yiels for any that is amissible in the original problem: R (C; T ) R (C; T; (C; T )) R (C; T; (C; T )) = R (C; T ): Taking the supremum over conclues then the proof for the secon case. It remains to prove (15). The argument uses the ltration ff t g T of - algebras containing information prior to time t ( in particular the value of c t ) an in aition the currently observe t. R (C; T; (C; T )) = E t (p t ( t t [c t ]) (C; T )) I fvtp t( t t [c t])g = E E h t (p t ( t t [c t ]) (C; T )) I fvtp t( t t = E t (p t ( t t [c t ]) (C; T )) E hi fvtp t( t = E t (r t ( t t [c t ]) (C; T ) t t [c t ]) t + (C; T ) C i [c t])gjf t i [c t])gjf t + (C; T ) C + (C; T ) C + (C; T ) C E t r t ( t; ) (C; T ) t; + (C; T ) C = E (t) T t r t ( t; ) (C; T ) t; + (C; T ) C = T (r ( ; ) (C; T ) ; ) f () + (C; T ) C = R (C; T; (C; T )): For the inequality, e have use that ; maximizes r () (C; T ). For the proof of Theorem 5, e rst nee a Lemma: Lemma 2 Let R T I (C; T ) be the revenue obtaine form the stationary policy T I : Let ( e t ; ev t ) T be an inepenent copy of the process ( t ; v t ) T. It hols that: 1. R T I (C; T ) = E (t) T r t ( t; ) t 1 P " t 1 X s=1 e s I fevsp es; g > C t! (16) : 22

23 2. R T I (C; T ) R (C; T ) 1 P T R 1 r ( ; ) min 1; (17) (t 1) 2 I ((T t+1) ) 2 f(t t+1) g + I f>(t t+1) g f () T R 1 r ( ; )f () here := min(c;t R 1 ; f () ), an here 2 T := E[2 I fvp g] R 2 ; = 1 2 ; f () 2. Proof. 1. R T I (C; T ) may be ritten as: R T I (C; T ) = E (t;vt) T = E (t) T r t ( t; ) t E (t;vt) T p t; t I fvtp t ; g I f P t 1 s=1 s I fvsp s; g C tg p t; t I fvtp t ; g I f P t 1 s=1 s I fvsp s; g > C tg In orer to simplify the secon term, e use the fact that v t an ( s ; v s ) t s=1 1 are inepenent conitional on t : p t; t I fvtp t ; g I P f t 1 s=1 s I fvsp s; g > C tg h i = E (t;vt) T E p t; t I fvtp t ; g I P f t 1 s=1 s I fvsp s; g > C tg j t E (t;v t) T = E (t;vt) T = E (t;vt) T p t; t t; P = E (t) T r t ( t; ) t P This establishes equation (16). p t; t E I fvtp t ; gj t E hi f P t 1 s=1 s I fvsp s; g > C tg j t " t 1 X s=1 " t 1 e s I fevsp es; g > C t X e s I fevsp es; g > C t : s=1 2. Recall that R (C; T ) = T R 1 r ( ; )f (). Observe furthermore that ; epens on C an T only through the ratio Ce, here T Ce = min(c; T R 1 via E[I fvp ; g] = R 1 ; f () = Ce P " t 1 X s=1 = P e s I fevsp es; g > C t P " t 1 X s=1 = T. Observe rst that " Xt 1 e s I fevsp es; g > T t s=1 e s I fevsp es; g (t 1) > (T t + 1) t 23 : i ; f () ),

24 We trivially boun the last expression by 1 if (T t + 1) t, an otherise use Chebychev s inequality to euce " t 1 X P e s I fevsp es; g (t 1) > (T t + 1) t s=1 2 P 4 E Xt 1 s=1! 2 e s I fevsp es; g (t 1) > ((T t + 1) t ) 2 5 h Pt 1 s=1 e s I fevsp es; g (t 1) 2 i ((T t + 1) t ) 2 = 3 (t 1) 2 ((T t + 1) t ) 2 : As e are bouning a probability, e can replace this estimate by the trivial boun 1 again henever this is better, i.e. if t is smaller than but close to (T t + 1). Thus, E (t;vt) T TX p t; t I fvtp t ; g I f P t 1 s=1 s I fvsp s; g > C tg r ( ; ) (t 1) 2 min 1; I ((T t + 1) ) 2 f(t t+1) g + I f>(t t+1) g Finally, iviing by R (C; T ) yiels the esire estimate. Proof of Theorem The starting point is the estimate from (17). Note that r ( ; )f () is an integrable upper boun for r ( ; (t 1) 2 ) min 1; I ((T t + 1) ) 2 f(t t+1) g + I f>(t t+1) g f (): Moreover, for xe, for arbitrary 2 (; 1) an for t T e have < (1 eventually as T; C! 1, C = const. Moreover, T (t 1) 2 ((T t + 1) ) T 2! ; as T! 1: 2 ((1 )T ) 2 )T f () : The Dominate Convergence Theorem implies then that r ( ; (t 1) 2 ) min 1; I ((T t + 1) ) 2 f(t t+1) g + I f>(t t+1) g f ()! ; in the consiere limit, for arbitrary 2 (; 1) an for t T. Consequently, also the term that is subtracte in the estimate (17) converges to zero. 2. If an v are inepenent, all the ; for i erent coincie, as o the ;. Call them an, respectively. We have then "! TX R T I (C; T ) = p( )E min C; t I fvtp( )g 2 TX = p( )E 4 t I fvtp( )g 24 TX t I fvtp( )g C! + 3 5

25 We use no the folloing estimate for E[(X k) + ], here X is a ranom variable ith mean m an variance 2 an here k is a constant: p E[(X k) (k m) ] 2 (k m) : 2 Note that by inepenence E t I fvtp( )g V ar t I fvtp( )g If T E[] > C an hence if = R CP (C; T ) R (C; T ) p( ) = E[]T ; = T E[( I fvp( )g )2 ] E[] 2 ( ) 2 = T E[ 2 ] E[] 2 ( ) 2 C this yiels: T E[] q T E[ 2 ] 2 = R (C; T ) 1 If T E[] C an hence if =, then C E PT + E t I fvtp( )g C p 2. Thus, 2 R T I (C; T ) R (C; T ) p( ) p T E( 2 ) 2 h PT = R (C; T ) 1 p! E[2 ]=E[] 2 p : C i t I fvtp( )g, so that p! E[2 ]=E[] 2 p : E()T Hence, e can conclue that: R T I (C; T ) R (C; T ) 1 p E[2 ]=E[] 2 p min(c; T E[]))! : References [1] Albright S.C. (1974): "Optimal Sequential Assignments ith Ranom Arrival Times", Management Science 21 (1), [2] Armstrong, M. (1996): Multiprouct Nonlinear Pricing, Econometrica 64, [3] Bitran, G.R. an Monschein, S.V. (1997): "Perioic Pricing of Seasonal Proucts in Retailing", Management Science 43 (1),

Preferences, Prices, and Performance in Monopoly and Duopoly

Preferences, Prices, and Performance in Monopoly and Duopoly Preferences, Prices, an Performance in Monopoly an Duopoly Yongmin Chen y an Michael H. Rioran z November 20, 2009 Abstract. This paper takes the new approach of using a copula to characterize consumer

More information

An investment strategy with optimal sharpe ratio

An investment strategy with optimal sharpe ratio The 22 n Annual Meeting in Mathematics (AMM 2017) Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science Chiang Mai University, Chiang Mai, Thailan An investment strategy with optimal sharpe ratio S. Jansai a,

More information

International monetary cooperation in a world of imperfect information

International monetary cooperation in a world of imperfect information International monetary cooperation in a orl of imperfect information Kang Yong Tan University of Oxfor Misa Tanaka Bank of Englan Not to be cite or istribute ithout authors prior persmission April 7, 007

More information

RULES OF ORIGIN AS A STRATEGIC POLICY TOWARDS MULTINATIONAL FIRMS. Masaru Umemoto. Working Paper Series Vol November 2001

RULES OF ORIGIN AS A STRATEGIC POLICY TOWARDS MULTINATIONAL FIRMS. Masaru Umemoto. Working Paper Series Vol November 2001 RULES OF ORIGIN AS A STRATEGIC POLICY TOARDS MULTINATIONAL FIRMS Masaru Umemoto Research Assistant Professor, ICSEAD oring Paper Series Vol. -33 November The vies expresse in this publication are those

More information

OPTIMAL DYNAMIC MECHANISM DESIGN WITH DEADLINES

OPTIMAL DYNAMIC MECHANISM DESIGN WITH DEADLINES OPTIMAL DYNAMIC MECHANISM DESIGN WITH DEADLINES KONRAD MIERENDORFF Abstract. A seller maximizes revenue from selling an object in a ynamic environment, with buyers that iffer in their patience: Each buyer

More information

Modes of Convergence

Modes of Convergence Moes of Convergence Electrical Engineering 126 (UC Berkeley Spring 2018 There is only one sense in which a sequence of real numbers (a n n N is sai to converge to a limit. Namely, a n a if for every ε

More information

Hyperbolic Discounting and Uniform Savings Floors

Hyperbolic Discounting and Uniform Savings Floors This work is istribute as a Discussion Paper by the STANFORD INSTITUTE FOR ECONOMIC POLICY RESEARCH SIEPR Discussion Paper No. 04-34 Hyperbolic Discounting an Uniform Savings Floors By Benjamin A. Malin

More information

Lecture Notes 1

Lecture Notes 1 4.45 Lecture Notes Guido Lorenzoni Fall 2009 A portfolio problem To set the stage, consider a simple nite horizon problem. A risk averse agent can invest in two assets: riskless asset (bond) pays gross

More information

REAL OPTION MODELING FOR VALUING WORKER FLEXIBILITY

REAL OPTION MODELING FOR VALUING WORKER FLEXIBILITY REAL OPTION MODELING FOR VALUING WORKER FLEXIBILITY Harriet Black Nembhar Davi A. Nembhar Ayse P. Gurses Department of Inustrial Engineering University of Wisconsin-Maison 53 University Avenue Maison,

More information

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON Av. Micro Theory, ECON 60-090 Assignment 4 Ansers, Fall 00 Due: Wenesay October 3 th by 5pm Directions: Anser each question as completely as possible. You may ork in a group consisting of up to 3 members

More information

CDO TRANCHE PRICING BASED ON THE STABLE LAW VOLUME II: R ELAXING THE LHP. Abstract

CDO TRANCHE PRICING BASED ON THE STABLE LAW VOLUME II: R ELAXING THE LHP. Abstract CDO TRANCHE PRICING BASED ON THE STABLE LAW VOLUME II: R ELAXING THE ASSUMPTION German Bernhart XAIA Investment GmbH Sonnenstraße 9, 833 München, Germany german.bernhart@xaia.com First Version: July 26,

More information

A NOTE ON THE DYNAMIC ROLE OF MONOPOLISTIC COMPETITION IN THE MONETARY ECONOMY. abstract

A NOTE ON THE DYNAMIC ROLE OF MONOPOLISTIC COMPETITION IN THE MONETARY ECONOMY. abstract A NOTE ON THE DYNAMIC ROLE OF MONOPOLISTIC COMPETITION IN THE MONETARY ECONOMY abstract In the new Keynesian economics, monopolistic competition plays an important role. Much static research is base on

More information

Preferences, Prices, and Performance in Multiproduct Industries

Preferences, Prices, and Performance in Multiproduct Industries Preferences, Prices, an Performance in Multiprouct Inustries Yongmin Chen y an Michael H. Rioran z July 27, 2010 Abstract: This paper evelops a new approach to iscrete choice eman for multiprouct inustries,

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PROFIT SHIFTING AND TRADE AGREEMENTS IN IMPERFECTLY COMPETITIVE MARKETS. Kyle Bagwell Robert W. Staiger

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PROFIT SHIFTING AND TRADE AGREEMENTS IN IMPERFECTLY COMPETITIVE MARKETS. Kyle Bagwell Robert W. Staiger NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PROFIT SHIFTING AND TRADE AGREEMENTS IN IMPERFECTLY COMPETITIVE MARKETS Kyle Bagwell Robert W. Staiger Working Paper 14803 http://www.nber.org/papers/w14803 NATIONAL BUREAU OF

More information

Why Has Swedish Stock Market Volatility Increased?

Why Has Swedish Stock Market Volatility Increased? Why Has Seish Stock Market Volatility Increase? by John Hassler Institute for International Economic Stuies This revision: May 29, 1995 Preliminary Abstract Is the increase volatility on the Seish stock

More information

Abstract Stanar Risk Aversion an the Deman for Risky Assets in the Presence of Backgroun Risk We consier the eman for state contingent claims in the p

Abstract Stanar Risk Aversion an the Deman for Risky Assets in the Presence of Backgroun Risk We consier the eman for state contingent claims in the p Stanar Risk Aversion an the Deman for Risky Assets in the Presence of Backgroun Risk Günter Franke 1, Richar C. Stapleton 2, an Marti G. Subrahmanyam. 3 November 2000 1 Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaften

More information

Introduction to Financial Derivatives

Introduction to Financial Derivatives 55.444 Introuction to Financial Derivatives Week of December n, 3 he Greeks an Wrap-Up Where we are Previously Moeling the Stochastic Process for Derivative Analysis (Chapter 3, OFOD) Black-Scholes-Merton

More information

Dynamic Pricing through Customer Discounts for Optimizing Multi-Class Customers Demand Fulfillment

Dynamic Pricing through Customer Discounts for Optimizing Multi-Class Customers Demand Fulfillment Dynamic Pricing through Customer Discounts for Optimizing ulti-class Customers Deman Fulfillment Qing Ding Panos Kouvelis an Joseph ilner# John. Olin School of Business Washington University St. Louis,

More information

Dynamic Accumulation Model for the Second Pillar of the Slovak Pension System

Dynamic Accumulation Model for the Second Pillar of the Slovak Pension System UDC: 368.914(437.6) JEL classification: C1, E27, G11, G23 Keywors: ynamic stochastic programming; fune pillar; utility function; Bellman equation; Slovak pension system; risk aversion; pension portfolio

More information

The Principal-Agent Problem

The Principal-Agent Problem The Principal-Agent Problem Class Notes A principal (she) hires an agent (he) or more than one agent for one perio. Agents effort levels provie a revenue to the principal, ho pays a age to each agent.

More information

Numerical solution of conservation laws applied to the Shallow Water Wave Equations

Numerical solution of conservation laws applied to the Shallow Water Wave Equations Numerical solution of conservation laws applie to the Shallow Water Wave Equations Stephen G Roberts Mathematical Sciences Institute, Australian National University Upate January 17, 2013 (base on notes

More information

CROSS-BORDER SHOPPING FROM SMALL TO LARGE COUNTRIES

CROSS-BORDER SHOPPING FROM SMALL TO LARGE COUNTRIES Copenhagen Business School Solbjerg Plas 3 DK-2000 Freeriksberg LEFIC WORKING PAPER 2002-06 CROSS-BORDER SHOPPING FROM SMALL TO LARGE COUNTRIES Søren Bo Nielsen www.cbs.k/lefic Cross-borer shopping from

More information

Liquidity Hoarding 1

Liquidity Hoarding 1 Liquiity Hoaring Douglas Gale New York University Tanju Yorulmazer 3 Feeral Reserve Bank of New York 9 August, The views expresse here are those of the authors an o not necessarily represent the views

More information

Repos, Fire Sales, and Bankruptcy Policy

Repos, Fire Sales, and Bankruptcy Policy Repos, Fire Sales, an Bankruptcy Policy Gaetano Antinolfi Francesca Carapella Charles Kahn Antoine Martin Davi Mills E Nosal Preliminary an Incomplete May 25, 2012 Abstract The events from the 2007-2009

More information

Appendix. Confidence Banking and Strategic Default. Guillermo Ordoñez. University of Pennsylvania and NBER

Appendix. Confidence Banking and Strategic Default. Guillermo Ordoñez. University of Pennsylvania and NBER Appenix Confience Banking an Strategic Default Guillermo Oroñez University of Pennsylvania an NBER 1 Proofs 1.1 Proof of Proposition 1 Since s ( ) is the signal that makes a goo firm with a given reputation

More information

INVESTMENT PERSPECTIVES ON THE INTERCONNECTION OF ISOLATED SYSTEMS WITH THE MAINLAND GRID: CRETE CASE STUDY

INVESTMENT PERSPECTIVES ON THE INTERCONNECTION OF ISOLATED SYSTEMS WITH THE MAINLAND GRID: CRETE CASE STUDY INVESTMENT PERSPECTIVES ON THE INTERCONNECTION OF ISOLATED SYSTEMS WITH THE MAINLAND GRID: CRETE CASE STUDY Emmanouil Loukarakis, Konstantinos Kalaitzakis, Eftichios Koutroulis, Georgios Stavrakakis Electronic

More information

A Costless Way to Increase Equity

A Costless Way to Increase Equity A Costless Way to Increase Equity Raphael Flore October 27, 2016 Abstract This paper complements stanar theories of optimal capital structure by allowing firms to invest in the financial markets in which

More information

Introduction to Financial Derivatives

Introduction to Financial Derivatives 55.444 Introuction to Financial Derivatives Week of December 3 r, he Greeks an Wrap-Up Where we are Previously Moeling the Stochastic Process for Derivative Analysis (Chapter 3, OFOD) Black-Scholes-Merton

More information

CARDIFF BUSINESS SCHOOL WORKING PAPER SERIES

CARDIFF BUSINESS SCHOOL WORKING PAPER SERIES CARDIFF BUSINESS SCHOOL WORKING PAPER SERIES Cariff Economics Working Papers Cemil Selcuk Motivate Sellers in the Housing Market E2010/2 Cariff Business School Cariff University Colum Drive Cariff CF10

More information

1. An insurance company models claim sizes as having the following survival function. 25(x + 1) (x 2 + 2x + 5) 2 x 0. S(x) =

1. An insurance company models claim sizes as having the following survival function. 25(x + 1) (x 2 + 2x + 5) 2 x 0. S(x) = ACSC/STAT 373, Actuarial Moels I Further Probability with Applications to Actuarial Science WINTER 5 Toby Kenney Sample Final Eamination Moel Solutions This Sample eamination has more questions than the

More information

A GENERALIZED COUPON COLLECTOR PROBLEM

A GENERALIZED COUPON COLLECTOR PROBLEM J. Appl. Prob. 48, 08 094 (20) Printe in Englan Applie Probability Trust 20 A GENERALIZED COUPON COLLECTOR PROBLEM WEIYU XU an A. KEVIN TANG, Cornell University Abstract This paper presents an analysis

More information

A Game Theoretic Model of Deposit Contracts between the Bank and the Depositor - Extend Study on the Economic Analysis of Bank Run

A Game Theoretic Model of Deposit Contracts between the Bank and the Depositor - Extend Study on the Economic Analysis of Bank Run wwwscieuca/ijfr International Journal of Financial Research Vol 5, No 3; 04 A Game Theoretic Moel of Deposit Contracts between the Bank an the Depositor - Exten Stuy on the Economic Analysis of Bank Run

More information

Equity Justi cations for Universal Service Obligations

Equity Justi cations for Universal Service Obligations Equity Justi cations for Universal Service Obligations Jean-Christophe Pouou an Michel Rolan yz January 29, 206 Abstract Equity is often invoke as a possible justi cation for the imposition of universal

More information

LABELLING BY A FOR-PROFIT CERTIFIER

LABELLING BY A FOR-PROFIT CERTIFIER LABELLING BY A FOR-PROFIT CERTIFIER IBRAHIMA BARRY OLIVIER BONROY PAOLO G. GARELLA Working Paper n. 2014-07 GIUGNO 2014 DIPARTIMENTO DI ECONOMIA, MANAGEMENT E METODI QUANTITATIVI Via Conservatorio 7 20122

More information

An Evaluation of Shareholder Activism

An Evaluation of Shareholder Activism An Evaluation of Shareholer Activism Barbara G. Katz Stern School of Business, New York University 44 W. 4th St., New York, NY 10012 bkatz@stern.nyu.eu; tel: 212 998 0865; fax: 212 995 4218 corresponing

More information

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies Harris Schlesinger Department of Finance, University of Alabama, USA Center of Finance & Econometrics, University of Konstanz, Germany E-mail: hschlesi@cba.ua.edu

More information

Bailouts, Time Inconsistency and Optimal Regulation

Bailouts, Time Inconsistency and Optimal Regulation Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Research Department Sta Report November 2009 Bailouts, Time Inconsistency and Optimal Regulation V. V. Chari University of Minnesota and Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis

More information

Allocative E ciency, Mark-ups, and the Welfare Gains from Trade

Allocative E ciency, Mark-ups, and the Welfare Gains from Trade Allocative E ciency, Mark-ups, an the Welfare Gains from Trae Thomas J. Holmes Wen-Tai Hsu Sanghoon Lee July 22, 23 Abstract This paper evelops an ine of allocative e ciency that epens upon the istribution

More information

Measuring the Wealth of Nations: Income, Welfare and Sustainability in Representative-Agent Economies

Measuring the Wealth of Nations: Income, Welfare and Sustainability in Representative-Agent Economies Measuring the Wealth of Nations: Income, Welfare and Sustainability in Representative-Agent Economies Geo rey Heal and Bengt Kristrom May 24, 2004 Abstract In a nite-horizon general equilibrium model national

More information

New Trade Models, New Welfare Implications

New Trade Models, New Welfare Implications New rae Moels, New Welfare Implications he Harvar community has mae this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Melitz, Marc J., an Stephen J.

More information

Exchange Rate Risk Sharing Contract with Risk-averse Firms

Exchange Rate Risk Sharing Contract with Risk-averse Firms 03 International Conference on Avances in Social Science, Humanities, an anagement ASSH 03 Exchange ate isk Sharing Contract with isk-averse Firms LIU Yang, A Yong-kai, FU Hong School of anagement an Economics,

More information

Capacity Constraint OPRE 6377 Lecture Notes by Metin Çakanyıldırım Compiled at 15:30 on Tuesday 22 nd August, 2017

Capacity Constraint OPRE 6377 Lecture Notes by Metin Çakanyıldırım Compiled at 15:30 on Tuesday 22 nd August, 2017 apacity onstraint OPRE 6377 Lecture Notes by Metin Çakanyılırım ompile at 5:30 on Tuesay 22 n August, 207 Solve Exercises. [Marginal Opportunity ost of apacity for Deman with onstant Elasticity] We suppose

More information

Option Pricing for Inventory Management and Control

Option Pricing for Inventory Management and Control 29 American Control Conference Hyatt Regency Riverfront, St. Louis, MO, USA June 1-12, 29 ThB7.3 Option Pricing for Inventory Management an Control Bryant Angelos, McKay Heasley, an Jeffrey Humpherys Abstract

More information

ECON Micro Foundations

ECON Micro Foundations ECON 302 - Micro Foundations Michael Bar September 13, 2016 Contents 1 Consumer s Choice 2 1.1 Preferences.................................... 2 1.2 Budget Constraint................................ 3

More information

Chapter 21: Option Valuation

Chapter 21: Option Valuation Chapter 21: Option Valuation-1 Chapter 21: Option Valuation I. The Binomial Option Pricing Moel Intro: 1. Goal: to be able to value options 2. Basic approach: 3. Law of One Price: 4. How it will help:

More information

P. Manju Priya 1, M.Phil Scholar. G. Michael Rosario 2, Associate Professor , Tamil Nadu, INDIA)

P. Manju Priya 1, M.Phil Scholar. G. Michael Rosario 2, Associate Professor , Tamil Nadu, INDIA) International Journal of Computational an Applie Mathematics. ISSN 89-4966 Volume, Number (07 Research Inia Publications http://www.ripublication.com AN ORDERING POLICY UNDER WO-LEVEL RADE CREDI POLICY

More information

Unintended Consequences of Price Controls: An Application to Allowance Markets

Unintended Consequences of Price Controls: An Application to Allowance Markets MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Unintene Consequences of Price Controls: An Application to Allowance Markets Anrew Stocking Congressional Buget Office September 2010 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.e/25559/

More information

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected Utility and Risk Aversion Expected utility and risk aversion 1/ 58 Introduction Expected utility is the standard framework for modeling investor choices. The following topics will be covered:

More information

Laboratoire d Economie de Dauphine. Document de travail. Contracting for information: On the effects of the principal's outiside option

Laboratoire d Economie de Dauphine. Document de travail. Contracting for information: On the effects of the principal's outiside option Laboratoire Economie e Dauphine WP n /015 Document e travail Contracting for information: On the effects of the principal's outisie option Franck Bien Thomas Lanzi Pôle Laboratoire Economie et e Gestion

More information

Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part 1

Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part 1 Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part Sotiris Georganas Royal Holloway University of London January 00 Problem Consider Hotelling s linear city with endogenous prices and exogenous and locations. Suppose,

More information

Mean-Variance Analysis

Mean-Variance Analysis Mean-Variance Analysis Mean-variance analysis 1/ 51 Introduction How does one optimally choose among multiple risky assets? Due to diversi cation, which depends on assets return covariances, the attractiveness

More information

Dynamic Demand for New and Used Durable Goods without Physical Depreciation: The Case of Japanese Video Games

Dynamic Demand for New and Used Durable Goods without Physical Depreciation: The Case of Japanese Video Games Dynamic Deman for New an Use Durable Goos without Physical Depreciation: The Case of Japanese Vieo Games Masakazu Ishihara Stern School of Business New York University Anrew Ching Rotman School of Management

More information

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models IEOR E4707: Foundations of Financial Engineering c 206 by Martin Haugh Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models These notes develop the theory of martingale pricing in a discrete-time,

More information

Pricing Multi-Dimensional Options by Grid Stretching and High Order Finite Differences

Pricing Multi-Dimensional Options by Grid Stretching and High Order Finite Differences Pricing Multi-Dimensional Options by Gri Stretching an High Orer Finite Differences Kees Oosterlee Numerical Analysis Group, Delft University of Technology Joint work with Coen Leentvaar Southern Ontario

More information

Engineering Decisions

Engineering Decisions GSOE9210 vicj@cse.uns.eu.au.cse.uns.eu.au/~gs9210 Decisions uner certainty an ignorance 1 Decision problem classes 2 Decisions uner certainty 3 Outline Decision problem classes 1 Decision problem classes

More information

Behavioral Finance and Asset Pricing

Behavioral Finance and Asset Pricing Behavioral Finance and Asset Pricing Behavioral Finance and Asset Pricing /49 Introduction We present models of asset pricing where investors preferences are subject to psychological biases or where investors

More information

TOBB-ETU, Economics Department Macroeconomics II (ECON 532) Practice Problems III

TOBB-ETU, Economics Department Macroeconomics II (ECON 532) Practice Problems III TOBB-ETU, Economics Department Macroeconomics II ECON 532) Practice Problems III Q: Consumption Theory CARA utility) Consider an individual living for two periods, with preferences Uc 1 ; c 2 ) = uc 1

More information

CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #18: Multi-Parameter Revenue-Maximization

CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #18: Multi-Parameter Revenue-Maximization CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #18: Multi-Parameter Revenue-Maximization Tim Roughgarden March 5, 2014 1 Review of Single-Parameter Revenue Maximization With this lecture we commence the

More information

Liquidity Hoarding 1

Liquidity Hoarding 1 Liquiity Hoaring Douglas Gale New York University Tanju Yorulmazer 3 Feeral Reserve Bank of New York 7 March, The views expresse here are those of the authors an o not necessarily represent the views of

More information

Introduction to Options Pricing Theory

Introduction to Options Pricing Theory Introuction to Options Pricing Theory Simone Calogero Chalmers University of Technology Preface This text presents a self-containe introuction to the binomial moel an the Black-Scholes moel in options

More information

2. Lattice Methods. Outline. A Simple Binomial Model. 1. No-Arbitrage Evaluation 2. Its relationship to risk-neutral valuation.

2. Lattice Methods. Outline. A Simple Binomial Model. 1. No-Arbitrage Evaluation 2. Its relationship to risk-neutral valuation. . Lattice Methos. One-step binomial tree moel (Hull, Chap., page 4) Math69 S8, HM Zhu Outline. No-Arbitrage Evaluation. Its relationship to risk-neutral valuation. A Simple Binomial Moel A stock price

More information

If you have ever spoken with your grandparents about what their lives were like

If you have ever spoken with your grandparents about what their lives were like CHAPTER 7 Economic Growth I: Capital Accumulation an Population Growth The question of growth is nothing new but a new isguise for an age-ol issue, one which has always intrigue an preoccupie economics:

More information

PERFORMANCE OF THE CROATIAN INSURANCE COMPANIES - MULTICRITERIAL APPROACH

PERFORMANCE OF THE CROATIAN INSURANCE COMPANIES - MULTICRITERIAL APPROACH PERFORMANCE OF THE CROATIAN INSURANCE COMPANIES - MULTICRITERIAL APPROACH Davorka Davosir Pongrac Zagreb school of economics an management Joranovac 110, 10000 Zagreb E-mail: avorka.avosir@zsem.hr Višna

More information

Full file at

Full file at Chapter 2 Supply an eman Analysis Solutions to Review uestions 1. Excess eman occurs when price falls below the equilibrium price. In this situation, consumers are emaning a higher quantity than is being

More information

Optimal Long-Term Supply Contracts with Asymmetric Demand Information. Appendix

Optimal Long-Term Supply Contracts with Asymmetric Demand Information. Appendix Optimal Long-Term Supply Contracts with Asymmetric Demand Information Ilan Lobel Appendix Wenqiang iao {ilobel, wxiao}@stern.nyu.edu Stern School of Business, New York University Appendix A: Proofs Proof

More information

GAINS FROM TRADE UNDER MONOPOLISTIC COMPETITION

GAINS FROM TRADE UNDER MONOPOLISTIC COMPETITION bs_bs_banner Pacific Economic Review, 2: (206) pp. 35 44 oi: 0./468-006.250 GAINS FROM TRADE UNDER MONOPOLISTIC COMPETITION ROBERT C. FEENSTRA* University of California, Davis an National Bureau of Economic

More information

Ch 10. Arithmetic Average Options and Asian Opitons

Ch 10. Arithmetic Average Options and Asian Opitons Ch 10. Arithmetic Average Options an Asian Opitons I. Asian Options an Their Analytic Pricing Formulas II. Binomial Tree Moel to Price Average Options III. Combination of Arithmetic Average an Reset Options

More information

International Trade

International Trade 4.58 International Trade Class notes on 5/6/03 Trade Policy Literature Key questions:. Why are countries protectionist? Can protectionism ever be optimal? Can e explain ho trade policies vary across countries,

More information

Troubled Asset Relief Program, Bank Interest Margin and. Default Risk in Equity Return: An Option-Pricing Model

Troubled Asset Relief Program, Bank Interest Margin and. Default Risk in Equity Return: An Option-Pricing Model Trouble Asset elief Program Bank Interest argin an Default isk in Equity eturn: An Option-Pricing oel JYH-JIUA I * CHIG-HUI CHAG 3 AD JYH-HOG I Department of tatistics Tamkang University 5 Ying-Chuan oa

More information

Forthcoming in The Journal of Banking and Finance

Forthcoming in The Journal of Banking and Finance Forthcoming in The Journal of Banking an Finance June, 000 Strategic Choices of Quality, Differentiation an Pricing in Financial Services *, ** Saneep Mahajan The Worl Bank (O) 0-458-087 Fax 0-5-530 email:

More information

Simple Robust Hedging with Nearby Contracts

Simple Robust Hedging with Nearby Contracts Simple Robust Heging with Nearby Contracts Liuren Wu Zicklin School of Business, Baruch College Jingyi Zhu University of Utah Abstract Most existing heging approaches are base on neutralizing risk exposures

More information

Assessment of Acceptance Sampling Plans Using Posterior Distribution for a Dependent Process

Assessment of Acceptance Sampling Plans Using Posterior Distribution for a Dependent Process Rochester Institute of Technology RIT Scholar Works Articles 1-21-2010 Assessment of Acceptance Sampling Plans Using Posterior Distribution for a Depenent Process A. Erhan Mergen Rochester Institute of

More information

Some Alternative Actuarial Pricing Methods: Application to Reinsurance and Experience Rating

Some Alternative Actuarial Pricing Methods: Application to Reinsurance and Experience Rating Reports on Economics an Finance, Vol., 06, no., - 35 HIKARI Lt, www.m-hikari.com http://x.oi.org/0.988/ref.06.54 Some Alternative Actuarial Pricing Methos: Application to Reinsurance an Experience Rating

More information

SPLITTING FIELDS KEITH CONRAD

SPLITTING FIELDS KEITH CONRAD SPLITTING FIELDS EITH CONRAD 1. Introuction When is a fiel an f(t ) [T ] is nonconstant, there is a fiel extension / in which f(t ) picks up a root, say α. Then f(t ) = (T α)g(t ) where g(t ) [T ] an eg

More information

Information Acquisition in Financial Markets: a Correction

Information Acquisition in Financial Markets: a Correction Information Acquisition in Financial Markets: a Correction Gadi Barlevy Federal Reserve Bank of Chicago 30 South LaSalle Chicago, IL 60604 Pietro Veronesi Graduate School of Business University of Chicago

More information

Technical Appendix to Long-Term Contracts under the Threat of Supplier Default

Technical Appendix to Long-Term Contracts under the Threat of Supplier Default 0.287/MSOM.070.099ec Technical Appendix to Long-Term Contracts under the Threat of Supplier Default Robert Swinney Serguei Netessine The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA, 904

More information

Organizational Form, the Business Environment, and Competitive. Strategy

Organizational Form, the Business Environment, and Competitive. Strategy Organizational Form, the Business Environment, an Competitive Strategy Davi Gais Ross Columbia Business School y September 2007 Abstract This paper uses a principal-agent moel to investigate how the business

More information

The Joint Dynamics of Electricity Spot and Forward Markets: Implications on Formulating Dynamic Hedging Strategies

The Joint Dynamics of Electricity Spot and Forward Markets: Implications on Formulating Dynamic Hedging Strategies Energy Laboratory MI EL 00-005 Massachusetts Institute of echnology he Joint Dynamics of Electricity Spot an Forwar Markets: Implications on Formulating Dynamic Heging Strategies ovember 2000 he Joint

More information

Notes on Intertemporal Optimization

Notes on Intertemporal Optimization Notes on Intertemporal Optimization Econ 204A - Henning Bohn * Most of modern macroeconomics involves models of agents that optimize over time. he basic ideas and tools are the same as in microeconomics,

More information

V. Reznik and U. Spreitzer Dr. Dr. Heissmann GmbH, Abraham-Lincoln-Str. 22, Wiesbaden.

V. Reznik and U. Spreitzer Dr. Dr. Heissmann GmbH, Abraham-Lincoln-Str. 22, Wiesbaden. n investigation of a portfolio-loss uner the CPM V. eznik an U. Spreitzer Dr. Dr. Heissmann GmbH, braham-incoln-str., 6589 Wiesbaen. bstract: We consier a portfolio built accoring to the Capital Market

More information

6th International Conference on Electronics, Mechanics, Culture and Medicine (EMCM 2015)

6th International Conference on Electronics, Mechanics, Culture and Medicine (EMCM 2015) 6th International Conference on Electronics Mechanics Culture an Meicine (EMCM 2015) esearch on the Evolution Mechanism an Countermeasures of Green Builing Market Base on Evolutionary Game Theory Zhongfu

More information

5. COMPETITIVE MARKETS

5. COMPETITIVE MARKETS 5. COMPETITIVE MARKETS We studied how individual consumers and rms behave in Part I of the book. In Part II of the book, we studied how individual economic agents make decisions when there are strategic

More information

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS 247 16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS Let us associate each state S with a numeric utility U(S), which expresses the desirability of the state A nondeterministic action A will have possible outcome states Result

More information

The use of Expected Utility Theory (EUT) in Taxpayers Behaviour Modelling

The use of Expected Utility Theory (EUT) in Taxpayers Behaviour Modelling American Journal of Applie Sciences Original Research Paper The use of Expecte Utility Theory (EUT) in Taxpayers Behaviour Moelling Fari Ameur an Mohame Tkiouat Stuies an Research Laboratory in Applie

More information

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Spring, 2013

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Spring, 2013 STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Spring, 2013 Section 1. (Suggested Time: 45 Minutes) For 3 of the following 6 statements,

More information

1 Answers to the Sept 08 macro prelim - Long Questions

1 Answers to the Sept 08 macro prelim - Long Questions Answers to the Sept 08 macro prelim - Long Questions. Suppose that a representative consumer receives an endowment of a non-storable consumption good. The endowment evolves exogenously according to ln

More information

An efficient method for computing the Expected Value of Sample Information. A non-parametric regression approach

An efficient method for computing the Expected Value of Sample Information. A non-parametric regression approach ScHARR Working Paper An efficient metho for computing the Expecte Value of Sample Information. A non-parametric regression approach Mark Strong,, eremy E. Oakley 2, Alan Brennan. School of Health an Relate

More information

Partial State-Owned Bank Interest Margin, Default Risk, and Structural Breaks: A Model of Financial Engineering

Partial State-Owned Bank Interest Margin, Default Risk, and Structural Breaks: A Model of Financial Engineering Partial State-Owne Bank Interest Margin, Default Risk, an Structural Breaks: A Moel of Financial Engineering JYH-HORNG IN,CHING-HUI CHANG * AND ROSEMARY JOU Grauate Institute of International Business

More information

Revenue Management Under the Markov Chain Choice Model

Revenue Management Under the Markov Chain Choice Model Revenue Management Under the Markov Chain Choice Model Jacob B. Feldman School of Operations Research and Information Engineering, Cornell University, Ithaca, New York 14853, USA jbf232@cornell.edu Huseyin

More information

Dynamic games with incomplete information

Dynamic games with incomplete information Dynamic games with incomplete information Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE) We have now covered static and dynamic games of complete information and static games of incomplete information. The next step

More information

Robust portfolio optimization using second-order cone programming

Robust portfolio optimization using second-order cone programming 1 Robust portfolio optimization using second-order cone programming Fiona Kolbert and Laurence Wormald Executive Summary Optimization maintains its importance ithin portfolio management, despite many criticisms

More information

Search, Welfare and the Hot Potato E ect of In ation

Search, Welfare and the Hot Potato E ect of In ation Search, Welfare and the Hot Potato E ect of In ation Ed Nosal December 2008 Abstract An increase in in ation will cause people to hold less real balances and may cause them to speed up their spending.

More information

Liability Insurance: Equilibrium Contracts under Monopoly and Competition.

Liability Insurance: Equilibrium Contracts under Monopoly and Competition. Liability Insurance: Equilibrium Contracts uner Monopoly an Competition. Jorge Lemus, Emil Temnyalov, an John L. Turner April 24, 2017 Abstract In thir-party liability lawsuits (e.g., patent infringement

More information

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints 1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints In this section we study conditions under which savings react to changes in income uncertainty. Recall that in the PIH, when you abstract from

More information

Continuous-Time Consumption and Portfolio Choice

Continuous-Time Consumption and Portfolio Choice Continuous-Time Consumption and Portfolio Choice Continuous-Time Consumption and Portfolio Choice 1/ 57 Introduction Assuming that asset prices follow di usion processes, we derive an individual s continuous

More information

Fiscal policy and minimum wage for redistribution: an equivalence result. Abstract

Fiscal policy and minimum wage for redistribution: an equivalence result. Abstract Fiscal policy and minimum wage for redistribution: an equivalence result Arantza Gorostiaga Rubio-Ramírez Juan F. Universidad del País Vasco Duke University and Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta Abstract

More information

Data Center Demand Response in Deregulated Electricity Markets

Data Center Demand Response in Deregulated Electricity Markets Data Center Deman Response in Deregulate Electricity Markets Shahab Bahrami, Stuent Member, IEEE, Vincent W.S. Wong, Fellow, IEEE, an Jianwei Huang, Fellow, IEEE Abstract With the evelopment of eregulate

More information

Host Country Financial Development and MNC Activity

Host Country Financial Development and MNC Activity Host Country Financial Development an MNC Activity Davin Chor Fritz Foley Kalina Manova Singapore Management Harvar Business School Stanfor University University an NBER an NBER October 2008 Abstract We

More information

LGD Risk Resolved. Abstract

LGD Risk Resolved. Abstract LGD Risk Resolve Jon Frye (corresponing author) Senior Economist Feeral Reserve Bank of Chicago 230 South LaSalle Street Chicago, IL 60604 Jon.Frye@chi.frb.org 32-322-5035 Michael Jacobs Jr. Senior Financial

More information

Chapter 17: Vertical and Conglomerate Mergers

Chapter 17: Vertical and Conglomerate Mergers Chapter 17: Vertical and Conglomerate Mergers Learning Objectives: Students should learn to: 1. Apply the complementary goods model to the analysis of vertical mergers.. Demonstrate the idea of double

More information