If Dividends Are Tips (Are Shareholders Entitled to the Residual?) Daniel Greenwood - 1 Mar 06 - Brooklyn Law School

Similar documents
Daniel JH Greenwood - Are Shareholders Entitled to the Residual? Hofstra University College of Law 2/8/06

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance

Explaining risk, return and volatility. An Octopus guide

Allstate Agency Value Index 2011 Year Review

ABOUT FREEDOM CLUB ABOUT DR. TONY

Fiduciary Duty: An Explosive Liability for Design Professionals

4 BIG REASONS YOU CAN T AFFORD TO IGNORE BUSINESS CREDIT!

5 Biggest Mistakes Most Home Buyers Make

GETTING RID OF DEBT: WHAT IS THE BEST OPTION FOR YOU?

LIABILITY AND RISK MANAGEMENT FOR BOARDS

MOCK NEGOTIATIONS: LIMITATION OF LIABILITY

Your Stock Market Survival Guide

Merk Insights September 8, 2016

Principal-Agent Issues and Managerial Compensation

You have many choices when it comes to money and investing. Only one was created with you in mind. A Structured Settlement can provide hope and a

What is the Lasting Powers of Attorney service?

Life and protection insurance explained

Board Leadership Southeast Alberta LIABILITY AND RISK MANAGEMENT FOR BOARDS. Alberta Chamber of Commerce Provincial Conference

Copyright 2015 Wilma G. Anderson, RFC. Retirement Freedom

DEBTS AND DISPUTES. Understanding Debt. What to do?

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW-PART 2. Contracts. I.1 Investment in Performance

Protecting Families. Getting the conversation started. For financial adviser use only. Not approved for use with customers.

10 Ways to Maximize Your Social Security

Chapter 3.3. Trading Psychology

c» BALANCE C:» Financially Empowering You Financial First Aid Podcast [Music plays] Nikki:

ABSOLUTE RETURN FUNDS FUND GUIDE

c» BALANCE c» Financially Empowering You Credit Matters Podcast

Life and protection insurance explained

Reading Five: A Right Jab & A Left Hook

GETTING READY TO INVEST

Trefzger, FIL 240 & FIL 404 Assignment: Debt and Equity Financing and Form of Business Organization

How to Stop and Avoid Foreclosure in Today's Market

Retirement Investments Insurance. Pensions. made simple TAKE CONTROL OF YOUR FUTURE

Acquirers Anonymous: Seven Steps back to Sobriety

Trade Deficit Hits New High, Trump Tariffs Are Bad

Conversations: Jeffrey Owens and Rick McDonell

Credit Management vs. Collections EXECUTIVE SUMMARY. Tom Gannon, CCE Director of Research & Education Federation of Credit and Financial Professionals

Collect the Biggest Dividends In Stock Market History

Protecting Families. Getting the conversation started. Retirement Investments Insurance Health

March Annuities and the Investor Perspective

Dear Cavan, Asset class treatment of residential property investment loans

Guide to buying an annuity

Pension Lifetime Allowance Guide

The Enforceability of Interest Under a Title-Transfer Theory of Contract. Roderick T. Long

Are You Receiving 8-10% Interest on your Investments?

Delegated Monitoring, Legal Protection, Runs and Commitment

What You Can Do to Improve Your Credit, Now

Activity: After the Bell Before the Curtain

Club Accounts - David Wilson Question 6.

Life insurance. Serious and critical illness insurance

spin-free guide to bonds Investing Risk Equities Bonds Property Income

The Truth About How To Create A Secure Retirement Income For Life

MGMT 165: Corporate Finance

THE BEST RETIREMENT INVESTMENT OPTIONS

NAVIGATING. a BriEF guide to the DErivativEs MarkEtPLaCE and its role in EnaBLing ECOnOMiC growth

Keeping Hometown Businesses At Home By John H. Brown and Corey Rosen

The Evolution of Fraud on the Market Suits and Halliburton II

Being a Guarantor. This booklet will help you understand all that is involved in being a Guarantor.

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

Note that there is an overlap between the T/F and multiple-choice questions, as some of the T/F statements are used in multiple-choice questions.

Preparing to buy your first home?

Copyright by Profits Run, Inc. Published by: Profits Run, Inc Beck Rd Unit F1. Wixom, MI

Financial Factoid By: Financial Scenarios, LLC

Recommendations for the Special Joint Committee on Deficit Reduction

Chapter 7 Review questions

GETTING READY TO INVEST

INVESTMENTS. The M&G guide to. bonds. Investing Bonds Property Equities Risk Multi-asset investing Income

A History of Shaping Financial Success THE QUICK GUIDE TO FINANCIAL SUCCESS

The 10 Golden Rules of Trading. A mini ebook in the SmartTrader Series. Paul M King

CHAPTER 29. Corporate Governance. Chapter Synopsis

corporate advisor Hale and Dorr LLP Directors of Financially Troubled Companies Face Special Duties and Risks

Nine Secrets To Stock Market Success! Valuable Tips From Market Pros

Maximizing Purchasing Power: Make the Most of Your Credit Score

MY TIPS FOR MAKING A LIVING FROM TRADING

Complaint about your pension? Here s how we can help

A Trader s Opportunity of a Generation

Steps to Financial Freedom Achieving lifelong financial

From The Desk Of: Matthew Whiz Buckley, Options Expert & Instructor 02/03/14

The Ideal Collection Alternative

TAX EFFECTIVE GEARED INVESTING

How to Strategically Manage Your Debt

Going-Private Regulation in an Era of Round Trip Transactions: A Commentary

Don t get Caught with Your Marketing and Crop Insurance on the Wrong Side of the Basis When it Narrows 1

Congratulations! You ve decided to get to grips with your. Exploring the Basics COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Chapter 1

aid Terry College of Business J.M. Tull School of Accounting File Reference No. 194-B

Profit Growth Strategies By Brian Tracy

ULTIMUS INSIGHTS. The Trust Tale of the Tape. Comparing Series Trusts to Standalone Trusts and Making the Right Decision for Your Business

Chapter 9 Topics in the Economics of Contract Law

Seven Trading Mistakes to Say Goodbye To. By Mark Kelly KNISPO Solutions Inc.

Credit Cards Are Not For Credit!

Debt Collection & the Fair Debt Collection Practice Act (FDCPA)

Improving Your Credit Score

What is Buying on Credit? What Kinds of Things Are Usually Bought on Credit? What is the Difference Between Open-End Credit and Closed-End Credit?

If you are over age 50, you get another $5,500 in catch-up contributions. Are you taking advantage of that additional amount?

NONPROFIT AGENDAS: STRATEGIES AND SOLUTIONS FOR CONTINUING TO GROW YOUR NONPROFIT ORGANIZATION

Understanding Investment Leverage

Christiano 362, Winter 2006 Lecture #3: More on Exchange Rates More on the idea that exchange rates move around a lot.

OPEB, LX Edition. What s under the hood of a benefits valuation

2. How easily do you adapt when things go wrong financially? Nervous, I lose sleep Uneasy Somewhat easily With Confidence

ECON 4245 ECONOMICS OF THE FIRM

Transcription:

(Are Shareholders Entitled to the Residual?) Daniel Greenwood - 1 Mar 06 - Brooklyn Law School A fuller version of this talk will be published as The Dividend Problem, 32:1 J. CORP. L. (forthcoming 2006); http://ssrn.com/abstract=799144 Dividends are tips. A waiter serves you, without a prior enforceable agreement as to what he ll be paid for doing so. Afterwards, the customer decides how much to pay, and the waiter has no legal recourse if unsatisfied. To be sure, there are clear social norms enforced by peer pressure among customers (and their dates). But an economist using a rational maximizer model would expect to find serious free rider issues and an omnipresent specter of a market for lemons. Why would a rational, amoral, profit-maximizer ever pay for a service already rendered? Why would a rational service provider be willing to take the risk of being stiffed? If the system works at all, wouldn t payments reflect the hold-up value of the waiter s implicit threat to refuse future service, rather than the marginal cost or benefit of past services rendered? If so, is there any reason to think that price will reflect cost or supply balance demand? If waiters are the enforcers, why would they make the individual sacrifice to punish, at the cost of another tip, rather than hoping like Charlie Brown, that this time Lucy won t misbehave? Rational maximization models may illuminate some of these issues at the margin. The central story, however, revolves around internalized social norms and their creation. Not maximizing but Trust, duty, character and loose social sanctions. Most customers tip where rational maximizers clearly would free ride, and waiters routinely trust where anyone using an rational maximizer model of customers would not. Dividends present each of these problems, but more so. Like waiters, shareholders apparently expect to be paid after the fact, based on some estimate of the value of the services they ve provided. Like waiters, they have no legally enforceable right to any payment at all. Unlike waiters, they don t even have a clear social norm specifying the amount they ought to receive.

Maximizing explanations of tips and dividends alike require some explanation of why payors don t free ride. Reputation is the most obvious one. But Enforcement by reputation is likely to be difficult, if only because * shareholders are an anonymous and rapidly changing mass less likely to be able to take its revenge than an angry maitre d at a oversubscribed hotspot, and * many dividend payors, especially the solid, established companies that most commonly pay them, are unlikely to need to sell new issues of stock on a regular basis, and * the actual human decision-makers who decide whether to pay dividends are top managers who will nearly always be in or near an end-game in which they will be tempted to exploit a prior reputation, and * the actual human decision-makers operating institutional shareholders are always tightly constrained to short-term time frames that will make it difficult for them to consider long-term investing in punishment when they could simply freeride. To be sure, the stock market, unlike waiters, has an additional enforcement mechanism: Hostile takeover. If the market concludes that the company is withholding dividends, stock prices may drop, making it a target for someone that plans to give a larger slice of the corporate pie to equity investors. But the stock market is not as allergic to low dividend stocks as it once was, under the influence of Miller & Modigliani. And the hostile takeover market is not what it was in the period after the invention of junk bonds and before the judicial acceptance of poison pills and the just-say-no defense. In short, free riding in a rationally maximizing stock market would quickly lead to market for lemons, with even those companies willing to commit to dividends unable to find shareholders willing to believe them. But that isn t the worst of the dividend puzzle. In a competitive market, producers should not be able to sell their product or services for more than marginal cost. Since dividends are not legally required, the marginal cost of equity capital is zero. Any company that pays dividends should find itself underpriced by a company that decides to renege on its implicit promises to equity investors. 2

In short, given the structure of the actual rights (none of them contractual) that shareholders have, in a world of rational maximizers, shareholders would rarely receive dividends. Anticipating this, they would even more rarely be willing to purchase shares. If the world worked like this, we would see a market for lemons, not 10% average returns. The economic rational maximizer theories must be missing something fundamental. *** So let s try some other perspectives. More lawyerly ones based on normative notions of what is right, rather than how maximizers would behave. Corporate law ideology often claims that shareholders are entitled to the residual because they are the residual risk bearers. This, of course, is nonsense in fact. When Asbestos companies failed, their tort victims were the biggest losers. If Indian Point were to go nuclear, the shareholders would lose no more than their investment in most cases pretty little. The real risk bearers are the downwinders. When Enron failed, diversified portfolio shareholders suffered far less than employees who lost the value of Enron s long term commitments to them. When American steel manufacturers invested in the wrong technology in the 1980s, or American car manufacturers committed to SUVs in this decade, the downside risk of their decision was largely borne by the unionized employees. The nexus of contracts understanding of the firm makes quite clear that the very notion of residual is wrong. All firm participants engage in more or less continuous renegotiation of the terms of their participation in the firm (that is why Alchian and Demsetz, in the seminal article setting out the nexus theory could claim that the firm could be understood in market terms). This is true, as pension holders repeatedly discover, even when the contracts purport to be long term. But if terms are always subject to renegotiation, then allocation of risk is always subject to renegotiation as well. Who bears the residual risk will simply be a function of relative market power at 3

any given time. Shareholder activists, in contrast, often prefer a metaphor of ownership. Shareholders own the firm, they assert, even though they have few or none of the attributes of ownership, and so they are entitled to the residual as a matter of moral right and perhaps agency or trust law as well. But this metaphor is as difficult as the nexus of contracts one. Shareholders are not owners in any normal sense of the word. The most important aspect of ownership in a free society is the sphere of privacy property creates, in which an owner is entitled to act without regard for the opinions of mankind, to do what she thinks is right or amusing even if no one else agrees. If I own this pencil, that means I can use it or abuse it with minimal regard for your views. But individually and collectively, the stockholders of a publicly traded Delaware corporation have no legal right to control the firm, no right to use or appropriate its assets, no right to destroy it, no right to make unconventional decisions. And, as we have seen, no right to the residual. The only significant legal rights they have are the right to vote for the board of directors on the basis of one-share, one-vote, the right to a pro-rata share of any distribution the board chooses to declare, and the right to ratify certain limited board decisions. These are political rights, not ownership rights. Nor are shareholders principals in a principal/agent relationship. Principals have the right to control their agents; but directors are legally required to exercise independent judgment and risk personal liability if they defer to shareholder wishes. And principals have the inalienable right to terminate the relationship at any time for any reason. Shareholders have only the political right to vote at appropriate times and places. If they are not principals, perhaps they are the opposite: trust beneficiaries. I m not a trust expert, and perhaps those who understand trust better than I do will 4

correct me. To my naive eyes, the difference between corporations and trusts are significant. Trusts normally end at some time and normally the beneficiary must have some entitlement to receive the corpus or its income at some point. Shareholders have no such rights. They do not even have an enforceable equitable interest in having the corporation managed in their interests except in limited circumstances (Revlon) ordinarily, Delaware repeats its statutory language, which directs that the directors act in the interest of the corporation, and then uses the business judgment rule to express what is, in effect, administrative deference for the autonomy of the corporation as an independent agency governed almost exclusively by its internal political processes. *** The answer to the question of my title is No. Shareholders are not entitled to the residual. Residuals are, by definition, rents: the surplus to cooperation that is the reason the firm is able to out-compete a market. In capitalist systems, no one has an ex ante right to rents. Rents are what we negotiate over. More than that. Shareholders are not evene in a particularly good position to bargain over these rents: they are purely fungible providers of a purely fungible commodity in our most competitive market, and so one would expect that the price they can command would be marginal cost, nothing more. And since equity is a sunk cost, marginal cost approaches zero. *** But shareholders do receive dividends, so something is wrong in the picture I ve painted. We need an alternative explanation outside the economic framework. Shareholders receive dividends, even if not the residual, for reasons of political power and, especially, ideology, not market. Shareholders receive dividends, NOT because of the nature of the market, and NOT because they are legally or morally entitled to them. Instead, first and foremost, because managers and directors think they should get them. That is, corporate law, the legal field most successfully colonized by economists, centrally 5

revolves around constructed normativity, not efficiency. As I hope I ve shown, the leading normative explanations for why shareholders SHOULD receive dividends are no stronger than the maximizer explanations for why they DO. This raises an interesting question Why have directors and managers found these unpersuasive stories so persuasive. And here the answer is, paradoxically, because the shareholder centered account of the firm is the best available defense of managerial self-interest. Publicly traded corporations have no clear owners. But one thing is quite clear. Managers are not the owners. Managers clearly are agents, not principals; employees not owners. So, while CEOs apparently have the market power to take the bulk of the proceeds under their control, they don t have a good explanation of why they are entitled to use their power in this way. Simply taking 8 or 9 figure pay because you can looks too much like corruption. Shareholder value maximization, and the related lionizing of the CEO who creates shareholder value serves as the smokescreen. We ve created a powerful normative structure based on praising the stockmarket for its efficiency that ends by vindicating the efficiency of paying CEOs for giving the shareholders what they cannot take for themselves. Shareholders, that is, receive dividends as a sideeffect of huge managerial pay-offs. So, to point to some consequences: A little one: Reformers who seek to restrain the rise in CEO salaries before it absorbs all our economic growth are looking in the wrong place if they delegate that task to shareholders. The stock market will not reduce CEO salaries at least so long as CEOs remain faithful to the task of extracting the maximum value from employees and continue to share at least some of it with investors. And a bigger one: If dividends reflect not marginal productivity but claims of duty based on particular, and somewhat peculiar, cultural understandings of how 6

firms should work, then they are as contingent on the continued persuasiveness of particular cultural political views as on profit. This means, first, that if you are, as I am, counting on the stock market to provide for your retirement, you had better hope that investors as a group find my analysis unpersuasive. If I am right, the only reason that shareholders receive dividends is because managers find it convenient to think that they should. That is a powerful reason but it is far less powerful if, as I ve claimed in other papers, the ideology supporting it is both inconsistent and destructive of its own underpinnings. CEOs already have most of the attributes of ownership. If they succeed in convincing the rest of us that they are entitled to use the power they have, they will have no reason to share with the public shareholders at all. After all, in a capitalist society, those who create value are entitled to keep it. This is not an attractive possibility. We should worry about the corrosive impact of an ideology that invites managers to think of themselves not as fiduciaries for the public good but as rational maximizers entitled to ever larger payments to do their jobs. This way leads, I fear, to looting, not building. Finally, and more hopefully. On this analysis, the current distribution of the corporate pie, with the bulk of the surplus to cooperative production going to a coalition of investors and managers, is not the result of efficient markets but ideological conviction and political struggle. Progressives need not worry that productivity or economic growth is tied to the status quo distribution of corporate surplus. Instead, we have a degree of political freedom to determine how to use the proceeds of capitalism that has seemed unthinkable in the last generation. All we need is a better story. 7