Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros

Similar documents
MAT 4250: Lecture 1 Eric Chung

Using the Maximin Principle

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

Yao s Minimax Principle

Thursday, March 3

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

MATH 121 GAME THEORY REVIEW

Outline for today. Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 13: General-Sum Games. General-sum games. General-sum games. Dominated pure strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

COS 511: Theoretical Machine Learning. Lecturer: Rob Schapire Lecture #24 Scribe: Jordan Ash May 1, 2014

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

ECO 5341 (Section 2) Spring 2016 Midterm March 24th 2016 Total Points: 100

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

Their opponent will play intelligently and wishes to maximize their own payoff.

Best counterstrategy for C

Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy!

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

MATH 210, PROBLEM SET 1 DUE IN LECTURE ON WEDNESDAY, JAN. 28

Solution to Tutorial 1

Solution to Tutorial /2013 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory

Strategy Lines and Optimal Mixed Strategy for R

Comparative Study between Linear and Graphical Methods in Solving Optimization Problems

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

IEOR E4004: Introduction to OR: Deterministic Models

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Assignment 1: Preference Relations. Decision Theory. Pareto Optimality. Game Types.

Math 152: Applicable Mathematics and Computing

Game theory for. Leonardo Badia.

6.896 Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory February 10, Lecture 3

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2008 David Wagner Final Exam

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

Homework #4. CMSC351 - Spring 2013 PRINT Name : Due: Thu Apr 16 th at the start of class

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

CS711 Game Theory and Mechanism Design

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

Notes on the symmetric group

ORF 307: Lecture 12. Linear Programming: Chapter 11: Game Theory

CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory)

Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy!

CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Zhen Sun, Milind Dawande, Ganesh Janakiraman, and Vijay Mookerjee

Name Date Student id #:

15.053/8 February 28, person 0-sum (or constant sum) game theory

COS 445 Final. Due online Monday, May 21st at 11:59 pm. Please upload each problem as a separate file via MTA.

Chapter 2 Strategic Dominance

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications. Lecture 11: Games of Perfect Information

Tug of War Game. William Gasarch and Nick Sovich and Paul Zimand. October 6, Abstract

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Games of Incomplete Information ( 資訊不全賽局 ) Games of Incomplete Information

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002

7. Infinite Games. II 1

Expectations & Randomization Normal Form Games Dominance Iterated Dominance. Normal Form Games & Dominance

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #3: Myerson s Lemma

Game Theory: Normal Form Games

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1

Maximum Contiguous Subsequences

(a) Describe the game in plain english and find its equivalent strategic form.

Section Strictly Determined Games, Dominated Rows, Saddle Points

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Game Theory Lecture #16

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Definition 4.1. In a stochastic process T is called a stopping time if you can tell when it happens.

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

Strategy -1- Strategy

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

Problem Set #4. Econ 103. (b) Let A be the event that you get at least one head. List all the basic outcomes in A.

TWIST UNTANGLE AND RELATED KNOT GAMES

MATH20180: Foundations of Financial Mathematics

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we

Econ 172A, W2002: Final Examination, Solutions

Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

GAME THEORY. Game theory. The odds and evens game. Two person, zero sum game. Prototype example

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming

ECON 214 Elements of Statistics for Economists 2016/2017

SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games

Page Points Score Total: 100

(a) (5 points) Suppose p = 1. Calculate all the Nash Equilibria of the game. Do/es the equilibrium/a that you have found maximize social utility?

Can we have no Nash Equilibria? Can you have more than one Nash Equilibrium? CS 430: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory II (Nash Equilibria)

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

CSE 316A: Homework 5

ECON 214 Elements of Statistics for Economists

Game Theory. Important Instructions

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012

Transcription:

Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros Midterm #1, February 3, 2017 Name (use a pen): Student ID (use a pen): Signature (use a pen): Rules: Duration of the exam: 50 minutes. By writing your name and signature on this exam paper, you attest that you are the person indicated and will adhere to the UCLA Student Conduct Code. You may use either a pen or a pencil to write your solutions. However, if you use a pencil I will withheld your paper for two weeks after grading it. No calculators, computers, cell phones (all the cell phones should be turned off during the exam), notes, books or other outside material are permitted on this exam. If you want to use scratch paper, you should ask for it from one of the proctors. Do not use your own scratch paper! Please justify all your answers with mathematical precision and write rigorous and clear proofs and arguments. You may lose points in the lack of justification of your answers. Theorems from the lectures and homework assignments may be used in order to justify your solution. In this case state the theorem you are using. This exam has 4 problems and is worth 20 points. Adding up the indicated points you can observe that there are 27 points, which means that there are 7 bonus points. This permits to obtain the highest score 20, even if you do not answer some of the questions. On the other hand nobody can be bored during the exam. All scores higher than 20 will be considered as 20 in the gradebook. The problems are not necessarily ordered with respect to difficulty. I wish you success! Problem Exercise 1 Exercise 2 Exercise 3 Exercise 4 Total Score

Exercise 1 (Jane and John playing a game 8 points). Jane and John are playing the following game: both of them write down an integer on a piece of paper, independently from the other, Jane is allowed to choose from the set {1,..., 5} and John from the larger set {1,..., 7}. Then they show their pieces of paper to each other and if the sum of the integers is odd Jane pays John $1, if the sum is even, then John pays Jane $2. They repeat this again and again. (1) To which category does this game belong to? Why? (2) Write down the payoff matrix associated to this game. (3) If it is possible, reduce the payoff matrix. Justify the procedure! Show that there are no pure optimal strategies for neither of the players. (4) Why does at least one optimal strategy exist for both players? Compute the optimal mixed strategies. Compute the optimal expected payoff, i.e. the value of the game! Interpret the optimal strategies and the value of the game. Hint: you may refer to theorems from the lectures, if you want to justify your answers. (5) What would happen if instead of choosing the integers from the finite sets, as described, they would be allowed to choose any natural number (the other rules of the game are the same)? What are the optimal mixed strategies in this case and the value of the game? (1) This game is a 2-person 0-sum game, because the loss of one of the players in the gain of the other. (2) From the point of view of Jane, the payoff matrix has the form A = 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 (3) Clearly, from the rules of the game one observes that it only matters the parity of the written number, and their values are not important. From the payoff matrix one can see that many rows and columns contain the exact same values. So, to solve the game, one can remove for instance the rows 3, 4, 5 and the columns 3, 4, 5, 6, 7. Thus, the reduced matrix has the form à = ( 2 1 1 2 Since this is a 2 2 matrix, it is clear that if there would be a pure optimal strategy for one of the players, the other player should have also a pure optimal strategy, so these can happen only at the same time. On the other hand all this kind of strategies have to come from saddle points of Ã, and this matrix clearly does not have any of these. In the next point we compute all the optimal strategies, from where one will see that there are no pure ones. That can be considered also an answer to this questions. (4) It is a consequence of von Neumann s theorem. To compute the optimal strategies, either we can rely on the fact that there are no pure optimal strategies and use the equalizing payoff technique, or one can compute them by hand. We denote the strategies of Jane by (x, 1 x) and the ones of John by (y, 1 y), where x, y [0, 1]. One has that 2y (1 y) = y + 2(1 y) from where y = 1/2 and in a very same way x = 1/2. Otherwise, if one wants to compute directly, one can write the global expected payoff function as G : [0, 1] [0, 1] R G(x, y) = 2xy x(1 y) (1 x)y + 2(1 x)(1 y) = 6xy 3x 3y + 2 ). 2

and use the same techniques that we developed during the lectures to compute the min max of it, that leads also to x = y = 1/2. The value of the game is G(1/2, 1/2) = (1/2 1/2)Ã(1/2 1/2) = 1/2. To interpret the optimal strategies, both players have to choose an odd number with probability 1/2 and an even number with probability 1/2, and the expected payoff of Jane (expected loss of John) will be $1/2. (5) Since the game is depending on the parity of the chosen numbers, everything would be the same if the players would be allowed to choose any natural number. The optimal strategies would be the same as well as the value of the game. 3

Exercise 2 (Jane and John playing another game 9 points). Jane and John are playing the following game: there is a table with the integers {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6} on it. The players take turns and at each turn they remove one of the numbers from the table. Whoever does a move that leads to a set of numbers which have an odd product wins and the game terminates. Also, if there exists only one remaining odd number (and some even ones) on the table, nobody is allowed to remove that single odd number (to avoid a tie). To illustrate a winning move, imagine for instance that someone is left with {3, 4, 5} at her/his turn, removing the number 4, this player wins since 3 5 = 15 is an odd number. (1) To which category does this game belong to? (combinatorial? if yes, impartial or partisan? progressively bounded or not?) Justify your answers. (2) Determine all the terminal positions of the game! (3) For each game position (derived from the given initial configuration) determine whether it is in the set N or P. Who has a winning strategy if Jane starts? I expect full justification for each of the positions and when describing the winning strategy as well! (4) Study the very same game in the general framework: there are the numbers {1, 2,..., n} on the table where n N is given, but arbitrary. Determine whether this configuration is N or P, in function of n. Remark: this last question can be more challenging, maybe it is better to consider working on it after you have spent some time on the other problems as well. (1) Since all the game positions (including the terminal ones) are available for both players, this is an impartial combinatorial game. There is a finite set of numbers and each turn the players remove one, so it is progressively bounded. (2) Since the game terminates when the product of the numbers is odd (and if there remains only one odd number, it cannot be removed), the terminal positions of the game are the ones when there are only odd numbers on the table, there are 7 of such positions. Since in this game only the parity of the number matters, we do not make distinctions between them. So, we denote the initial position by {3e, 3d} (where e stands for even and d for odd). The terminal positions can be written as {0e, 1d}, {0e, 2d}, {0e, 3d}. (3) With a straight forward reasoning we can describe {0e, 1d}, {0e, 2d}, {0e, 3d} P, as terminal positions. Since 1 odd number always has to remains we have also clearly that Furthermore {1e, 1d} N, {2e, 1d} P and {3e, 1d} N. {1e, 2d}, {1e, 3d} N, since the next player can remove the only even number and win/terminate the game. Next, {2e, 2d} N, since there is a legal move that leads to {2e, 1d} P. {2e, 3d} P since both legal moves lead to {2e, 2d}, {1e, 3d} N. Similarly, {3e, 2d} P and {3e, 3d} N. To summarize {0e, 1d}, {0e, 2d}, {0e, 3d}, {2e, 1d}, {2e, 3d}, {3e, 2d} P, 4

and {1e, 1d}, {1e, 2d}, {1e, 3d}, {2e, 2d}, {3e, 1d}, {3e, 3d} N. This last clearly implies that the player who starts, i.e. Jane has a winning strategy. This strategy can be read backwards in the previous lines. (4) For the general case, one might have to study some more positions to observe a pattern. But we claim the following: Claim: let us suppose that one is given a N {0} and b N. Then, if a = 0 then {ae, bd} P, if a = 1 then {ae, bd} N for arbitrary b N. If a 2, then we have to cases: Case 1. If a and b have the same parities, then {ae, bd} N. Otherwise, Case 2. {ae, bd} P. We prove this claim by induction. Actually the first two cases, when a = 0 or a = 1 are straight forward, so we work with the cases when a 2. The initial step of the induction was checked in (3). Now let us suppose that for a given n 3 the claim is true whenever a + b = n. We need to show the claim for a + b = n + 1. Case 1. Suppose that a and b have the same parity. If b = 1, then clearly {ae, 1d} N, since a is also odd. Otherwise, if b 2 and a = 2, then performing the legal move that leads to {ae, (b 1)d}, this position clearly has a + (b 1) = n and a and b 1 have opposite parity, so by the inductive step {ae, (b 1)d} P, implying that {ae, bd} N by definition of P. If a > 2 and b 2 both legal moves lead to either {ae, (b 1)d} or to {(a 1)e, bd}, which by the inductive step are in P so {ae, bd} N. Case 2. Suppose now that a and b have different parities. If b = 1, when since a is even, {ae, bd} P. If b 2 we need to study cases when a 3. So any legal move will lead to either {ae, (b 1)d} or to {(a 1)e, bd} which by the inductive step (since a + (b 1) = (a 1) + b = n and (a 1), b and a, (b 1) have the same parities) are in N. So by definition of P, {ae, bd} P. This concludes the proof. This means that for a general n N given in the exercise (which is greater than 6, since up to 6 we studied everything in (3)), if n is even, then we have the same number of even and odd numbers on the table, so the first player, i.e. Jane has winning strategy, while if n is odd, then the second player, i.e. John has a winning strategy. 5

Exercise 3 (8 points). (1) Let us consider below the payoff matrix of a 0-sum 2-person game, where the first player (having 3 possible actions) is aiming to maximize the expected global payoff, while the second player (having 5 possible actions) is aiming to minimize the expected global payoff. A = 2 5 3 0 1 5 2 8 7 5 3 3 2 8 4 (a) Does the above matrix have any saddle points? Which type of optimal strategies are more likely to occur in the above game? Justify your answers! (b) Determine an optimal strategy for each of the players and the value of the game. Hint: reduce first the payoff matrix. (2) Let us consider below the payoff matrix of a 0-sum 2-person game, where the first player (having 3 possible actions) is aiming to maximize the expected global payoff, while the second player (having 4 possible actions) is aiming to minimize the expected global payoff. B = 3 1 0 0 5 1 1 7 4 2 1 8 (a) Show that the above game have some pure optimal strategies for both players. Determine all these pure optimal strategies together with the value of the game. (b) Show that at least for one of the players there is an infinite number of mixed strategies and determine these. (1)(a) No, it does not have. So we are expecting mixed optimal strategies here. (1)(b) We observe that by domination, one can remove the last two columns. Then in the remaining matrix the second row dominates the third one, so we can remove the third one. Then the third column dominates the first one, so one can remove this third one as well. Hence we get the 2 2 payoff matrix ( ) 2 5 Ã = 5 2 This matrix is symmetric and on the main diagonal one has the same numbers. A similar argument and computation as in the case of Exercise 1, leads to the optimal strategies (1/2, 1/2) and (1/2, 1/2), which has to be written in the original game framework as (1/2, 1/2, 0) the optimal strategy of PI and (1/2, 1/2, 0, 0, 0) the optimal strategy of PII. The value of the game is 3/2. (2)(a) Saddle points of B will determine pure optimal strategies of the players. These are the index pairs (2, 2) and (2, 3). These correspond to the pure optimal strategies (0, 1, 0) (PI) and (0, 1, 0, 0) (PII) from the one hand and (0, 1, 0) (PI) and (0, 0, 1, 0) (PII) on the other hand. The value of the game is 1. (b) From the previous point one can see that while PI is playing the optimal strategy (0, 1, 0), PII can play either (0, 1, 0, 0) or (0, 0, 1, 0). In is easy to see that PII can actually play any convex combination of these two strategies, and that will be optimal, i.e. the optimal strategies of PII are (0, p, 1 p, 0) where p [0, 1] is arbitrary. This shows that this player has an infinite number of optimal strategies. 6

Exercise 4 (The last game of Jane and John 2 points). Jane and John are playing the following game: both of them have a sufficient amount of building blocks and for a given n N number, they have to build a tower that has a height of n blocks by placing always 1, 2 or 3 blocks on the top previous ones (they have to advance always vertically). They take turns and at each turn they need to place at least one block. The winner will be who will finish the tower by placing the n th block (one may assume that the blocks have the same special physical properties, allowing that any number of them can be placed one on the others without collapsing). If Jane is starting the construction, determine whether either of them has a winning strategy and if so, find this strategy in terms of n. Hint: you may relate this game to some that we studied already during the lectures. Observe that this is exactly the subtraction game, that we considered during the lectures. If you imagine that there is already an imaginary tower built with n blocks, at each turn the corresponding player removes 1, 2 or 3 blocks from this tower to build the new one. The game actually ends, when there are no blocks in the imaginary tower. So clearly, for any n one of the players has a winning strategy: if 4 n, then John has this strategy, otherwise Jane does. 7