DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES"

Transcription

1 ANALELE ŞTIINŢIFICE ALE UNIVERSITĂŢII AL.I. CUZA DIN IAŞI (S.N.) MATEMATICĂ, Tomul LXI, 2015, f.2 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES BY D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU Abstract. The main purpose of this paper is to present new results in divisible and semi-divisible residuated lattices. It also presents a new characterization for boolean elements of a residuated lattice (Theorem 9). Mathematics Subject Classification 2010: 03G10, 06D35, 06D72, 03G05, 06B20. Key words: divisible and semi-divisible residuated lattices, Boolean algebra, semi- G-algebra, MT L-algebra, BL-algebra, MV -algebra, regular element, dense element, reflective subcategory, deductive system, maximal deductive system, radical. 1. Introduction The origin of residuated lattices is in Mathematical Logic without contraction. They have been investigated by Krull [18], Dilworth [9], Ward and Dilworth [26], Ward [25], Balbes and Dwinger [1] and Pavelka [20]. In [16], Idziak prove that the class of residuated lattices is equational. These lattices have been known under many names: BCK- latices in [15], full BCK- algebras in [18], FL ew - algebras in [19], and integral, residuated, commutative l-monoids in [3]. Apart from their logical interest, residuated lattices have interesting algebraic properties (see [2], [5], [9], [12], [25], [26]). MV-algebras are known to be special residuated lattices with a proper additive operation. MV-algebras fulfill a double negation law x = x, too. For a residuated lattice L we denote by MV (L) the set of all elements

2 288 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 2 x = x 0 with x L. (MV (L),,, 0) is an MV algebra iff for all x, y L, (x y ) y = (y x ) x (see [22]), where for x, y MV (L), x y = x y. In particular, for any semi-divisible residuated lattice L, the subset (MV (L),,, 0) is an MV -algebra (see [22]). The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we recall the basic definitions of residuated lattices. Also we present M V -center of a semi-divisible residuated lattice, defined by Turunen and Mertanen in [22]. This is a very important construction, which associates an M V -algebra to every semi-divisible residuated lattice. In this way, many properties can be transferred from M V -algebras to residuated lattices and backwards. In Section 3 we prove that the category MV of MV -algebras is a reflective subcategory of the category RL d of divisible residuated lattices and as consequence we obtain some informations relative to injective divisible residuated lattices (Corollary 3). In Section 4, for a residuated lattice L we denote by R(L) the set of regular elements of L, by D(L) the set of dense elements of L and by B(L) the set of boolean elements of L. We present new characterizations for these elements. We prove that in general, B(L) R(L) MV (L). If L is a semidivisible MT L-algebra, then B(L) = B(MV (L)). Theorem 10 characterize the residuated lattices which are Boolean algebras. In Section 5, we present new results relative to lattice of maximal deductive systems of a residuated lattice. We introduce the notion of semi-galgebra and we obtain that if L is a semi-g-algebra, then there is a bijection between Max(L) and RL(L, {0, 1}) = { f : L {0, 1} f is a morphism of residuated lattices} (Theorem 14). We prove that if L is semi-divisible, then there is a bijective correspondence between maximal deductive systems of L and maximal deductive systems of MV (L). In Section 6, we characterize Rad(M V (L)), for a semi-divisible residuated lattice L. 2. Definitions and preliminaries We review the basic definitions of residuated lattices. Also we present M V -center of a semi-divisible residuated lattice, defined by Turunen and Mertanen in [22].

3 3 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 289 Definition 1. A residuated lattice ([2], [23]) is an algebra (L,,,,, 0, 1) of type (2, 2, 2, 2, 0, 0) equipped with an order satisfying the following: (LR 1 ) (L,,, 0, 1) is a bounded lattice; (LR 2 ) (L,, 1) is a commutative ordered monoid; (LR 3 ) and form an adjoint pair, i.e. a x y iff a x y for all a, x, y L. The relations between the pair of operations and expressed by (LR 3 ), is a particular case of the law of residuation ([2]). The class RL of residuated lattices is equational (see [16]). Example 1 ([23]). Let p be a fixed natural number and I = [0, 1] the real unit interval. We define for x, y I, x y = (max{0, x p + y p 1}) 1/p and x y = min{1, (1 x p +y p ) 1/p }, then (I, max, min,,, 0, 1) become a residuated lattice called generalized Lukasiewicz structure. For p = 1 we obtain the notion of Lukasiewicz structure ( x y = max{0, x + y 1}, x y = min{1, 1 x + y}). Example 2 ([23]). If consider on I = [0, 1], to be the usual multiplication of real numbers and for x, y I, x y = 1 if x y and y/x otherwise, then (I, max, min,,, 0, 1) is a residuated lattice (called Products structure or Gaines structure). Example 3 ([23]). If (B,,,, 0, 1) is a Boolean algebra, then if we define for every x, y B, x y = x y and x y = x y, then (B,,,,, 0, 1) becomes a residuated lattice. In L we consider the following identities: (BL 1 ) x (x y) = x y (divisibility); (BL 2 ) (x y) (y x) = 1 (preliniarity); (BL 1 ) [x (x y )] = (x y ) (semi-divisibility). Definition 2. The residuated lattice L is called: (i) divisible if L verify (BL 1 );

4 290 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 4 (ii) MT L-algebra if L verify (BL 2 ); (iii) BL-algebra if L verify (BL 1 ) and (BL 2 ) (that is, L is a divisible MT L algebra); (iv) semi-divisible if L verify (BL 1 ). We denote by RL ( RL d, MT L, BL, RL sd ) the class of residuated lattices (divisible residuated lattices, M T L-algebras, BL-algebras, semidivisible residuated lattices). Proposition 1 ([22]). For a residuated lattice L, the following conditions are equivalent: (i) L RL d ; (ii) For every x, y L with x y there exists z L such that x = y z; (iii) For every x, y, z L, x (y z) = (x y) [(x y) z]. We recall ([7], [23]) that type (2, 1, 0) such that: an MV -algebra is an algebra (M,,, 0) of (MV 1 ) (M,, 0) is a commutative monoid; (MV 2 ) x = x, for every x M; (MV 3 ) (x y) y = (y x) x, for every x, y M (where x y = x y). We denote by MV the class of MV -algebras. Remark 1 ([14], [23]). 1. It is not hard to see that an equivalent presentation of MV -algebras can be given as BL-algebras plus condition (MV 2 ). 2. Let (L,,,,, 0, 1) be a residuated lattice. If for x, y L we denote x y = x y, then (L,,, 0) is an MV -algebra iff (x y) y = (y x) x, for every x, y L. Remark 2. Lukasiewicz structures and Boolean algebras are BL algebras; not every residuated lattice is a BL-algebra (see [23], p.16).

5 5 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 291 Example 4 ([17]). We give an another example of a finite residuated lattice, which is not a BL-algebra. Let L = {0, a, b, c, 1} with 0 < a, b < c < 1, but a, b are incomparable. L become a residuated lattice relative to the following operations: 0 a b c a b 1 b 1 1 b a a c 0 a b a b c 1, 0 a b c a 0 a 0 a a b 0 0 b b b c 0 a b c c 1 0 a b c 1. In what follows by L we denote the universe of a residuated lattice; for x L and a natural number n, we define x = x 0, x = (x ), x 0 = 1 and x n = x n 1 x for n 1. In residuated lattices we have the following rules of calculus: Theorem 1 ([5], [6], [8], [12], [23]). Let x, x 1, x 2, y, y 1, y 2, z L. Then we have: (c 1 ) 1 x = x, x 1 = 1, 0 x = 1, x 0 = 0; (c 2 ) x y iff x y = 1; (c 3 ) x y x, x (x y) y, ((x y) y) y = x y; (c 4 ) x y (z x) (z y); (c 5 ) x y (y z) (x z); (c 6 ) (x y) (x z) x (y z); (c 7 ) x (y z) = (x y) (x z), (y z) x (y x) (z x); (c 8 ) (x y) z = (x z) (y z); (c 9 ) x y implies z x z y and y z x z; (c 10 ) x 1 y 1 (y 2 x 2 ) [(y 1 y 2 ) (x 1 x 2 )]; (c 11 ) x y implies z x z y; (c 12 ) x (x y) x y, x y (x y);

6 292 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 6 (c 13 ) x (x (x y)) = x y; (c 14 ) x (y z) = (x y) z = y (x z); (c 15 ) x y (x z) (y z) and (x 1 y 1 ) (x 2 y 2 ) (x 1 x 2 ) (y 1 y 2 ); (c 16 ) (x 1 y 1 ) (x 2 y 2 ) (x 1 x 2 ) (y 1 y 2 ); (c 17 ) (x 1 y 1 ) (x 2 y 2 ) (x 1 x 2 ) (y 1 y 2 ); (c 18 ) x y = 1 x y = x y; (c 19 ) x (y z) (x y) (x z), so, x m y n (x y) mn for any natural numbers m, n; (c 20 ) x (y z) y (x z) (x y) (x z); (c 21 ) x (y z) = (x y) (x z); (c 22 ) (x y) n x n y n for every n 1; (c 23 ) (x y) n x n y n, for every n 1; (c 24 ) (x y) n x n y n, for every n 1. Theorem 2 ([5], [6], [8], [12], [23]). If x, y L, then: (c 25 ) 1 = 0, 0 = 1; (c 26 ) x y y x ; (c 27 ) x y y x ; (c 28 ) x x = 0 and x y = 0 iff x y ; (c 29 ) x x, x x x, x = x ; (c 30 ) (x y) = x y = y x ; (c 31 ) (x y) = x y ; (c 32 ) x y = y x = x y ; (c 33 ) (x y ) = x y ;

7 7 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 293 (c 34 ) (x y) x y ; (c 35 ) x y (x y), so (x ) n (x n ) for every natural number n; (c 36 ) x y (x y). Corollary 1. If L is a divisible residuated lattice, then for every x, y L we have: (c 37 ) (x x) = 0; (c 38 ) (x y) = x y ; (c 39 ) (x y) = x (x y ), (x y) = x y ; (c 40 ) y x x (x y) = y ; (c 41 ) x (y z) = (x y) (x z), x (y z) = (x y) (x z). Proof. (c 37 ). From x x x (x x) x (x x) = x (x x) (BL 1) = x [x (x x) ] (c 30) = x [(x x) (x ) ] (c 30) = x [(x x) x ] (BL 1) = x (x x) = x x = 0. (c 38 ). From (c 34 ) we have (x y) x y = x y. On the another hand we have (x y ) (x y) = (x y ) (x y) (c 34) [(x y ) (x y)] = [(x (x y )) y] (BL 1) = [(x y ) y] [(x y) (y y)] (y y) (c 37) = 0 = 1 (x y ) (x y) = 1 x y (x y) (x y) = x y = x y. (c 39 ). From x y x (x y) x (x y) = (x y) x = [(x y) ] x = (y x ) x = x [x (y x ) ] = x [x (x y ) ] = x [x (y x ) ] = x [(y x ) x ] = x [(x y ) x ] = x [(x y ) x ] = x [(x y ) x ] = x (x y ). Clearly, (x y) x, y. Consider t L such that t x, y. Then x, y t x y t t (x y ). But t t and (x y ) = x y t x y (x y) = x y. (c 40 ). From y x x (x y) = (x y) x = (x y ) x = [x (x y )] = (x y ) = y. (c 41 ). Clearly x (y z) (x y) (x z).

8 294 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 8 On the other hand, (x y) (x z) = (x y) [(x y) (x z)] = (x y) [x (y (x z))] = (x y) [y (x (x z))] = x [y (y (x (x z)))] = x [y (x (x z))] = x [(x (x z)) ((x (x z)) y)]. But z x (x z) (x (x z)) y z y, so (x y) (x z) x [x (x z)] (z y) = x z (z y) = x (y z) (x y) (x z) = x (y z). Clearly, x (y z) (x y) (x z). On the another hand we have x (y z) = (y z) [(y z) x] (c 21) = [y ((y z) x)] [z ((y z) x)] [y (y x)] [z (z x)] = (y x) (z x) = (x y) (x z). 3. MV-center of a divisible residuated lattice For a residuated lattice L we consider the subset MV (L) = {x : x L} = {x L : x = x} of L. MV (L) is non-void, since 1 = 0 MV (L). Moreover, MV (L) is closed with respect to the operations (because by (c 30 ), x y = (x y) MV (L)), (by c 31 ) and in particular, with respect to the operation. For x, y L we define x y = x y. Theorem 3 ([22]). (MV (L),,, 0) is an MV -algebra iff for all x, y L, (x y ) y = (y x ) x. Theorem 4 ([22]). If (x y ) y = (y x ) x holds in a residuated lattice L, then L is semi-divisible. Corollary 2 ([22]). In any semi-divisible residuated lattice L, (M V (L),,, 0) is an MV algebra (called MV center of L). Recall that an algebra (W,,, 1) of type (2, 1, 0) is a Wajsberg algebra if it satisfies the following conditions: (W 1 ) 1 x = x; (W 2 ) (x y) ((y z) (x z)) = 1; (W 3 ) (x y) y = (y x) x; (W 4 ) (x y ) (y x) = 1. Following [23], if (W,,, 1) is a Wajsberg algebra, then (W,,, 0) is an MV algebra, where for x, y W, x y = x y. Conversely, if

9 9 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 295 (W,,, 0) is an MV algebra, then (W,,, 1) is a Wajsberg algebra, where for x, y W, x y = x y. The order relation on a Wajsberg algebra W is given by: x y iff x y = 1. Following Theorems 3, 4 and Corollary 2, if L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice and for x, y L we define x y = (x ) y = x y = y x = y x = x y, then MV (L) has a structure of MV algebra (hence, Wajsberg algebra) and the order relation W on the Wajsberg algebra MV (L) is defined by x W y iff x y = 1 x y (in L). Hence the order relation on MV (L) coincides with the order relation on L. According to [22], the lattice operations least upper bound {x, y }, denoted by x W y, and greatest lower bound {x, y }, denoted by x W y, on the Wajsberg algebra MV (L) are defined via x W y = (x y ) y and x W y = (x W y ). In general, the meet operation W on MV (L) may not be the restriction of the meet operation on L and, similarly, for join operation. Proposition 2 ([22]). If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice, then W and coincide on MV (L). Lemma 1. If x, y L, then: (c 42 ) [x (x y )] = (y x ) x ; (c 43 ) x W y = (x y ) (c 31) = (x y). Proof. (c 42 ). We have [x (x y )] = [x (y x )] = [(y x ) x ] = (y x ) (x 0) = (y x ) x. (c 43 ). From x y x x (x y ) and analogously y (x y ). To prove x W y = (x y ) consider t MV (L) such that x, y t. Then t x, y t x y (x y ) t = t. We present a new characterization for semi-divisible residuated lattices: Proposition 3. For a residuated lattice L, the following conditions are equivalent: (i) L RL sd ; (ii) (x y ) y = (y x ) x for every x, y L.

10 296 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 10 Proof. (i) (ii). If L RL sd, then for x, y L, [x (x y )] = [y (y x )] (= (x y ) ) and by (c 42 ) we deduce that (x y ) y = (y x ) x. (ii) (i). If x, y L and (x y ) y = (y x ) x, since (x y ) = x W y = (x y ) y and [x (x y )] = (y x ) x, then we obtain that [x (x y )] = (x y ), that is, L RL sd. Remark Every divisible residuated lattice is semi-divisible, so, every BL-algebra is semi-divisible. 2. Not every residuated lattice is semi-divisible. Consider, for example (see [22]) a fixed real number c, 0 < c < 1, and define the residuated lattice L c = ([0, 1],,,,, 0, 1) such that for all x, y [0, 1], such that x y = 0 if x+y c and min{x, y} elsewhere, x y = 1 if x y and max{c x, y} elsewhere. We have MV (L c ) = [0, c) {1}. Let x = 3 5 c, y = 4 5c. Then x, y MV (L c ), (y x) x = 1, but (x y) y = y. Thus, the condition from Theorem 3 does not hold. So L c is not semi-divisible. Evidently, each residuated lattice L c is linear, therefore is a MT L-algebra. We deduce that M T L-algebras are not, in general semi-divisible. 3. There are residuated lattices that are semi-divisible but not divisible. Consider, for example (see [22]) the residuated lattice L sd = ([0, 1],,,,, 0, 1) such that for all x, y [0, 1], x y = 0 if x, y [0, 1 2 ] and min{x, y} elsewhere x y = 1 if x y; 1 2 if y < x 1 2 and y if (y < x, 1 2 < x). We have MV (L sd ) = {0, 1 2, 1} and the condition from Theorem 3 holds, whence, L sd is a semi-divisible residuated lattice. L sd is not divisible. Indeed, let x = 1 3, y = 1 2. Then 1 2 ( ) = = = min{ 1 3, 1 2 }. We recall that if (L i,,,,, 0, 1), i = 1, 2 are two residuated lattices then, a map f : L 1 L 2 is called morphism of residuated lattices if f satisfies the following conditions, for every x, y L 1 : (m 1 ) f(0) = 0; (m 2 ) f(1) = 1; (m 3 ) f(x y) = f(x) f(y); (m 4 ) f(x y) = f(x) f(y); (m 5 ) f(x y) = f(x) f(y);

11 11 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 297 (m 6 ) f(x y) = f(x) f(y). We define Ker(f) = {x L 1 : f(x) = 1}. Remark If L 1, L 2 are BL-algebras, then f : L 1 L 2 is morfism of residuated lattices iff f verifies (m 1 ), (m 5 ) and (m 6 ). 2. If L 1, L 2 are divisible, then f : L 1 L 2 is morfism of residuated lattices iff f verifies the conditions (m 1 ), (m 4 ), (m 5 ) and (m 6 ). 3. If L 1, L 2 are MT L-algebras, then f : L 1 L 2 is morfism of residuated lattices iff f verifies (m 1 ) (m 3 ) and (m 5 ) (m 6 ). So, RL becomes in canonical way a category such that RL d, MT L, RL sd and BL are subcategories of RL. Remark 5 ([1, p.31]). Since the categories MV and RL are equational, then in these categories the monomorphisms are exactly the one-one morphisms. In what follows, by L we denote the universe of a divisible residuated lattice. Since L is semi-divisible, by Corollary 2, (MV (L),,, 0) is a MV - algebra (hence BL algebra), where for x, y MV (L), x = x 0 MV (L) and x y = x y = x y = (x y ) MV (L). The order on MV (L) is defined for x, y MV (L) by x W y iff x y = 1 x y = 1 x y = 1, so the order on MV (L) is the restriction of the order on L to MV (L). Also, if for x, y L we define x W y = [(x ) (y ) ] = (x y ), then (MV (L), W, W =,, W, 0, 1) is a BL-algebra (hence a residuated lattice). Proposition 4. If x, y L, then (x y) = x W y. Proof. We have x W y (c 44) = (x y ) = (x y ) = (x y ) = (y x ) = (y (x 0)) = [(x y) ] = (x y). We denote R(L) = MV (L) and we define Φ R (L) : L MV (L) by Φ R (L)(x) = x, for all x L. Proposition 5. If L is a divisible residuated lattice, then Φ R (L) is a morphism of residuated lattices (between the lattices (L,,,,, 0, 1) and (MV (L), W, W =,, W, 0, 1)). Proof. Clearly, Φ R (L)(0) = 0, Φ R (L)(1) = 1, Φ R (L)(x y) = (x y) (c 43) = x W y = Φ R (L)(x) W Φ R (L)(y), Φ R (L)(x y) = (x

12 298 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 12 y) (c 38) = x y = Φ R (L)(x) Φ R (L)(y) and by Proposition 4, Φ R (L)(x y) = (x y) = x W y = Φ R (L)(x) W Φ R (L)(y) for all x, y L. Since L is divisible, we have x y = x (x y), hence, Φ R (L)(x y) = Φ R (L)(x) W Φ R (L)(y), so, Φ R (L) is a morphism of residuated lattices. If L, L are divisible residuated lattices and f : L L is a morphism of residuated lattices, then R(f) : MV (L) MV (L ) defined by R(f)(x ) = f(x ) = (f(x)) for every x L is a morphism in MV. Indeed, if x, y L, then R(f)(x y ) = R(f)((x y) ) = (f(x y)) = (f(x) f(y)) = f(x) f(y) = (R(f)(x )) (R(f)(y )) and R(f)((x ) ) = (f(x )) = (f(x) ) = (R(f)(x )). So, the assignments L MV (L) = R(L) and f R(f) define a functor (covariant) R : RL d MV from the category of divisible residuated lattices to the category of MV -algebras. Theorem 5. The category MV of MV -algebras is a reflective subcategory of the category RL d of divisible residuated lattices and the reflector R preserves monomorphisms. Proof. To prove R is a reflector ([1]), we consider the diagram L f L R(L) Φ R(L) R(f) R(L ) Φ R(L ) with L, L RL d. If x L, then (Φ R (L ) f)(x) = Φ R (L )(f(x)) = (f(x)) and (R(f) Φ R (L))(x) = R(f)(Φ R (L)(x)) = R(f)(x ) = (f(x )) = (f(x) ) = (f(x)), hence Φ R (L ) f = R(f) Φ R (L), that is, the above diagram is commutative. Let now L RL d, M MV and f : L M a morphism of residuated lattices R(L) L R(L) Φ f M f For x L, we define f : R(L) M by f (x ) = f(x ) = f(x) (that is, f = f MV(L) ). For x, y L, we have f (x y ) = f ((x y) ) = (f(x

13 13 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 299 y)) = (f(x) f(y)) = f(x) f(y), f((x ) ) = f(x) = f(x) = (f(x )) and f (0) = f (1 ) = f(1) = 1 = 0, hence f is a morphism in MV. Since for x L, (f Φ R (L))(x) = f (Φ R (L)(x)) = f (x ) = f(x) = f(x), we deduce that f Φ R (L) = f. If we have again f : R(L) M a morphism in MV such that f Φ R (L) = f, then for any x L, (f Φ R (L))(x ) = f(x ), hence f (x ) = f(x ) = f (x ), so f = f, so R is a reflector. To prove that R preserves monomorphisms, let f : L L a monomorphism in RL d and x, y L such that R(f)(x ) = R(f)(y ). Then f(x ) = f(y ), hence x = y, that is, R(f) is a monomorphism in MV. We recall that an MV -algebra is called complete if it contains the greatest lower bound and the lowest upper bound of any subset. Also, an MV - algebra L is called divisible if for any a L and for any natural number n 1 there is x L such that nx = a and a [(n 1)x] = x. In [23], p.66, it is proved: Theorem 6. For any MV -algebra L the following assertions are equivalent: (i) L is injective object in the category MV, (ii) L is complete and divisible MV -algebra. So, we obtain the following: Corollary 3. If L is a complete and divisible MV -algebra, then L is an injective object in the category RL d. Proof. By Theorem 6, L is an injective object in the category MV. Since MV is reflective subcategory of RL d and the reflector R : RL d MV preserves monomorphisms (by Theorem 5), then by Theorem 6 from [1] we deduce that L is injective object in the category RL d. Remark 6. Following Corollary 4.4 from [11] we deduce that if L is an injective object in the category RL d, then L is a complete lattice. Open problem. If L is an injective object in the category RL d, then L is divisible?

14 300 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU Boolean center, regular and dense elements Let (L,,, 0, 1) be a bounded lattice. Recall (see [1], [13]) that an element a L is called complemented if there is an element b L such that a b = 1 and a b = 0; if such element b exists it is called a complement of a. We will denote b = a and the set of all complemented elements in L by B(L). Complements are generally not unique, unless the lattice is distributive. In residuated lattices however, although the underlying lattices need not be distributive, the complements are unique. Lemma 2 ([12]). Let L be a residuated lattice and suppose that a L have a complement b L. Then, the following hold: (i) If c is another complement of a in L, then c = b; (ii) a = b and b = a; (iii) a 2 = a. Let L be a residuated lattice and B(L) the set of all complemented elements of the lattice (L,,, 0, 1). So, if e B(L), then e = e and e = e. Also, e x = e x, for every x L, see ([12]). The set B(L) is the universe of a Boolean subalgebra of L (called the Boolean center of L - see [12]). Proposition 6 ([5]). If L is a residuated lattice, then for e L the following are equivalent: (i) e B(L); (ii) e e = 1. Theorem 7 ([7]). For every element e in an MV -algebra A, the following conditions are equivalent: (i) e B(A); (ii) e e = 1; (iii) e e = 0; (iv) e e = e;

15 15 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 301 (v) e e = e. Proposition 7 ([5]). Let L be a residuated lattice. For e L we consider the following assertions: (i) e B(L); (ii) e 2 = e and e = e ; (iii) e 2 = e and e e = e; (iv) (e x) e = e, for every x L; (v) e e = 0. Then (i) (ii), (iii), (iv) and (v) but (ii) (i), (iii) (i), (iv) (i), (v) (i). Remark 7 ([4]). If L is a BL-algebra, then all assertions from above proposition are equivalent. Remark 8. If L is a residuated lattice, then B(L) MV (L). We put in evidence new rule of calculus with boolean elements: Lemma 3. Let x, y L and e, f B(L). Then: (c 42 ) x (x e) = x e, e (e x) = e x; (c 43 ) e (x y) = (e x) (e y); (c 44 ) e (x y) = (e x) (e y); (c 45 ) e (x y) = e [(e x) (e y)]; (c 46 ) x (e f) = x [(x e) (x f)]; (c 47 ) e (x y) = (e x) (e y); (c 48 ) e (e x) = e x; (c 49 ) (e x) e = e; (c 50 ) (e x) x (x e) e; (c 51 ) e x = (e x) x = e x;

16 302 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 16 (c 52 ) e (x y) = (e x) (e y); (c 53 ) (e x) (f x) = (e f) x; (c 54 ) x (e f) = (x e) (x f); (c 55 ) e (x y) = (e x) (e y); (c 56 ) x (e f) = (x e) (x f); (c 57 ) If e, f x, then e (x f) = f (x e); (c 58 ) (e x) (x e) = 1; (c 59 ) e x = [(e x) x] [(x e) e]. Proof. For (c 42 ) (c 47 ) see [5]. (c 48 ). We have e (e x) = e 2 x = e x. (c 49 ). See [5]. (c 50 ). We have (e x) x (c 5) (x e) [(e x) e] = (x e) e. (c 51 ). From e e x and x e x e x e x. Also from e (e x) x (e x) (e x) and e (e x) e (e x) (e x), since e e = 1 (e x) (e x) = 1 e x e x e x = e x e x = e x. Since e, x (e x) x e x (e x) x. Since e e x (e x) x e x = e x (e x) x=e x. (c 52 ). By (c 51 ) we have e (x y) = e (x y) (c 47) = (e x) (e y) = (e x) (e y). (c 53 ). We have (e x) (f x) (c 51) = (e x) (f x) = f [(e x) x] (c 51) = f (e x) = f (e x) = (f e) x = (f e) x and (e f) x = (e f) x = (e f) x = (e f) x = (e f ) x = (e f ) x, so (e x) (f x) = (e f) x. (c 54 ). (x e) (x f) (c 14) = [x (x e)] f (c 42) = (x e) f = (x e) f (c 14) = x (e f). (c 55 ). We have e (x y) = e (x y) (c 21) = (e x) (e y) = (e x) (e y). (c 56 ). We have x (e f) = x (e f) (c 21) = (x e) (x f) = (x e) (x f). (c 57 ). We have e (x f) = (e x) (x f) = [x (x e)] (x f) = (x e) [x (x f)] = (x e) (x f) = f (x e);

17 17 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 303 (c 58 ). If e B(A) then e e = 1. Since e e x and e x e we deduce that 1 = e e (e x) (x e), so (e x) (x e) = 1. (c 59 ). Denote t = [(e x) x] [(x e) e]. We have e (e x) x and x (e x) x; it follows that e x (e x) x. Analogous, e x (x e) e. Hence e x [(e x) x] [(x e) e], so e x t. We have t = t 1 (c 58) = t [(e x) (x e)] (c 21) = [t (e x)] [t (x e)]; but t (e x) = [((e x) x) ((x e) e)] (e x) [(e x) x] (e x) (e x) x x; similarly, t (x e) e. Hence, t = [t (e x)] [t (x e)] x e. It follows that e x = t. Proposition 8. If L is a divisible residuated lattice, then the assertions (i), (ii), (iii) and (iv) from Proposition 7 are equivalent. Proof. (i) (ii). See Proposition 7. (ii) (iii). We have that e e = e (e 0) = (e e) 0 = e 0 = e. Hence, e e = e (e e ) = e e = 0. Since e e = e e = e (e e) = 0, we obtain that e e e = e. But, e e e so e e e. We have that e e = e. (iii) (i). Applying (c 59 ), e e = 1 (e e ) e = 1 and (e e) e = 1. By (iii), e e = e, hence (e e) e = 1. We also have that e e = e (e 0) = (e e) 0 = e 0 = e. So, (e e ) e = 1. We deduce that e e = 1, that is, e B(A), from Proposition 6. (i) (iv). See Proposition 7. (iv) (i). If x L, then from (e x) e = e we deduce (e x) [(e x) e] = (e x) e, hence (e x) e = e x. For x = 0 we obtain that e e = 0. Also, from hypothesis (for x = 0) we obtain e e = e. So, from (c 59 ) we obtain e e = [(e e ) e ] [(e e) e] = [(e e ) e ] (e e) = [(e e ) e ] 1 = (e e ) e (c 30) = [e (e e )] = (e e ) = 0 = 1, hence e B(L), from Proposition 6. Proposition 9. Let L be a residuated lattice. For e L we consider the following assertions: (i) e B(L);

18 304 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 18 (vi) (e e ) (e e) = 1. Then (i) (vi) but (vi) (i). Proof. (i) (vi) If e B(L) from (c 58 ) for x = e we deduce that (e e ) (e e) = 1. (vi) (i). Consider the residuated lattice L = {0, a, b, c, 1} from the Example 4; it is easy to verify that B(L) = {0, 1}. We have (c c ) (c c) = (c 0) (0 c) = 1, but c / B(L). Definition 3. If L is a residuated lattice, we say that an element x L is regular if for every y L we have (x y) x = x. We denote by R(L) the set of all regular elements of L. We say that an element x L is dense if for every r R(L) we have x r = r. We denote by D(L) the set of all dense elements of L. We give a new characterization for regular elements: Theorem 8. Let L be a residuated lattice. assertions are equivalent: For x L the following (i) x R(L); (ii) x x = x. (iii) x = x and x (x x) = 0. Proof. (i) (ii). If x R(L), then (x y) x = x, so for y = 0 we obtain x x = x. (ii) (i). Suppose that x x = x and let y L. Then 0 y x 0 x y x x y (x y) x x x = x. Since x (x y) x we deduce that (x y) x = x, so x R(L). (ii) (iii). Let x L such that x x = x. Then x (x x) = x x = 0. To prove that x = x we use (c 29 ) and the relation x x x = x. (iii) (ii). Since x (x x) = 0 we deduce that x x x = x. But, x x x, so x x = x. From this theorem we obtain that: Corollary 4. If L is a residuated lattice, then R(L) MV (L). Corollary 5. If x, y R(L), then x R(L) and x y R(L).

19 19 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 305 Proof. Let x R(L); by Theorem 8, x = x and x x = x, so x R(L). From x y x x (x y) (x y) x x x = x (x y) x = x. Analogously we deduce that (x y) y = y. Then (x y) (x y) (c 7) = [(x y) x] [(x y) y] = x y x y R(L). A residuated lattice L will be called G- algebra if x 2 = x, for every x L. L is a G-algebra iff x (x y) = x y = x y for every x, y L (see [21]). Remark 9. If L is a G-algebra, then for every x L we deduce that x R(L). Indeed, x verifies the conditions (iii) from the Theorem 8 because x = (x ) and (x ) [(x ) x ] = x (x x ) = x x = 0. Lemma 4. Let L be a residuated lattice. If x L such that x x = x then x x = x. Proof. x x = x (x 0) = (x x) 0 = x 0 = x. We give a new characterization for boolean elements: Theorem 9. Let L be a residuated lattice. assertions are equivalent: For x L the following (i) x B(L); (ii) x R(L), x x = x and (x x ) (x x) = 1. Proof. (i) (ii). If x B(L), then by Proposition 7, x x = x, x = x and x x = 0. Since x (x x) x x = 0 x (x x) = 0, so x R(L) (by Theorem 8, (iii) (i)). By Lemma 4 and Proposition 7, (iii), since x B(L) we deduce that (x x ) (x x) = x x = 1. (ii) (i). Since x x = x, by Lemma 4, x x = x. Since x R(L), then by Theorem 8, (ii), x x = x. Then x x = (x x) (x x ) = 1. Using Proposition 6, we conclude that x B(L). Corollary 6. Let L be a MT L algebra. assertions are equivalent: For x L the following (i) x B(L); (ii) x R(L) and x x = x.

20 306 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 20 Corollary 7. In general, for a residuated lattice L, B(L) R(L). Proof. By Theorem 9 we deduce that B(L) R(L). To prove that B(L) R(L) we consider the residuated lattice L = {0, a, b, c, 1} from Example 4; it is easy to verify that B(L) = {0, 1}. We have a = b, b = a, hence a = b = a and a (a a) = b (b a) = b a = 0, hence a R(L) but a / B(L). Corollary 8. If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice, then B(L) B(MV (L)) R(L). Proof. Since L is semi-divisible then MV (L) is an MV -algebra. Let e B(L). Then by Proposition 7, e = e = (e ) MV (L) and e e = 0. Since e e = 0 e W e = 0 e B(MV (L)), by Theorem 7. We deduce that B(L) B(MV (L)). Consider now e B(MV (L)). Then e = e and e W e = 1. Hence e W e = 1 e W e = 1 (e e ) e = 1 (e e) e = 1 e e = e, hence by Theorem 8, (ii) (i), we deduce that e R(L), so B(L) B(MV (L)) R(L). Corollary 9. If L is a MT L-algebra and x x = x for every x L, then B(L) = R(L). Corollary 10. If L is a semi-divisible M T L-algebra, then B(L) = B(MV (L)). Proof. By Corollary 8, B(L) B(MV (L)) for any semi-divisible residuated lattice L. Consider now that L is a semi-divisible MT L-algebra and let e B(MV (L)). Then e W e = 1 e W e = 1 (e e ) e = 1 (e e ) e = 1 e e = e. Also e W e = 1 e W e = 1 (e e ) e = 1 (e e) e = 1 e e = e. Then e e = (e e ) (e e) = 1, since L is a MT L-algebra, so e B(L) and B(MV (L)) B(L). We deduce that B(L) = B(MV (L)). Corollary 11. If L is a G semi-divisible MT L-algebra, then B(L) = B(MV (L)) = R(L). Remark We consider the residuated lattice from Remark 3, (2) which is not semi-divisible. Let c = 1 2. We have 0 = 1, x = 1 2 x, if x (0, 1 2 ), x = 0, if x [ 1 2, 1]. Then, 0 = 0, x = x, if x (0, 1 2 ), x = 1,

21 21 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 307 if x [ 1 2, 1]. Also, 0 0 = 0, x x = x, if x (0, 1 4 ), x x = 1, if x [ 1 4, 1]. We conclude that MV (L) = {x L : x = x} = [0, 1 2 ) {1} (but MV (L) is not an MV-algebra), R(L) = {x L : x x = x} = [0, 1 4 ) {1} and B(L) = {x L : x x = 1} = {0, 1}. So, B(L) R(L) MV (L). 2. If consider the residuated lattice from Remark 3, (3) which is semidivisible we have 0 = 1, x = 1 2, if x (0, 1 2 ], x = 0, if x ( 1 2, 1]. Then, 0 = 0, x = 1 2, if x (0, 1 2 ], x = 1, if x ( 1 2, 1]. Also, 0 0 = 0, x x = 1 2, if x (0, 1 2 ), x x = 1, if x [ 1 2, 1]. We conclude that MV (L) = {x L : x = x} = {0, 1 2, 1} (in this case MV (L) is an MValgebra), R(L) = {x L : x x = x} = {0, 1} and B(L) = {x L : x x = 1} = {0, 1}. Since B(MV (L)) = {x MV (L) : x x = 0} = {0, 1} we have B(L) = R(L) MV (L) and B(L) = B(MV (L)) (since L is semidivisible, see Corollary 8). We characterize the residuated lattices which are Boolean algebras: Theorem 10. For a residuated lattice L the following assertions are equivalent: (i) L is a Boolean algebra relative to the natural ordering; (ii) L is a G - algebra and x = x, for every x L. Proof. (i) (ii). If L is a Boolean algebra relative to the natural ordering, then L becomes a residuated lattice (see Example 3) and x x = x x = x, x = x, for every x L. (ii) (i). Let L be a G - algebra such that x = x, for every x L. Then x y = x y for every x, y L. First we shall prove that x y = x y for every x, y L. Indeed, x, y x y. Let t L such that x, y t. From x t we deduce that t x, hence x y t y t t = t t = (t t ) 0 = t 0 = t = t. Following Proposition 6, to prove that L is a Boolean algebra it will suffice to prove that x x = 1, for every x L. Obviously, x x = x x = 1. Theorem 11. Let L be a residuated lattice. For x L the following assertions are equivalent: (i) x D(L); (ii) x = 0.

22 308 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 22 Proof. (i) (ii). Since (0 y) 0 = 1 0 = 0 for every y L, we deduce that 0 R(L). Let x D(L); since 0 R(L), we obtain x 0 = 0, hence x = 0. (ii) (i). Let now x L such that x = 0 and r R(L) (hence r = r, by Theorem 8). Then x r = x r = x (r 0) (c 14) = r (x 0) = r x = r 0 = r = r, hence x D(L). Proposition 10. If L is a G-algebra, then: (i) For every x L, x x D(L); (ii) x D(L) iff x = y y for some y L; (iii) For every x L, x (x x) = x and (x x) x = x. Proof. (i). Since x, x x x, we deduce that (x x) x x x, hence (x x) x x so (x x) (x x) (x x) (x x) (x x) 0 (x x) = 0 x x D(L). (ii). By (i), if x = y y for some y L, we deduce that x D(L). Conversely, let x D(L). Then for y = x we obtain x x = 0 x = 1 x = x. (iii). First we prove that x (x x) = x. Clearly, x x, x x. Let t A such that t x, x x. We deduce that x t x, hence t x t x, so t t = t x, that is, x (x x) = x. We prove now that (x x) x = x. Since x (x x) = x and L is a G- algebra we deduce that x (x x) = x, so x (x x) x. Hence x (x x) x. Since x x (x x) x (x x) x (c 32) = x (x x). From (i), x x D(L) for every x L, so (x x) x x 0 = x. We deduce that (x x) x = x. Corollary 12. If L is a G-algebra, then for every x L there are y R(L) and z D(L) such that x = y z. Proof. We have y = x R(L) and z = x x D(L). 5. Semi-G-algebras Definition 4 ([12], [23]). A non empty subset D L is called a deductive system of L, ds for short, if the following conditions are satisfied:

23 23 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 309 (Ds 1 ) 1 D; (Ds 2 ) If x, x y D, then y D. A ds D of L is called proper if D L. Remark 11 ([12], [23]). A nonempty subset D L is a ds of L iff: (Ds 1 ) If x, y D, then x y D; (Ds 2 ) If x D, y L, x y, then y D. We denote by Ds(L) the set of all deductive systems of L. For a nonempty subset S L, the smallest ds of L which contains S, i.e. {D Ds(L) : S D}, is said to be the ds of L generated by S and will be denoted by < S >. For D 1, D 2 Ds(L) we put D 1 D 2 = D 1 D 2 and D 1 D 2 =< D 1 D 2 >. The lattice (Ds(L), ) is a complete Brouwerian lattice (hence distributive). We say ([21]) that D Ds(L) is prime if D L and D verify one of the equivalent assertions: (i) If D = D 1 D 2 with D 1, D 2 Ds(L), then D = D 1 or D = D 2 ; (ii) For a, b L, if a b D, then a D or b D. We denote by Spec(L) the set of all prime deductive systems of L. A ds of L is maximal if it is proper and it is not contained in any other proper ds. In a nontrivial residuated lattice L, every proper ds can be extended to a maximal ds. We shall denote by Max(L) the set of all maximal ds of L. Obviously, Max(L) Spec(L). In what follow, we present new results relative to lattice of maximal deductive systems of a residuated lattice. We prove that if L is semi-divisible, then there is a bijective correspondence between maximal deductive systems of L and maximal deductive systems of MV (L). Also, we characterize Rad(M V (L)), for a semi-divisible residuated lattice L. Theorem 12 ([5]). Let L be a residuated lattice and M a proper ds of L. Then the following are equivalent: (i) M Max(L),

24 310 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 24 (ii) For any x L, x / M iff (x n ) M, for some n 1. Corollary 13. Let L be a residuated lattice. If M M ax(l) and x, y L such that (x n ) y M, for any n 1, then x M or y M. Proof. Let x, y L such that (x n ) y M for any n 1 and suppose that x / M and y / M. From Theorem 12 we deduce that there is n 0 1 such that (x n 0 ) M. Since (x n 0 ), (x n 0 ) y M y M, a contradiction. Theorem 13. Let L be a residuated lattice. If M is a proper ds of L, then the following are equivalent: (i) M Max(L), (ii) If x / M, then there is n 1 such that x n y M, for every y L. Proof. (i) (ii). If we suppose that x / M then by Theorem 12 there is n 1 such that (x n ) M. Because (x n ) x n y for every y L we deduce that x n y M, for every y L. (ii) (i). Let D Ds(L) proper such that M D, hence there is x 0 D such that x 0 / M. Then there is n 1 such that x n 0 y M, for every y L. Hence x n 0 y D. Since D Ds(L) and x 0 D we deduce that x n 0 D. From xn 0, xn 0 y D y D, for every y L. Hence D = L, a contradiction. Proposition 11. Let M Max(L) and x L. Then x M iff x M. Proof. If x M since x x, then x M. Conversely, let x L such that x M and suppose by contrary that x / M. Since M Max(L), then there is n 1 such that (x n ) M. Following (c 35 ), (x ) n (x n ), so (x n ) M. From (x n ), (x n ) M 0 M M = L, a contradiction. Remark 12. In a residuated lattice L, the following are equivalent: (i) x x = x for every x L; (ii) (x 2 ) = x for every x L; (iii) (x n ) = x for every x L and n 2;

25 25 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 311 (iv) x (x x ) = 0 for every x L. Definition 5. L is called semi G-algebra if it verifies one of equivalent conditions of Remark 12. We recall that a residuated lattice L is called a G-algebra if x 2 = x for every x L. We will show that not every residuated lattice is semi G-algebra and, moreover, there are residuated lattices that are semi G-algebras but not G-algebras. Indeed, consider L = [0, 1] such that (L, max, min,,, 0, 1) is a Product structure or Gaines structure, see Example 2. For x = 0, (0 2 ) = 0 = 1 = 0 and for x > 0 x = x 0 = 0/x = 0. Since x 2 > 0 (x 2 ) = x 2 0 = 0/x 2 = 0, so (x 2 ) = x = 0, hence L is a semi ) 2 = G-algebra. Since ( 1 2, L is not a G-algebra. Consider L from Example 1 for p = 1. Then ( 1 ) 2 = = max{0, } = min{1, 1 2 } = 1 2 and ( 1 [ ( 2 1 ) ] 2 2 = = ( 1 2), hence L is not a semi G-algebra. 2 ) = = min{1, 1 1} = 0, so Lemma 5. If L is a semi G-algebra and x, y R(L), then x y R(L). In particular x R(L) x R(L). Proof. If x, y R(L), following Theorem 8, x = x and y = y. By (c 34 ), (x y) x y = x y, so (x y) = x y. By (c 15 ), (x y) (x y) [(x y) (x y) ] [(x y) (x y) ] = [(x y) ] 2 0 = ([(x y) ] 2 ) = [(x y) ] = (x y) = x y, hence (x y) (x y) x y (x y) (x y) = x y x y R(L). For D Ds(L), we consider φ D : L {0, 1} defined for x L by φ D (x) = 1 if x D and φ D (x) = 0 if x / D. Lemma 6. Let D Ds(L) proper. Then: (i) φ D (0) = 0, φ D (1) = 1, φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) and φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y), for every x, y L; (ii) If D Spec(L), then φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y), for every x, y L; (iii) If L is a semi G-algebra and D Max(L) then φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y), for every x, y L.

26 312 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 26 Proof. (i). Since 0 / D and 1 D, then φ D (0) = 0 and φ D (1) = 1. Consider x, y L. If x y D, then x, y D, so φ D (x y) = 1 = 1 1 = φ D (x) φ D (y). If x y / D, then we deduce that x / D or y / D, so φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 0. If x y D then x, y D, so φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 1. If x y / D, then x / D or y / D (since if by contrary x D and y D x y D x y D ), so φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 0. (ii). If x y D, since D is prime, then x D or y D, so φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 1. If x y / D, then x / D and y / D, so φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 0. (iii). Consider x, y L such that x y D. If x D, then y D, so φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 1. If x / D and y D, then φ D (x) φ D (y) = 0 1 = 1 φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 1. If x / D and y / D, then φ D (x) φ D (y) = 0 0 = 1 φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) = 1. If x y / D, then y / D. To prove the equality φ D (x y) = φ D (x) φ D (y) it is necessary to prove that φ D (x) = 1, that is x D. If by contrary x / D, since D Max(L), then there is n 1 such that (x n ) D. Since L is supposed to be a semi G-algebra, then (x n ) = x, so x D. Since x x y, then x y D, a contradiction. Corollary 14. If L is a semi G-algebra and M Max(L), then φ M : L {0, 1} is a morphism of residuated lattices and Ker(f M ) = M. Proof. Using Lemma 6, φ M is a morphism of residuated lattices. Obviously, Ker(φ M ) = M, because Ker(φ M ) = {x L : φ M (x) = 1} = {x L : x M} = M. Theorem 14. If L is a semi G-algebra, then there is a bijection between Max(L) and RL(L, {0, 1}) = { f : L {0, 1} f is a morphism of residuated lattices}. Proof. We define α : Max(L) RL(L, {0, 1}) by α(m) = f M, for every M Max(L) and β : RL(L, {0, 1}) Max(L) by β(f) = Ker(f), for every f RL(L, {0, 1}). Ker(f) Max(L) because if x / Ker(f) then f(x) = 0. Since f(x ) = (f(x)) = 0 = 1, we deduce that x Ker(f), so Ker(f) Max(L). For M Max(L), (β α)(m) = β(α(m)) = Ker(f M ) = M, from Corollary 14,

27 27 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 313 that is, β α = 1 Max(L). If f RL(L, {0, 1}), then (α β)(f) = α(β(f)) = f Ker(f). We prove that f Ker(f) = f. If x Ker(f), then f(x) = 1, so f Ker(f) (x) = 1 and if x / Ker(f), then f(x) = 0, so f Ker(f) (x) = 0. We deduce that α β = 1 RL(L,{0,1}), so α, β are bijections. We recall that an MV -algebra is an algebra (M,,, 0) of type (2, 1, 0) such that (M,, 0) is a commutative monoid, x = x for every x M and (x y) y = (y x) x, for every x, y M. We denote 0 = 1. For x, y M we denote x y = (x y ) and x y = x y. Then ([23]), (M,,,,, 0, 1) is a BL-algebra, where for x, y M, x y = (x y) y and x y = (x y ). Conversely, a BL-algebra (L,,,,, 0, 1) is an MV -algebra iff x = x for every x L, where x = x 0. Lemma 7. Let L be a residuated lattice. If D Ds(L), then D MV (L) = {y MV (L) : y = x for some x D}. Proof. If y MV (L) such that y = x with x D, since x x, then y D, hence y D MV (L). Conversely, if y D MV (L), then y D and y = x (with x L). We have y = x = x = y. Suppose L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice. Then M V (L) is an MV algebra (by Corollary 2), hence a BL algebra and by Ds(MV (L)) we denote the set of all deductive systems of MV (L). We recall that for x, y MV (L), x y = x y (so x y = x y). Lemma 8. If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice and D Ds(L), then D MV (L) Ds(MV (L)). Proof. Clearly 1 D MV (L). Let x, y MV (L) such that x, x y D MV (L). Since D Ds(L) and x, x y D, then y D, hence y D MV (L), so D MV (L) Ds(MV (L)). Lemma 9. If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice and M Max(L), then M MV (L) Max(MV (L)). Proof. We have M L. If M MV (L) = MV (L), then MV (L) M 0 M M = L, a contradiction. So, M MV (L) is proper in MV (L). To prove M MV (L) is maximal in MV (L), suppose by contrary that there is N Ds(MV (L)) such that M MV (L) N MV (L). Then there is x 0 N such that x 0 / M MV (L). Then x 0 / M hence there is

28 314 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 28 n 1 such that (x n 0 ) M (x n 0 ) M MV (L) N (x n 0 ) N. Since x n 0 N 0 N N = MV (L), so M MV (L) Max(MV (L)). Let L be a semi-divisible residuated lattice. For D Ds(MV (L)) we denote by D = {x L : x D} (since x x we deduce that D D). Lemma 10. Let L be a semi-divisible residuated lattice. (i) If D Ds(MV (L)), then D Ds(L); (ii) If M Max(MV (L)), then M Max(L). Proof. (i). Since 1 D and 1 = 1 1 D. If x, y L, x y and x D then x D and from x y y D y D. If x, y D, then x, y D x y D MV (L) x y = (x y ) = [x (y 0)] = (x y ) = (x y ) = (y x ) = (y x ) = (x y ) = [(x y) ] = (x y) x y D. (ii). Suppose M Max(MV (L)). Then M MV (L). If M = L, then 0 M 0 = 0 M M = MV (L), a contradiction. Hence M is proper in L. To prove M Max(L), consider N Ds(L) such that M N L. Then there is x 0 N such that x 0 / M; hence x 0 / M. Since M Max(MV (L)), there is n 1 such that [(x 0 )n ] M M [(x 0 )n ] M N [(x 0 )n ] N. But x 0 N x 0 N (x 0 )n N 0 N N = L. Lemma 11. Let L be a semi-divisible residuated lattice. Then: (i) If M Max(L), then M = M MV (L); (ii) If N Max(MV (L)), then N = N MV (L). Proof. (i). If M Max(L), by Lemma 9, M MV (L) Max(MV (L)) and from Lemma 10, (ii), we deduce that M MV (L) Max(L). Since for x M x M MV (L), then x M MV (L) M M MV (L) M = M MV (L). (ii). Since N Max(MV (L)), by Lemma 10, (ii), N Max(L), so by Lemma 9, N MV (L) Max(MV (L)). If y N MV (L), then y = x for some x N x N N MV (L) N N MV (L) = N.

29 29 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 315 Theorem 15. If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice, then there is a bijection between Max(L) and Max(MV (L)). Proof. Following Lemma 9 and Lemma 10 we deduce that we can define f : Max(L) Max(MV (L)), by f(m) = M MV (L), for every M Max(L) and g : Max(MV (L)) Max(L), by g(n) = N, for every N Max(MV (L)). By Lemma 11 we deduce that f g = 1 Max(MV (L)) and g f = 1 Max(L), hence we deduce that f is bijective and f 1 = g. Definition 6 ([23]). A residuated lattice L is called semilocal (local) if it contains only a finite number (only one) of maximal deductive systems. Clearly, if L is a chain, then L is local. Following Theorem 15 we have: Theorem 16. If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice, then L is a semilocal residuated lattice iff MV (L) is a semilocal MV -algebra. 6. The radical of a semi-divisible residuated lattice Definition 7 ([12]). The intersection of the maximal deductive systems of a residuated lattice L is called the radical of L and will be denoted by Rad(L). For n 1 and x L we denote ñx = [(x ) n ]. Following [11], [12], Rad(L) = {x L : for every n 1 there is k n 1 such that k n (x n ) = 1} = {x L : for every n 1 there is k n 1 such that [(x n ) ] kn = 0}. If L is a BL-algebra, then Rad(L) = {x L : (x n ) x, for every n 1} (see [23]). Proposition 12. If L is a chain, then Rad(L) = {x L : x n > x, for every n 1}. Proof. If L is a chain, then there is an unique maximal deductive system M of L, so Rad(L) = M. If x M then x n M, for every n 1, hence x n > (x n ) (because if by contrary x n (x n ) (x n ) M 0 M, a contradiction). Since x n < x (x n ) > x, so x n > x. Conversely, let x L such that x n > x, for every n 1. Then x n 0 for every n 1 < x > is proper x < x > M = Rad(L). Now, we characterize Rad(MV (L)), for a semi-divisible residuated lattice L.

30 316 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU 30 Theorem 17. If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice, then Rad(MV (L)) Rad(L) MV (L). Proof. Clearly, Rad(MV (L)) MV (L). We prove now that Rad(MV (L)) Rad(L). Suppose that there is an element x Rad(MV (L)) such that x / Rad(L). Then there is M Max(L) such that x / M. Thus, there is n 1 such that [(x ) n ] M. Because [(x ) n ] = ([(x ) n ] ) we deduce that [(x ) n ] M MV (L), which is maximal in MV (L), see Lemma 9. Since x Rad(MV (L)) M MV (L) we obtain that (x ) n M MV (L), so 0 = (x ) n [(x ) n ] M MV (L), a contradiction because M MV (L) is proper. So, Rad(MV (L)) Rad(L) MV (L). Theorem 18. If L is a semi-divisible residuated lattice and x Rad(L), then x Rad(MV (L)). Proof. Let x Rad(L) and suppose that x / Rad(MV (L)). Then there is M Max(MV (L)) such that x / M. Thus, there is n 1 such that [(x ) n ] M. Because [(x ) n ] = ([(x ) n ] ) we deduce that [(x ) n ] M, which is maximal in L. Since x Rad(L) M we obtain that (x ) n M, so 0 = (x ) n [(x ) n ] M, a contradiction because M is proper. So, if x Rad(L), then x Rad(MV (L)). Theorem 19. Let L be a semi-divisible residuated lattice and x L. Then, x Rad(L) x Rad(MV (L)). Proof. Let x Rad(L). From Theorem 18, (x ) = x Rad(MV (L)). Conversely, let x Rad(MV (L)). By Theorem 17, we deduce that x Rad(L). Corollary 15. Rad(L) MV (L) Rad(MV (L)). From Theorem 17 and Corollary 15 we deduce that: Corollary 16. For a semi-divisible residuated lattice L, Rad(M V (L)) = Rad(L) MV (L).

31 31 DIVISIBLE AND SEMI-DIVISIBLE RESIDUATED LATTICES 317 REFERENCES 1. Balbes, R.; Dwinger, P. Distributive Lattices, University of Missouri Press, Columbia, Mo., Blyth, T.S.; Janowitz, M.F. Residuation Theory, International Series of Monographs in Pure and Applied Mathematics, Vol. 102, Pergamon Press, Oxford-New York-Toronto, Ont., Blok, W.J.; Pigozzi, D. Algebraizable logics, Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 77 (1989), no Buşneag, D.; Piciu, D. BL-algebra of fractions relative to an -closed system, An. Ştiinţ. Univ. Ovidius Constanţa Ser. Mat., 11 (2003), Buşneag, D.; Piciu, D. Residuated lattice of fractions relative to a -closed system, Bull. Math. Soc. Sci. Math. Roumanie (N.S.), 49 (2006), Buşneag, D.; Piciu, D.; Jeflea, A. Archimedean residuated lattices, An. Ştiinţ. Univ. Al.I. Cuza Iaşi. Mat. (N.S.), 56 (2010), Cignoli, R.L.O.; D Ottaviano, I.M.L.; Mundici, D. Algebraic Foundations of Many-Valued Reasoning, Trends in Logic-Studia Logica Library, 7, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Cignoli, R.; Torrens, A. Free algebras in varieties of BL-algebras with a Boolean retract, Algebra Universalis, 48 (2002), Dilworth, R.P. Non-commutative residuated lattices, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 46 (1939), Esteva, F.; Godo, L. Monoidal t-norm based logic: towards a logic for leftcontinuous t-norms, Fuzzy logic, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 124 (2001), Freytes, H. Injectives in residuated algebras, Algebra Universalis, 51 (2004), Galatos, N.; Jipsen, P.; Kowalski, T.; Ono, H. Residuated Lattices: An Algebraic Glimpse at Substructural Logics, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 151, Elsevier B.V., Amsterdam, Grätzer, G. Lattice Theory, First concepts and distributive lattices, W.H. Freeman and Co., San Francisco, Calif., Hájek, P. Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic, Trends in Logic-Studia Logica Library, 4, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Höhle, U. Commutative, Residuated l-monoids, Non-classical logics and their applications to fuzzy subsets (Linz, 1992), , Theory Decis. Lib. Ser. B Math. Statist. Methods, 32, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht, 1995.

32 318 D. BUŞNEAG, D. PICIU and J. PARALESCU Idziak, P.M. Lattice operation in BCK-algebras, Math. Japon., 29 (1984), Iorgulescu, A. Algebras of logic as BCK algebras, Editura ASE, Bucharest, Krull, W. Axiomatische Begründung der allgemeinen Ideal theorie, Sitzung. der phys. medizin. Soc. der Erlangen, 56 (1924), Okada, M.; Terui, K. The finite model property for various fragments of intuitionistic linear logic, J. Symbolic Logic, 64 (1999), Pavelka, J. On fuzzy logic. II, Enriched residuated lattices and semantics of propositional calculi, Z. Math. Logik Grundlag. Math., 25 (1979), Piciu, D. Algebras of Fuzzy Logic, Ed. Universitaria, Craiova, Turunen, E.; Mertanen, J. States on semi-divisible residuated lattices, Soft Comput., (2008) 12, Turunen, E. Mathematics Behind Fuzzy Logic, Advances in Soft Computing, Physica-Verlag, Heidelberg, Turunen, E.; Sessa, S. Local BL-algebras, G.C. Moisil memorial issue. Mult.- Valued Log., 6 (2001), Ward, M. Residuated distributive lattices, Duke Math. J., 6 (1940), Ward, M.; Dilworth, R.P. Residuated lattices, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 45 (1939), Received: 25.VI.2012 Revised: 20.VII.2012 Accepted: 24.VII.2012 Faculty of Exacte Sciences, Department of Mathematics, University of Craiova, , Craiova, ROMANIA busneag@central.ucv.ro danap@central.ucv.ro paralescu iustin@yahoo.com

PURITY IN IDEAL LATTICES. Abstract.

PURITY IN IDEAL LATTICES. Abstract. ANALELE ŞTIINŢIFICE ALE UNIVERSITĂŢII AL.I.CUZA IAŞI Tomul XLV, s.i a, Matematică, 1999, f.1. PURITY IN IDEAL LATTICES BY GRIGORE CĂLUGĂREANU Abstract. In [4] T. HEAD gave a general definition of purity

More information

CONGRUENCES AND IDEALS IN A DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICE WITH RESPECT TO A DERIVATION

CONGRUENCES AND IDEALS IN A DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICE WITH RESPECT TO A DERIVATION Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 42:1/2 (2013), pp. 1 10 M. Sambasiva Rao CONGRUENCES AND IDEALS IN A DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICE WITH RESPECT TO A DERIVATION Abstract Two types of congruences are introduced

More information

The illustrated zoo of order-preserving functions

The illustrated zoo of order-preserving functions The illustrated zoo of order-preserving functions David Wilding, February 2013 http://dpw.me/mathematics/ Posets (partially ordered sets) underlie much of mathematics, but we often don t give them a second

More information

CATEGORICAL SKEW LATTICES

CATEGORICAL SKEW LATTICES CATEGORICAL SKEW LATTICES MICHAEL KINYON AND JONATHAN LEECH Abstract. Categorical skew lattices are a variety of skew lattices on which the natural partial order is especially well behaved. While most

More information

Ideals and involutive filters in residuated lattices

Ideals and involutive filters in residuated lattices Ideals and involutive filters in residuated lattices Jiří Rachůnek and Dana Šalounová Palacký University in Olomouc VŠB Technical University of Ostrava Czech Republic SSAOS 2014, Stará Lesná, September

More information

THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET

THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET MICHAEL PINSKER Abstract. We calculate the number of unary clones (submonoids of the full transformation monoid) containing the

More information

LATTICE EFFECT ALGEBRAS DENSELY EMBEDDABLE INTO COMPLETE ONES

LATTICE EFFECT ALGEBRAS DENSELY EMBEDDABLE INTO COMPLETE ONES K Y BERNETIKA VOLUM E 47 ( 2011), NUMBER 1, P AGES 100 109 LATTICE EFFECT ALGEBRAS DENSELY EMBEDDABLE INTO COMPLETE ONES Zdenka Riečanová An effect algebraic partial binary operation defined on the underlying

More information

Theorem 1.3. Every finite lattice has a congruence-preserving embedding to a finite atomistic lattice.

Theorem 1.3. Every finite lattice has a congruence-preserving embedding to a finite atomistic lattice. CONGRUENCE-PRESERVING EXTENSIONS OF FINITE LATTICES TO SEMIMODULAR LATTICES G. GRÄTZER AND E.T. SCHMIDT Abstract. We prove that every finite lattice hasa congruence-preserving extension to a finite semimodular

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF CODES BY LATTICE VALUED FUZZY SETS. 1. Introduction. Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 35, No. 2, 2005,

CONSTRUCTION OF CODES BY LATTICE VALUED FUZZY SETS. 1. Introduction. Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 35, No. 2, 2005, Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 35, No. 2, 2005, 155-160 CONSTRUCTION OF CODES BY LATTICE VALUED FUZZY SETS Mališa Žižović 1, Vera Lazarević 2 Abstract. To every finite lattice L, one can associate a binary blockcode,

More information

Epimorphisms and Ideals of Distributive Nearlattices

Epimorphisms and Ideals of Distributive Nearlattices Annals of Pure and Applied Mathematics Vol. 18, No. 2, 2018,175-179 ISSN: 2279-087X (P), 2279-0888(online) Published on 9 November 2018 www.researchmathsci.org DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.22457/apam.v18n2a5

More information

Gödel algebras free over finite distributive lattices

Gödel algebras free over finite distributive lattices TANCL, Oxford, August 4-9, 2007 1 Gödel algebras free over finite distributive lattices Stefano Aguzzoli Brunella Gerla Vincenzo Marra D.S.I. D.I.COM. D.I.C.O. University of Milano University of Insubria

More information

ON THE LATTICE OF ORTHOMODULAR LOGICS

ON THE LATTICE OF ORTHOMODULAR LOGICS Jacek Malinowski ON THE LATTICE OF ORTHOMODULAR LOGICS Abstract The upper part of the lattice of orthomodular logics is described. In [1] and [2] Bruns and Kalmbach have described the lower part of the

More information

GUESSING MODELS IMPLY THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 25 Mar 2019

GUESSING MODELS IMPLY THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 25 Mar 2019 GUESSING MODELS IMPLY THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS arxiv:1903.10476v1 [math.lo] 25 Mar 2019 Abstract. In this article we prove three main theorems: (1) guessing models are internally unbounded, (2)

More information

Skew lattices of matrices in rings

Skew lattices of matrices in rings Algebra univers. 53 (2005) 471 479 0002-5240/05/040471 09 DOI 10.1007/s00012-005-1913-5 c Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel, 2005 Algebra Universalis Skew lattices of matrices in rings Karin Cvetko-Vah Abstract.

More information

The finite lattice representation problem and intervals in subgroup lattices of finite groups

The finite lattice representation problem and intervals in subgroup lattices of finite groups The finite lattice representation problem and intervals in subgroup lattices of finite groups William DeMeo Math 613: Group Theory 15 December 2009 Abstract A well-known result of universal algebra states:

More information

Lattice Laws Forcing Distributivity Under Unique Complementation

Lattice Laws Forcing Distributivity Under Unique Complementation Lattice Laws Forcing Distributivity Under Unique Complementation R. Padmanabhan Department of Mathematics University of Manitoba Winnipeg, Manitoba R3T 2N2 Canada W. McCune Mathematics and Computer Science

More information

Translates of (Anti) Fuzzy Submodules

Translates of (Anti) Fuzzy Submodules International Journal of Engineering Research and Development e-issn: 2278-067X, p-issn : 2278-800X, www.ijerd.com Volume 5, Issue 2 (December 2012), PP. 27-31 P.K. Sharma Post Graduate Department of Mathematics,

More information

On the h-vector of a Lattice Path Matroid

On the h-vector of a Lattice Path Matroid On the h-vector of a Lattice Path Matroid Jay Schweig Department of Mathematics University of Kansas Lawrence, KS 66044 jschweig@math.ku.edu Submitted: Sep 16, 2009; Accepted: Dec 18, 2009; Published:

More information

A Property Equivalent to n-permutability for Infinite Groups

A Property Equivalent to n-permutability for Infinite Groups Journal of Algebra 221, 570 578 (1999) Article ID jabr.1999.7996, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on A Property Equivalent to n-permutability for Infinite Groups Alireza Abdollahi* and Aliakbar

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 24 Feb 2014

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 24 Feb 2014 Residuated Basic Logic II. Interpolation, Decidability and Embedding Minghui Ma 1 and Zhe Lin 2 arxiv:1404.7401v1 [math.lo] 24 Feb 2014 1 Institute for Logic and Intelligence, Southwest University, Beibei

More information

Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA

Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA THE CLASSIFICATION OF DIGITAL COVERING SPACES Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA Abstract. In this paper we classify digital covering spaces using the conjugacy class corresponding to a digital covering space.

More information

LATTICE LAWS FORCING DISTRIBUTIVITY UNDER UNIQUE COMPLEMENTATION

LATTICE LAWS FORCING DISTRIBUTIVITY UNDER UNIQUE COMPLEMENTATION LATTICE LAWS FORCING DISTRIBUTIVITY UNDER UNIQUE COMPLEMENTATION R. PADMANABHAN, W. MCCUNE, AND R. VEROFF Abstract. We give several new lattice identities valid in nonmodular lattices such that a uniquely

More information

Homomorphism and Cartesian Product of. Fuzzy PS Algebras

Homomorphism and Cartesian Product of. Fuzzy PS Algebras Applied Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 8, 2014, no. 67, 3321-3330 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/10.12988/ams.2014.44265 Homomorphism and Cartesian Product of Fuzzy PS Algebras T. Priya Department

More information

ORDERED SEMIGROUPS HAVING THE P -PROPERTY. Niovi Kehayopulu, Michael Tsingelis

ORDERED SEMIGROUPS HAVING THE P -PROPERTY. Niovi Kehayopulu, Michael Tsingelis ORDERED SEMIGROUPS HAVING THE P -PROPERTY Niovi Kehayopulu, Michael Tsingelis ABSTRACT. The main results of the paper are the following: The ordered semigroups which have the P -property are decomposable

More information

Residuated Lattices of Size 12 extended version

Residuated Lattices of Size 12 extended version Residuated Lattices of Size 12 extended version Radim Belohlavek 1,2, Vilem Vychodil 1,2 1 Dept. Computer Science, Palacky University, Olomouc 17. listopadu 12, Olomouc, CZ 771 46, Czech Republic 2 SUNY

More information

Cut-free sequent calculi for algebras with adjoint modalities

Cut-free sequent calculi for algebras with adjoint modalities Cut-free sequent calculi for algebras with adjoint modalities Roy Dyckhoff (University of St Andrews) and Mehrnoosh Sadrzadeh (Universities of Oxford & Southampton) TANCL Conference, Oxford, 8 August 2007

More information

FUZZY PRIME L-FILTERS

FUZZY PRIME L-FILTERS International Journal of Applied Mathematical Sciences ISSN 0973-0176 Volume 9, Number 1 (2016), pp. 37-44 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com FUZZY PRIME L-FILTERS M. Mullai Assistant

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 13 Feb 2014

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 13 Feb 2014 A LOWER BOUND FOR GENERALIZED DOMINATING NUMBERS arxiv:1401.7948v2 [math.lo] 13 Feb 2014 DAN HATHAWAY Abstract. We show that when κ and λ are infinite cardinals satisfying λ κ = λ, the cofinality of the

More information

Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA

Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA SOME PROPERTIES OF DIGITAL COVERING SPACES Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA Abstract. In this paper we study digital versions of some properties of covering spaces from algebraic topology. We correct and

More information

Fuzzy L-Quotient Ideals

Fuzzy L-Quotient Ideals International Journal of Fuzzy Mathematics and Systems. ISSN 2248-9940 Volume 3, Number 3 (2013), pp. 179-187 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com Fuzzy L-Quotient Ideals M. Mullai

More information

Ordered Semigroups in which the Left Ideals are Intra-Regular Semigroups

Ordered Semigroups in which the Left Ideals are Intra-Regular Semigroups International Journal of Algebra, Vol. 5, 2011, no. 31, 1533-1541 Ordered Semigroups in which the Left Ideals are Intra-Regular Semigroups Niovi Kehayopulu University of Athens Department of Mathematics

More information

CARDINALITIES OF RESIDUE FIELDS OF NOETHERIAN INTEGRAL DOMAINS

CARDINALITIES OF RESIDUE FIELDS OF NOETHERIAN INTEGRAL DOMAINS CARDINALITIES OF RESIDUE FIELDS OF NOETHERIAN INTEGRAL DOMAINS KEITH A. KEARNES AND GREG OMAN Abstract. We determine the relationship between the cardinality of a Noetherian integral domain and the cardinality

More information

Some Remarks on Finitely Quasi-injective Modules

Some Remarks on Finitely Quasi-injective Modules EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS Vol. 6, No. 2, 2013, 119-125 ISSN 1307-5543 www.ejpam.com Some Remarks on Finitely Quasi-injective Modules Zhu Zhanmin Department of Mathematics, Jiaxing

More information

General Lattice Theory: 1979 Problem Update

General Lattice Theory: 1979 Problem Update Algebra Universalis, 11 (1980) 396-402 Birkhauser Verlag, Basel General Lattice Theory: 1979 Problem Update G. GRATZER Listed below are all the solutions or partial solutions to problems in the book General

More information

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS 4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS Marek Rutkowski School of Mathematics and Statistics University of Sydney Semester 2, 2016 M. Rutkowski (USydney) Slides 4: Single-Period Market Models 1 / 87 General Single-Period

More information

COLLOQUIA MATHEMATICA SOCIETATIS JANOS BOLYAI SZEGED (HUNGARY), 1980.

COLLOQUIA MATHEMATICA SOCIETATIS JANOS BOLYAI SZEGED (HUNGARY), 1980. COLLOQUIA MATHEMATICA SOCIETATIS JANOS BOLYAI 33. CONTRIBUTIONS TO LATTICE THEORY SZEGED (HUNGARY), 1980. A SURVEY OF PRODUCTS OF LATTICE VARIETIES G. GRATZER - D. KELLY Let y and Wbe varieties of lattices.

More information

Yao s Minimax Principle

Yao s Minimax Principle Complexity of algorithms The complexity of an algorithm is usually measured with respect to the size of the input, where size may for example refer to the length of a binary word describing the input,

More information

Non replication of options

Non replication of options Non replication of options Christos Kountzakis, Ioannis A Polyrakis and Foivos Xanthos June 30, 2008 Abstract In this paper we study the scarcity of replication of options in the two period model of financial

More information

Axiomatizing the Skew Boolean Propositional Calculus

Axiomatizing the Skew Boolean Propositional Calculus Axiomatizing the Skew Boolean Propositional Calculus R. Veroff University of New Mexico M. Spinks La Trobe University April 14, 2007 Abstract. The skew Boolean propositional calculus (SBP C) is a generalization

More information

Interpolation of κ-compactness and PCF

Interpolation of κ-compactness and PCF Comment.Math.Univ.Carolin. 50,2(2009) 315 320 315 Interpolation of κ-compactness and PCF István Juhász, Zoltán Szentmiklóssy Abstract. We call a topological space κ-compact if every subset of size κ has

More information

Equivalence between Semimartingales and Itô Processes

Equivalence between Semimartingales and Itô Processes International Journal of Mathematical Analysis Vol. 9, 215, no. 16, 787-791 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/1.12988/ijma.215.411358 Equivalence between Semimartingales and Itô Processes

More information

On the Number of Permutations Avoiding a Given Pattern

On the Number of Permutations Avoiding a Given Pattern On the Number of Permutations Avoiding a Given Pattern Noga Alon Ehud Friedgut February 22, 2002 Abstract Let σ S k and τ S n be permutations. We say τ contains σ if there exist 1 x 1 < x 2

More information

An Optimal Odd Unimodular Lattice in Dimension 72

An Optimal Odd Unimodular Lattice in Dimension 72 An Optimal Odd Unimodular Lattice in Dimension 72 Masaaki Harada and Tsuyoshi Miezaki September 27, 2011 Abstract It is shown that if there is an extremal even unimodular lattice in dimension 72, then

More information

A Translation of Intersection and Union Types

A Translation of Intersection and Union Types A Translation of Intersection and Union Types for the λ µ-calculus Kentaro Kikuchi RIEC, Tohoku University kentaro@nue.riec.tohoku.ac.jp Takafumi Sakurai Department of Mathematics and Informatics, Chiba

More information

INTERVAL DISMANTLABLE LATTICES

INTERVAL DISMANTLABLE LATTICES INTERVAL DISMANTLABLE LATTICES KIRA ADARICHEVA, JENNIFER HYNDMAN, STEFFEN LEMPP, AND J. B. NATION Abstract. A finite lattice is interval dismantlable if it can be partitioned into an ideal and a filter,

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 27 Mar 2009

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 27 Mar 2009 arxiv:0903.4691v1 [math.lo] 27 Mar 2009 COMBINATORIAL AND MODEL-THEORETICAL PRINCIPLES RELATED TO REGULARITY OF ULTRAFILTERS AND COMPACTNESS OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES. V. PAOLO LIPPARINI Abstract. We generalize

More information

Collinear Triple Hypergraphs and the Finite Plane Kakeya Problem

Collinear Triple Hypergraphs and the Finite Plane Kakeya Problem Collinear Triple Hypergraphs and the Finite Plane Kakeya Problem Joshua Cooper August 14, 006 Abstract We show that the problem of counting collinear points in a permutation (previously considered by the

More information

Applied Mathematics Letters

Applied Mathematics Letters Applied Mathematics Letters 23 (2010) 286 290 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Applied Mathematics Letters journal homepage: wwwelseviercom/locate/aml The number of spanning trees of a graph Jianxi

More information

Computing Unsatisfiable k-sat Instances with Few Occurrences per Variable

Computing Unsatisfiable k-sat Instances with Few Occurrences per Variable Computing Unsatisfiable k-sat Instances with Few Occurrences per Variable Shlomo Hoory and Stefan Szeider Department of Computer Science, University of Toronto, shlomoh,szeider@cs.toronto.edu Abstract.

More information

COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS

COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS DAN HATHAWAY AND SCOTT SCHNEIDER Abstract. We discuss combinatorial conditions for the existence of various types of reductions between equivalence

More information

SHIMON GARTI AND SAHARON SHELAH

SHIMON GARTI AND SAHARON SHELAH (κ, θ)-weak NORMALITY SHIMON GARTI AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We deal with the property of weak normality (for nonprincipal ultrafilters). We characterize the situation of Q λ i/d = λ. We have an application

More information

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models 1.1 Law of one price and Arrow securities 1.2 No-arbitrage theory and

More information

REMARKS ON K3 SURFACES WITH NON-SYMPLECTIC AUTOMORPHISMS OF ORDER 7

REMARKS ON K3 SURFACES WITH NON-SYMPLECTIC AUTOMORPHISMS OF ORDER 7 REMARKS ON K3 SURFACES WTH NON-SYMPLECTC AUTOMORPHSMS OF ORDER 7 SHNGO TAK Abstract. n this note, we treat a pair of a K3 surface and a non-symplectic automorphism of order 7m (m = 1, 3 and 6) on it. We

More information

Projective Lattices. with applications to isotope maps and databases. Ralph Freese CLA La Rochelle

Projective Lattices. with applications to isotope maps and databases. Ralph Freese CLA La Rochelle Projective Lattices with applications to isotope maps and databases Ralph Freese CLA 2013. La Rochelle Ralph Freese () Projective Lattices Oct 2013 1 / 17 Projective Lattices A lattice L is projective

More information

Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data

Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data a thesis submitted to the department of industrial engineering and the institute of engineering and sciences of bilkent university

More information

SEMICENTRAL IDEMPOTENTS IN A RING

SEMICENTRAL IDEMPOTENTS IN A RING J. Korean Math. Soc. 51 (2014), No. 3, pp. 463 472 http://dx.doi.org/10.4134/jkms.2014.51.3.463 SEMICENTRAL IDEMPOTENTS IN A RING Juncheol Han, Yang Lee, and Sangwon Park Abstract. Let R be a ring with

More information

Hyperidentities in (xx)y xy Graph Algebras of Type (2,0)

Hyperidentities in (xx)y xy Graph Algebras of Type (2,0) Int. Journal of Math. Analysis, Vol. 8, 2014, no. 9, 415-426 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/10.12988/ijma.2014.312299 Hyperidentities in (xx)y xy Graph Algebras of Type (2,0) W. Puninagool

More information

CTL Model Checking. Goal Method for proving M sat σ, where M is a Kripke structure and σ is a CTL formula. Approach Model checking!

CTL Model Checking. Goal Method for proving M sat σ, where M is a Kripke structure and σ is a CTL formula. Approach Model checking! CMSC 630 March 13, 2007 1 CTL Model Checking Goal Method for proving M sat σ, where M is a Kripke structure and σ is a CTL formula. Approach Model checking! Mathematically, M is a model of σ if s I = M

More information

New tools of set-theoretic homological algebra and their applications to modules

New tools of set-theoretic homological algebra and their applications to modules New tools of set-theoretic homological algebra and their applications to modules Jan Trlifaj Univerzita Karlova, Praha Workshop on infinite-dimensional representations of finite dimensional algebras Manchester,

More information

Ratio Mathematica 20, Gamma Modules. R. Ameri, R. Sadeghi. Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Basic Science

Ratio Mathematica 20, Gamma Modules. R. Ameri, R. Sadeghi. Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Basic Science Gamma Modules R. Ameri, R. Sadeghi Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Basic Science University of Mazandaran, Babolsar, Iran e-mail: ameri@umz.ac.ir Abstract Let R be a Γ-ring. We introduce the notion

More information

1 Directed sets and nets

1 Directed sets and nets subnets2.tex April 22, 2009 http://thales.doa.fmph.uniba.sk/sleziak/texty/rozne/topo/ This text contains notes for my talk given at our topology seminar. It compares 3 different definitions of subnets.

More information

A No-Arbitrage Theorem for Uncertain Stock Model

A No-Arbitrage Theorem for Uncertain Stock Model Fuzzy Optim Decis Making manuscript No (will be inserted by the editor) A No-Arbitrage Theorem for Uncertain Stock Model Kai Yao Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract Stock model is used to describe

More information

A note on the number of (k, l)-sum-free sets

A note on the number of (k, l)-sum-free sets A note on the number of (k, l)-sum-free sets Tomasz Schoen Mathematisches Seminar Universität zu Kiel Ludewig-Meyn-Str. 4, 4098 Kiel, Germany tos@numerik.uni-kiel.de and Department of Discrete Mathematics

More information

3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure

3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure Mathematical Models in Economics and Finance Topic 3 Fundamental theorem of asset pricing 3.1 Law of one price and Arrow securities 3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure 3.3 Valuation

More information

INFLATION OF FINITE LATTICES ALONG ALL-OR-NOTHING SETS TRISTAN HOLMES J. B. NATION

INFLATION OF FINITE LATTICES ALONG ALL-OR-NOTHING SETS TRISTAN HOLMES J. B. NATION INFLATION OF FINITE LATTICES ALONG ALL-OR-NOTHING SETS TRISTAN HOLMES J. B. NATION Department of Mathematics, University of Hawaii, Honolulu, HI 96822, USA Phone:(808)956-4655 Abstract. We introduce a

More information

Browder-type theorems for direct sums of operators

Browder-type theorems for direct sums of operators Functional Analysis, Approximation and Computation 7 (1) (2015), 77 84 Published by Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, University of Niš, Serbia Available at: http://www.pmf.ni.ac.rs/faac Browder-type

More information

MITCHELL S THEOREM REVISITED. Contents

MITCHELL S THEOREM REVISITED. Contents MITCHELL S THEOREM REVISITED THOMAS GILTON AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. Mitchell s theorem on the approachability ideal states that it is consistent relative to a greatly Mahlo cardinal that there is no

More information

Optimal Allocation of Policy Limits and Deductibles

Optimal Allocation of Policy Limits and Deductibles Optimal Allocation of Policy Limits and Deductibles Ka Chun Cheung Email: kccheung@math.ucalgary.ca Tel: +1-403-2108697 Fax: +1-403-2825150 Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Calgary,

More information

An orderly algorithm to enumerate finite (semi)modular lattices

An orderly algorithm to enumerate finite (semi)modular lattices An orderly algorithm to enumerate finite (semi)modular lattices BLAST 23 Chapman University October 6, 23 Outline The original algorithm: Generating all finite lattices Generating modular and semimodular

More information

Introduction to Priestley duality 1 / 24

Introduction to Priestley duality 1 / 24 Introduction to Priestley duality 1 / 24 2 / 24 Outline What is a distributive lattice? Priestley duality for finite distributive lattices Using the duality: an example Priestley duality for infinite distributive

More information

Sy D. Friedman. August 28, 2001

Sy D. Friedman. August 28, 2001 0 # and Inner Models Sy D. Friedman August 28, 2001 In this paper we examine the cardinal structure of inner models that satisfy GCH but do not contain 0 #. We show, assuming that 0 # exists, that such

More information

Chair of Communications Theory, Prof. Dr.-Ing. E. Jorswieck. Übung 5: Supermodular Games

Chair of Communications Theory, Prof. Dr.-Ing. E. Jorswieck. Übung 5: Supermodular Games Chair of Communications Theory, Prof. Dr.-Ing. E. Jorswieck Übung 5: Supermodular Games Introduction Supermodular games are a class of non-cooperative games characterized by strategic complemetariteis

More information

Notes on Natural Logic

Notes on Natural Logic Notes on Natural Logic Notes for PHIL370 Eric Pacuit November 16, 2012 1 Preliminaries: Trees A tree is a structure T = (T, E), where T is a nonempty set whose elements are called nodes and E is a relation

More information

Fuzzy Join - Semidistributive Lattice

Fuzzy Join - Semidistributive Lattice International Journal of Mathematics Research. ISSN 0976-5840 Volume 8, Number 2 (2016), pp. 85-92 International Research Publication House http://www.irphouse.com Fuzzy Join - Semidistributive Lattice

More information

Generating all nite modular lattices of a given size

Generating all nite modular lattices of a given size Generating all nite modular lattices of a given size Peter Jipsen and Nathan Lawless Dedicated to Brian Davey on the occasion of his 65th birthday Abstract. Modular lattices, introduced by R. Dedekind,

More information

AN INFINITE CARDINAL-VALUED KRULL DIMENSION FOR RINGS

AN INFINITE CARDINAL-VALUED KRULL DIMENSION FOR RINGS AN INFINITE CARDINAL-VALUED KRULL DIMENSION FOR RINGS K. ALAN LOPER, ZACHARY MESYAN, AND GREG OMAN Abstract. We define and study two generalizations of the Krull dimension for rings, which can assume cardinal

More information

k-type null slant helices in Minkowski space-time

k-type null slant helices in Minkowski space-time MATHEMATICAL COMMUNICATIONS 8 Math. Commun. 20(2015), 8 95 k-type null slant helices in Minkowski space-time Emilija Nešović 1, Esra Betül Koç Öztürk2, and Ufuk Öztürk2 1 Department of Mathematics and

More information

More On λ κ closed sets in generalized topological spaces

More On λ κ closed sets in generalized topological spaces Journal of Algorithms and Computation journal homepage: http://jac.ut.ac.ir More On λ κ closed sets in generalized topological spaces R. Jamunarani, 1, P. Jeyanthi 2 and M. Velrajan 3 1,2 Research Center,

More information

Continuous images of closed sets in generalized Baire spaces ESI Workshop: Forcing and Large Cardinals

Continuous images of closed sets in generalized Baire spaces ESI Workshop: Forcing and Large Cardinals Continuous images of closed sets in generalized Baire spaces ESI Workshop: Forcing and Large Cardinals Philipp Moritz Lücke (joint work with Philipp Schlicht) Mathematisches Institut, Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität

More information

Congruence lattices of finite intransitive group acts

Congruence lattices of finite intransitive group acts Congruence lattices of finite intransitive group acts Steve Seif June 18, 2010 Finite group acts A finite group act is a unary algebra X = X, G, where G is closed under composition, and G consists of permutations

More information

ON THE EQUATIONAL DEFINABILITY OF BROUWER-ZADEH LATTICES

ON THE EQUATIONAL DEFINABILITY OF BROUWER-ZADEH LATTICES ON THE EQUATIONAL DEFINABILITY OF BROUWER-ZADEH LATTICES M. SPINKS AND R. VEROFF Abstract. We give an axiomatisation of the variety of Brouwer- Zadeh lattices, suitable for applications to quantum theory.

More information

Notes on the symmetric group

Notes on the symmetric group Notes on the symmetric group 1 Computations in the symmetric group Recall that, given a set X, the set S X of all bijections from X to itself (or, more briefly, permutations of X) is group under function

More information

Another Variant of 3sat. 3sat. 3sat Is NP-Complete. The Proof (concluded)

Another Variant of 3sat. 3sat. 3sat Is NP-Complete. The Proof (concluded) 3sat k-sat, where k Z +, is the special case of sat. The formula is in CNF and all clauses have exactly k literals (repetition of literals is allowed). For example, (x 1 x 2 x 3 ) (x 1 x 1 x 2 ) (x 1 x

More information

Modeling the Risk by Credibility Theory

Modeling the Risk by Credibility Theory 2011 3rd International Conference on Advanced Management Science IPEDR vol.19 (2011) (2011) IACSIT Press, Singapore Modeling the Risk by Credibility Theory Irina Georgescu 1 and Jani Kinnunen 2,+ 1 Academy

More information

CHARACTERIZATION OF CLOSED CONVEX SUBSETS OF R n

CHARACTERIZATION OF CLOSED CONVEX SUBSETS OF R n CHARACTERIZATION OF CLOSED CONVEX SUBSETS OF R n Chebyshev Sets A subset S of a metric space X is said to be a Chebyshev set if, for every x 2 X; there is a unique point in S that is closest to x: Put

More information

Generating all modular lattices of a given size

Generating all modular lattices of a given size Generating all modular lattices of a given size ADAM 2013 Nathan Lawless Chapman University June 6-8, 2013 Outline Introduction to Lattice Theory: Modular Lattices The Objective: Generating and Counting

More information

Long-Term Values in MDPs, Corecursively

Long-Term Values in MDPs, Corecursively Long-Term Values in MDPs, Corecursively Applied Category Theory, 15-16 March 2018, NIST Helle Hvid Hansen Delft University of Technology Helle Hvid Hansen (TU Delft) MDPs, Corecursively NIST, 15/Mar/2018

More information

Forecast Horizons for Production Planning with Stochastic Demand

Forecast Horizons for Production Planning with Stochastic Demand Forecast Horizons for Production Planning with Stochastic Demand Alfredo Garcia and Robert L. Smith Department of Industrial and Operations Engineering Universityof Michigan, Ann Arbor MI 48109 December

More information

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies Chapter 10 Elimination by Mixed Strategies The notions of dominance apply in particular to mixed extensions of finite strategic games. But we can also consider dominance of a pure strategy by a mixed strategy.

More information

Unary PCF is Decidable

Unary PCF is Decidable Unary PCF is Decidable Ralph Loader Merton College, Oxford November 1995, revised October 1996 and September 1997. Abstract We show that unary PCF, a very small fragment of Plotkin s PCF [?], has a decidable

More information

ON THE QUOTIENT SHAPES OF VECTORIAL SPACES. Nikica Uglešić

ON THE QUOTIENT SHAPES OF VECTORIAL SPACES. Nikica Uglešić RAD HAZU. MATEMATIČKE ZNANOSTI Vol. 21 = 532 (2017): 179-203 DOI: http://doi.org/10.21857/mzvkptxze9 ON THE QUOTIENT SHAPES OF VECTORIAL SPACES Nikica Uglešić To my Master teacher Sibe Mardešić - with

More information

Undecidability and 1-types in Intervals of the Computably Enumerable Degrees

Undecidability and 1-types in Intervals of the Computably Enumerable Degrees Undecidability and 1-types in Intervals of the Computably Enumerable Degrees Klaus Ambos-Spies Mathematisches Institut, Universität Heidelberg, D-69120 Heidelberg, Germany Denis R. Hirschfeldt Department

More information

3 Arbitrage pricing theory in discrete time.

3 Arbitrage pricing theory in discrete time. 3 Arbitrage pricing theory in discrete time. Orientation. In the examples studied in Chapter 1, we worked with a single period model and Gaussian returns; in this Chapter, we shall drop these assumptions

More information

Permutation Factorizations and Prime Parking Functions

Permutation Factorizations and Prime Parking Functions Permutation Factorizations and Prime Parking Functions Amarpreet Rattan Department of Combinatorics and Optimization University of Waterloo Waterloo, ON, Canada N2L 3G1 arattan@math.uwaterloo.ca June 10,

More information

NOTES ON (T, S)-INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY SUBHEMIRINGS OF A HEMIRING

NOTES ON (T, S)-INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY SUBHEMIRINGS OF A HEMIRING NOTES ON (T, S)-INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY SUBHEMIRINGS OF A HEMIRING K.Umadevi 1, V.Gopalakrishnan 2 1Assistant Professor,Department of Mathematics,Noorul Islam University,Kumaracoil,Tamilnadu,India 2Research

More information

ADDING A LOT OF COHEN REALS BY ADDING A FEW II. 1. Introduction

ADDING A LOT OF COHEN REALS BY ADDING A FEW II. 1. Introduction ADDING A LOT OF COHEN REALS BY ADDING A FEW II MOTI GITIK AND MOHAMMAD GOLSHANI Abstract. We study pairs (V, V 1 ), V V 1, of models of ZF C such that adding κ many Cohen reals over V 1 adds λ many Cohen

More information

Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items

Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items Nir Shabbat - 05305311 December 5, 2012 Introduction The paper I read is called Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items by Sergiu Hart

More information

Lecture l(x) 1. (1) x X

Lecture l(x) 1. (1) x X Lecture 14 Agenda for the lecture Kraft s inequality Shannon codes The relation H(X) L u (X) = L p (X) H(X) + 1 14.1 Kraft s inequality While the definition of prefix-free codes is intuitively clear, we

More information

Conditional Square Functions and Dyadic Perturbations of the Sine-Cosine decomposition for Hardy Martingales

Conditional Square Functions and Dyadic Perturbations of the Sine-Cosine decomposition for Hardy Martingales Conditional Square Functions and Dyadic Perturbations of the Sine-Cosine decomposition for Hardy Martingales arxiv:1611.02653v1 [math.fa] 8 Nov 2016 Paul F. X. Müller October 16, 2016 Abstract We prove

More information

SAT and DPLL. Introduction. Preliminaries. Normal forms DPLL. Complexity. Espen H. Lian. DPLL Implementation. Bibliography.

SAT and DPLL. Introduction. Preliminaries. Normal forms DPLL. Complexity. Espen H. Lian. DPLL Implementation. Bibliography. SAT and Espen H. Lian Ifi, UiO Implementation May 4, 2010 Espen H. Lian (Ifi, UiO) SAT and May 4, 2010 1 / 59 Espen H. Lian (Ifi, UiO) SAT and May 4, 2010 2 / 59 Introduction Introduction SAT is the problem

More information