Information Acquisition under Persuasive Precedent versus Binding Precedent (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Information Acquisition under Persuasive Precedent versus Binding Precedent (Preliminary and Incomplete)"

Transcription

1 Information Acquisition under Persuasive Precedent versus Binding Precedent (Preliminary and Incomplete) Ying Chen Hülya Eraslan January 9, 216 Abstract We analyze a dynamic model of judicial decision making. A court regulates a set of activities by allowing or banning them. In each period a new judge is appointed and a new case arises which must be decided by the judge appointed in that period. The judges share the same preferences over whether a case should be allowed or banned, but they are uncertain about the correct ruling until a costly investigation is made. We compare two institutions: persuasive precedent and binding precedent. Under persuasive precedent, a judge is not required to follow previous rulings but can use the information acquired by the investigations of previous judges. Under binding precedent, however, a judge must follow previous rulings when they apply. We show that the incentives to acquire information for the appointed judges are stronger in earlier periods when there are few precedents under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent, but as more precedents are established over time, the incentive to acquire information for the appointed judge becomes weaker under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent. Department of Economics, Johns Hopkins University Department of Economics, Rice University 1

2 1 Introduction We analyze a dynamic model of judicial decision making. A court regulates a set of activities by allowing or banning them. In each period a new judge is appointed and a new case arises which must be decided by the judge appointed in that period. The judges share the same preferences over whether a case should be allowed or banned, but they are uncertain about the correct ruling until a costly investigation is made. Following Baker and Mezzetti [212], we assume that the judge appointed in a given period can either investigate the case before making a ruling or summarily decide without investigation. We compare two institutions: persuasive precedent and binding precedent. Under persuasive precedent, a judge is not required to follow previous rulings but can use the information acquired by the investigations of previous judges. Under binding precedent, however, a judge must follow previous rulings when they apply. We show that the incentives to acquire information for the appointed judges are stronger in earlier periods when there are few precedents under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent, but as more precedents are established over time, the incentive to acquire information for the appointed judge becomes weaker under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent. To see why, note that the cost of making a wrong summary decision is higher under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent since future judges have to follow precedents when they are binding even if they are erroneous. Hence, a judge who faces few precedents is more inclined to investigate to avoid mistakes under binding precedent. As more precedents are established over time, however, the value of information acquired through investigation becomes lower under binding precedent since future judges may not be able to use the information to make rulings, and this discourages judges from acquiring information under binding precedent. We establish these results first in a simple three-period model and then in an infinite-horizon model. In the infinite horizon model, we show there is a unique Markov perfect equilibrium payoff by showing that the Contraction Mapping Theorem applies. In our model, the uniqueness of Markov perfect equilibrium payoff 2

3 implies the uniqueness of Markov perfect equilibrium strategy profile. Given the contraction property, value function iteration converges to the unique equilibrium payoff. The numerical results we obtain are consistent with our finding that the appointed judge in earlier periods investigate more under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent, but as more precedents are established over time, eventually the appointed judge investigates less under binding precedent. Related Literature Landes and Posner [1976], Schwartz [1992], Rasmusen [1994], Talley [1999], Bueno De Mesquita and Stephenson [22], Gennaioli and Shleifer [27], Baker and Mezzetti [212], Ellison and Holden [214], Anderlini, Felli, and Riboni [214], Callander and Hummel [214], Callander and Clark [215]. 2 Model A court regulates a set of activities by allowing or banning them. In each period, a new case arises which must be decided by the judge appointed in that period. We refer to the judge appointed to make the decision in period t as judge t. Each judge prefers to allow activities that she regards as beneficial and ban activities which she regards as harmful. We denote a case by a real number x [, 1]. Judge t has a threshold value [, 1] such that she regards case x as beneficial and would like it to be permitted if and only if x <. Since we assume that does not vary with t, the judges have the same preferences regarding the cases. Following Baker and Mezzetti [212], we assume that the cases are observed by the judges, but the preference parameter is unknown initially. Specifically, we assume is distributed according to cumulative distribution function F with density function f. The support of is [, ] and < < < 1 holds. In period t {1,... }, a case x t randomly arises according to distribution G on [, 1]. We assume that the cases are independent across periods. The precedent at time t is captured by two numbers L t and R t with < L t < R t < 1 where L t is the highest case that was ever allowed and R t is the lowest case that was ever banned 3

4 by time t. We assume L 1 < < < R 1, that is, the precedent at the beginning of period 1 is consistent with the judges preferences. The timing of the events is as follows. In period t, after case x t is brought to the court, judge t chooses whether to investigate the case or not before deciding whether to permit the activity or ban it. 12 An investigation allows judge t to learn what is at a fixed cost z. If the case is decided without an investigation, we say the judge made a summary decision. Let s = ((L, R), x). In what follows, for expositional convenience, we refer to s as the state even though it does not include the information about. Let S p denote the set of possible precedents, i.e. S p = {(L, R), [, 1] 2 : R > L}, and let S denote the set of possible states, i.e. S = S p [, 1]. Denote the ruling at time t by r t {, 1}, where r t = if the case is banned and r t = 1 if the case is permitted. After the judge makes her ruling, the precedent changes to L t+1 and R t+1. If x t was permitted, then L t+1 = max{l t, x t } and R t+1 = R t ; if x t was banned, then L t+1 = L t and R t+1 = min{r t, x t }. Formally, the transition of the precedent is captured by the function π : S {, 1} S p where π(s, ) is the vector (L, min{r, x}) and π(s, 1) is the vector (max{l, x}, R). Judge t observes the investigation decisions by the previous judges as well as the outcome of the investigation and the ruling. We consider two institutions: a binding precedent and a persuasive precedent. Under binding precedent, judge t must permit x t if x t L t and ban it if x t R t. Under persuasive precedent, judge t is free to make any decision. In this case, the role of the precedent is potentially to provide information regarding whether the case is beneficial or not for judge t. We assume the violation of a binding precedent is infinitely costly. The payoff of any judge from the ruling r t on case x t in period t is 1 We assume judges investigate the case when indifferent for expositional simplicity. 2 We assume that a judge learns about his preference parameter through investigation. Alternatively, we can assume that a judge knows about his preferences in terms of the consequences of cases, but does not know how the consequence of a particular case unless he investigates. To illustrate, let c(x) denote the consequence of a case x and assume that c(x) = x + γ. A judge would like to permit case x if c(x) is below some threshold c and would like to ban it otherwise. Suppose that judge knows c and observe x, but γ is unknown until a judge investigates. This alternative model is equivalent to ours. 4

5 given by u(x t,, r t ) = { if x t < and r t = P, or x t and r t = B, l x t otherwise, where l x t is the variable cost of making a mistake, that is, permitting a case when it is above or banning a case when it is below. The total payoff of the appointed judge is the sum of her discounted payoffs from the rulings made in each period net of the investigation cost if she carried out an investigation. The discount factor is denoted by δ. We consider stationary Markov perfect equilibria. A Markov strategy depends only on payoff-relevant events, and a stationary Markov strategy does not depend on calendar time. A stationary Markov perfect equilibrium is a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium in stationary Markov strategies. We henceforth refer to a stationary Markov perfect equilibrium simply as an equilibrium. Persuasive precedent In the model with persuasive precedent, the payoff-relevant state in any period is the realized case x [, 1] and the information about. If is known at the time when the relevant decisions are made, then it is optimal not to investigate the case for any s, it is optimal to permit x if x <, and it is optimal to ban x if x >. If is unknown at the time when the relevant decisions are made, a (pure) strategy for the judge is a pair of functions σ = (µ, ρ), where µ : [, 1] {, 1} is an investigation strategy and ρ : [, 1] {, 1} is an uninformed ruling strategy, where µ(x) = 1 if and only if an investigation is made when the case is x; and ρ(x) = 1 if and only if case x is permitted. To each strategy σ = (µ, ρ) we can associate two functions V ( ; σ) and W ( ; σ). The value V (x; σ) represents the dynamic payoff of a judge when she is appointed in the current period and the value W (x; σ) represents the dynamic payoff of a judge when she was appointed in a previous period when the current case is x and is unknown, and the strategy profile σ will be played from the current period 5

6 onwards. In what follows, we suppress the dependence of the dynamic payoffs on σ for notational convenience. A triple (σ, V, W ) is a Markov Perfect Equilibrium if and only if (E1-P) Given (V, W ), the uninformed ruling strategy satisfies ρ (x) = 1 if and ρ (x) = if for any case x. l l max{x,} max{x,} ( x)df () > l ( x)df () < l min{x, } min{x, } (x )df () (x )df () (E2-P) Given (V, W ) and the uninformed ruling strategy ρ, for any state s, the investigation strategy satisfies µ (x) = 1 if and only if z ρ (x)l max{x,} ( x)df () + (1 ρ (x))l (x )df () + δ min{x, } (E3-P) Given σ, for any state s, the dynamic payoffs satisfy W (x) = (1 µ (x)) [ ρ (x)l max{x,} ( x)df () + (1 ρ (x))l (x )df () + δ min{x, } V (x) = µ (x)z + W (x). 1 W (x )dg(x ) Condition (E1-P) says that the the ruling decision depends on only the current period payoff, and in particular, the judge chooses the ruling that minimizes the expected cost of making a mistake in the current period. ] 1 This is because under persuasive precedent, the ruling does not affect the judge s continuation payoff. If a judge investigates case x, then becomes known and no mistake in ruling W (x )dg(x ). 6

7 will be made in the current period as well as in the future. In this case, the dynamic payoff of the appointed judge, V (x), is negative of the cost of investigation, and the dynamic payoff of a previously appointed judge, W (x), is. If a judge does not investigate case x, then her dynamic payoff is the sum of the expected cost of making a mistake in the current period and the continuation payoff. In this case, since the appointed judge does not incur any investigation cost, her dynamic payoff is the same as the dynamic payoff of a previously appointed judge. Condition (E3- P) formalizes this and condition (E2-P) says that the appointed judge chooses to investigate a case if and only if her dynamic payoff from investigating is higher than her expected dynamic payoff from not investigating. Binding precedent In the model with binding precedent, the payoff-relevant state in any period is the precedent pair (L, R) [, 1] 2, the realized case x [, 1] and the information about. If is known at the time when the relevant decisions are made, then it is optimal not to investigate the case for any s, it is optimal to permit x if x < max{l, }, and it is optimal to ban x if x > min{r, }. Let C(L, R) denote the expected dynamic payoff of the judge when the precedent is (L, R), conditional on being known when decisions regarding the cases are made where the expectation is taken over before it is revealed and over all future cases x. Formally C(L, R) = l [ 1 δ L L ( x)dg(x)df () + R R ] (x )dg(x)df (), (1) where L is the (possibly degenerate) interval [, max{l, }] and R is the (possibly degenerate) interval [min{r, }, ]. To see how we derive C(L, R), note that if < L and x (, L], then the judge incurs a cost of l( x) since she has to permit x; similarly, if > R and x [R, ), then the judge incurs a cost of l(x ) since she has to ban x. It follows [ that the expected per-period payoff of a judge conditional on being known is l ( x)dg(x)df () + ] L (x )dg(x)df (), L R R and her dynamic payoff in the infinite horizon model is 1/(1 δ) times the per-period payoff. Note that max{l, } is increasing in L and min{r, } is decreasing in R, and 7

8 therefore C(L, R) is decreasing in L and increasing in R. If is unknown at the time when the decisions regarding the cases are made, a (pure) strategy for the judge is a pair of functions σ = (µ, ρ), where µ : S {, 1} is an investigation strategy and ρ : S {, 1} is an uninformed ruling strategy, where µ(s) = 1 if and only if an investigation is made when the state is s, and ρ(s) = 1 if and only if case x is permitted when the state is s. To each strategy σ = (µ, ρ) we can associate two functions V ( ; σ) and W ( ; σ). The value V (s; σ) represents the dynamic payoff of a judge when she is appointed in the current period and the value W (s; σ) represents the dynamic payoff of a judge when she is not appointed in the current period, when the state is ((L, R), x), is unknown, and the strategy profile σ will be played from the current period onwards. In what follows, we suppress the dependence of the dynamic payoffs on σ for notational convenience. A triple (σ, V, W ) is a Markov Perfect Equilibrium if and only if (E1-B) Given (V, W ), the uninformed ruling strategy satisfies ρ (s) = 1 if either x L or x (L, R) and l > l max{x,} ( x)df () + δ (x )df () + δ 1 1 min{x, } and ρ (s) = if either x R or x (L, R) and l < l for any state s. max{x,} ( x)df () + δ (x )df () + δ 1 1 min{x, } W (π(s, 1), x )dg(x ) W (π(s, ), x )dg(x ), W (π(s, 1), x )dg(x ) W (π(s, ), x )dg(x ), (E2-B) Given (V, W ) and the uninformed ruling strategy ρ, for any state s, the 8

9 investigation strategy µ satisfies µ(s) = 1 if and only if ρ (s)l max{x,} z + 1 L (x)l x ( x)df () + (1 ρ (s))l ( x)df () + 1 R (x)l min{x, } where 1 A (x) takes the value 1 if x A and otherwise. (x )df () + δ (E3-B) Given σ, for any state s, the dynamic payoffs satisfy W (s) = µ (s) [ 1 L (x)l + (1 µ (s)) [ x ρ (s)l ( x)df () + 1 R (x)l max{x,} ( x)df () + (1 ρ (s))l (x )df () + δ min{x, } V (s) = µ (s)z + W (s). 1 x (x )df () + δc(l, R) x 1 (x )df () + δc(l, R) W (π(s, ρ (s)), x )dg(x ) Under binding precedent, the ruling decision may change the precedent, which in turn may affect the continuation payoff. As such, condition (E1-B) says the ruling decision depends on both the current period payoff and the continuation payoff. In particular, the judge chooses the ruling that maximizes the sum of the current period payoff and the continuation payoff, taking into consideration how her ruling affects the precedent in the next period. If a judge investigates case x, then becomes known. When the precedents are binding, however, mistakes in ruling can still happen if < L or if > R. this case, the dynamic payoff of the appointed judge, V (s), is the expected cost of making mistakes in the ruling, both in the current period and in future periods, minus the cost of investigation. The difference between V (s) and the dynamic payoff of a previously appointed judge, W (s), is still the cost of investigation. If a judge does not investigate case x, then her dynamic payoff is the sum of the expected W (π(s, ρ (s)), x )dg(x ) ] ] In 9

10 cost of making a mistake in the current period and the continuation payoff. In this case, since the appointed judge does not incur any investigation cost, V (s) is the same as W (s). Condition (E3-B) formalizes this and condition (E2-B) says that the appointed judge chooses to investigate a case if and only if her dynamic payoff from investigating is higher than her expected dynamic payoff from not investigating. 3 A three-period model Before we analyze the infinite horizon model, we discuss a three-period model to illustrate some of the intuition. For simplicity, we assume that F is uniform distribution on [, ] and G is uniform distribution on [, 1]. 3.1 Persuasive Precedent Consider the judge in period t. If a previous judge has investigated, then is known and judge t permits or bans case x t according to. Suppose no previous judge has investigated, then judge t s belief about is the same as the prior. If judge t investigates, his payoff is z in period t and in future periods. The following result says that if judge t does not investigate, then he permits x t if x t < E() and bans x t if x t > E(). For notational convenience, let e = E() and α =. Lemma 1. Under persuasive precedent, for any x t e, if no previous judge has investigated, then E [u(x t,, B) u(x t,, P )](x t e ) >. Lemma 1 implies that if no previous judge has investigated and judge t does not investigate case x t, then he permits it if x t < e and bans it if x t > e. Now we analyze the judges investigation decisions. The following lemma says that when the investigation cost is sufficiently low, the judge appointed in each period investigates with positive probability and the cases that judge t investigates forms an interval. 1

11 Lemma 2. Suppose z < αl. In the three-period model under persuasive precedent, 8 judge t {1, 2, 3} investigates x t with positive probability in equilibrium. Specifically, there exist x L t and x H t > x L t such that judge t investigates x t if and only if x t [x L t, x H t ]. 3.2 Binding precedent We first show that in equilibrium, in each period t, the cases that judge t investigates also form a (possibly degenerate) interval under binding precedent. Lemma 3. In the three-period model under binding precedent, the set of cases that judge t investigates in equilibrium is either empty or convex for any precedent (L t, R t ). In the next proposition, we show that judge 1 investigates more under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent, but judges 2 and 3 investigate less under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent. Proposition 1. Judge 3 investigates less under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent. Specifically, for any precedent (L 3, R 3 ), judge 3 investigates case x 3 if and only if x 3 (L 3, R 3 ) [x L 3, x H 3 ]. Judge 2 also investigates less under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent. Specifically, if the precedent in period 2 satisfies [, ] [L 2, R 2 ], then the set of cases that judge 2 investigates under binding precedent is the same as [x L 2, x H 2 ]; otherwise the set of cases he investigates under binding precedent is a subset of [x L 2, x H 2 ]. Judge 1 investigates more under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent, that is, given any precedent (L 1, R 1 ) (, ), the set of cases that judge 1 investigates under binding precedent contains the set [x L 1, x H 1 ]. The reason for judge 3 to investigate less under binding precedent is that investigation has no value if x 3 L 3 or if x 3 R 3 since the judge must permit any x 3 L 3 and must ban any x 3 R 3 no matter what the investigation outcome; moreover, since period 3 is the last period, the information about has no value for the future either. For x 3 (L 3, R 3 ), judge 3 faces the same incentives under binding and persuasive precedent and therefore investigate the same set of cases. 11

12 For judge 2, if the precedent in period 2 satisfies [, ] [L 2, R 2 ], then investigation avoids mistakes in ruling in the current period as well as the future period even under binding precedent. In this case, judge 2 faces the same incentives under binding and persuasive precedent and therefore investigate the same set of cases. However, if the precedent in period 2 does not satisfy [, ] [L 2, R 2 ], then even if x 2 (L 2, R 2 ) and judge 2 investigates, mistakes in ruling can still happen in period 3 under binding precedent if / [L 2, R 2 ] since judge 3 has to follow the precedent. In this case, the value of investigation is lower under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent and therefore judge 2 investigates less under binding precedent. For judge 1, since the precedent in period 1 satisfies [, ] [L 1, R 1 ], investigation avoids mistakes in ruling in the current period as well as in future periods even under binding precedent. However, for x 1 (, ), if the judge does not investigate x 1 and makes a summary ruling, then she changes the precedent in a way that [, ] [L 2, R 2 ]. As discussed in the previous paragraph, this diminishes judge 2 s incentive to investigate, which in turn lowers judge 1 s dynamic payoff. Hence, judge 1 s payoff from not investigating is lower under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent, and therefore she has a stronger incentive to investigate under binding precedent. 4 Infinite-horizon model We now consider the infinite-horizon model, that is, T =. 4.1 Persuasive precedent If a previous judge already investigated, then judge t knows the value of and would permit or ban a case according to. We next show that if no previous judge has investigated, then the cases that judge t investigates form a convex set. Proposition 2. Under persuasive precedent, if judge t investigates x 1 and x 2 > x 1 in equilibrium, then she investigates any x [x 1, x 2 ] in equilibrium. 12

13 Fix an equilibrium. Suppose the set of cases the judge investigates is nonempty. Let a = inf{x : µ (x) = 1} and b = sup{x : µ (x) = 1}. We next show that if a judge faces a case such that there is no uncertainty about what the correct ruling is for that case (that is, if x or if x ), then the judge does not investigate the case in equilibrium, even though the information from investigation is valuable for future rulings. Proposition 3. In equilibrium, we have < a b <. Let W e = 1 W (x )dg(x ). To find the equilibria, note that δw e if x, or if x, l x W (x) = ( x)df () + δw e if < x < a, if x [a, b], l e (x )df () + δw if b < x <. x (2) Hence, we have W e = δw e [G(a) + 1 G(b)]+l a x ( x)df ()dg(x)+l b x (x )df ()dg(x). Since the appointed judge is indifferent between investigating and not investigating when x = a, we have z = l a (3) ( a)df () + δw e. (4) Similarly, since the appointed judge is indifferent between investigating and not investigating when x = b, we have z = l b (b )df () + δw e. (5) We can solve for W e, a, b from equations (3), (4), and (5). Plugging these in (2), 13

14 we can solve for W (x). We can also solve for V (x) since V (x) = z for x [a, b] and V (x) = W (x) for x / [a, b]. 4.2 Binding precedent We now consider binding precedent. Let F denote the set of bounded measurable functions on S taking values in R. For f F, let f = sup{ f(s) : s S}. An operator Q : F F satisfies the contraction property for if there is a β (, 1) such that for f 1, f 2 F, we have Q(f 1 ) Q(f 2 ) β f 1 f 2. For any operator Q that satisfies the contraction property, there is a unique f V such that Q(f) = f. Recall L is the (possibly degenerate) interval [, max{l, }] and R is the (possibly degenerate) interval [min{r, }, ]. Let A(s) denote the appointed judge s dynamic payoff if he investigates in state s = ((L, R), x), not including the investigation cost. Formally, A(s) = 1 L (x)l x ( x)df () + 1 R (x)l x (x )df () + δc(l, R). Also, let g p (s) be the appointed judge s current period payoff if he permits the case without investigation in state s and g b (s) be his current period payoff if he bans the case without investigation in state s. Formally, l max{x,} ( x)df () if x < R, g p (s) = if x R, l (x )df () if x > L, g b min{x, } (s) = if x L. Note that for any s S, µ (s) as defined in (E2-B) satisfies µ (s) arg max µ[ z + A(s)] µ {,1} + (1 µ) max{g p (s) + δ 1 W (max{x, L}, R)dG(x ), g b (s) + δ 14 1 W (L, min{x, R})dG(x )}.

15 For W F and any s S, define T W (s) = µ(s)z + max{ z + A(s), g p (s) + δ 1 W (max{x, L}, R)dG(x ), g b (s) + δ Note that W as defined in (E3-B) satisfies W = T W. We next show that T is a contraction. Proposition 4. T : F F is a contraction. In contrast to a dynamic single-agent decision problem with discounting, value functions in a dynamic game often fail the contraction mapping property because a player s payoff depends not only on her own action but other players actions as well. In the game we analyze, however, the judges have the same preference over the rulings and the only divergence of interest comes from the private cost a judge incurs if she carries out an investigation. We are able to exploit this to establish the contraction mapping property. Since T is a contraction, there is a unique W that satisfies T W = W and therefore a unique W that satisfies (E3-B). Once we solve for W, we can solve for the equilibrium strategies ρ and µ from (E1-B) and (E2-B). We can then solve for V from (E3-B). We next establish that the equilibrium value functions W and V are decreasing in L and increasing in R and the equilibrium investigation strategy µ is also decreasing in L and increasing in R. This result says that as the precedent gets tighter, the appointed judge investigates less and her payoff also becomes lower. 1 W (L, min{x, R})dG(x )}. Proposition 5. Suppose the precedent (ˆL, ˆR) is tighter than (L, R), that is, L ˆL < ˆR R. Under binding precedent, when z is sufficiently low, for any case x [, 1], if an appointed judge investigates x under precedent (ˆL, ˆR), then she also investigates x under precedent (L, R), that is, µ (L, R, x) is decreasing in L and increasing in R; moreover, the value functions W (L, R, x) and V (L, R, x) are also decreasing in L and increasing in R. 15

16 We next show that the set of cases that an appointed judge investigates is either empty or convex, and the appointed judge does not investigate any case for which she must follow the precedent in ruling. Proposition 6. Under binding precedent, for any precedent (L, R) S p, (i) if the appointed judge investigates case x 1 and x 2 > x 1 in equilibrium, then she also investigates any x [x 1, x 2 ], and (ii) the appointed judge does not investigate any case x / (L, R). For any (L, R) S p such that {x : µ (L, R, x) = 1}, let a(l, R) = inf{x : µ (L, R, x) = 1} and b(l, R) = sup{x : µ (L, R, x) = 1}. Proposition 6 implies that when facing the precedent (L, R), the appointed judge investigates x (a(l, R), b(l, R)) where a(l, R) L and b(l, R) R. We refer to (a(l, R), b(l, R)) as the investigation interval under (L, R). We conjecture that if L < a(l, R) < b(l, R) < R, then under precedent (L, R), the judge is indifferent between investigating or not when x = a(l, R) and when x = b(l, R), which implies that the set of cases that the appointed judge investigates is the closed interval [a(l, R), b(l, R)]. Suppose that given the initial precedent (L 1, R 1 ), the set of cases that judge 1 investigates is nonempty (if it is empty, then no judge will investigate any case). Specifically, judge 1 investigates x 1 if and only if x 1 [a(l 1, R 1 ), b(l 1, R 1 )]. For notational simplicity, let a 1 = a(l 1, R 1 ) and b 1 = b(l 1, R 1 ). If x 1 [a 1, b 1 ], judge 1 investigates x 1. In this case, since becomes known, no future judge will investigate. If x 1 / [a 1, b 1 ], then judge 1 makes a summary ruling without any investigation and changes the precedent to (x 1, R 1 ) if he permits the case and to (L 1, x 1 ) if he bans the case. Note that when judge 1 makes a summary ruling, the resulting new precedent satisfies L 2 < a 1 and b 1 < R 2. Monotonicity of µ in Proposition 5 implies that the investigation interval in period 2 satisfies a(l 2, R 2 ) a 1 and b(l 2, R 2 ) b 1 and therefore we have L 2 < a(l 2, R 2 ) b(l 2, R 2 ) < R 2. An iteration of this argument shows that on any realized equilibrium path, the investigation interval is a strict subset of the precedent in any period and is either closed or empty. Denote a nonempty investigation interval on an equilibrium path by [a(l e, R e ), b(l e, R e )]. By Propositions 5 and 6, we have 16

17 L e < a(l e, R e ) b(l e, R e ) < R e and given the precedent (L e, R e ), the judge is indifferent between investigating x or not if x = a(l e, R e ) or if x = b(l e, R e ). On the equilibrium path, the investigation intervals either converge to or to some nonempty set [â, ˆb] such that if the precedent is (L, R) = (â, ˆb), then a(l, R) = â and b(l, R) = ˆb. We conjecture that in period 1 when the precedent is (L 1, R 1 ), the appointed judge investigates more under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent. But as more precedents are established over time, the appointed judge has less freedom in making her ruling when precedents are binding, and eventually she investigates less than if the precedent is persuasive. Recall that [a, b] denotes the set of cases that an appointed judge investigates under persuasive precedent. Conjecture 1. We have (â, ˆb) [a, b] [a(l 1, R 1 ), b(l 1, R 1 )]. Conjecture 1 is analogous to Proposition 1 in the 3-period model, which says that judge 1 investigates more under binding precedent than under persuasive precedent, but judges 2 and 3 investigate less under binding precedent. We next provide a numerical example to illustrate the results. Since T is a contraction as shown in Proposition 4, value function iteration converges to the unique equilibrium value function W. Example 1. Suppose that is uniformly distributed on [.2,.8], x is uniformly distributed on [, 1], δ =.95, z =.5, l = 1. Under persuasive precedent, if no previous judge had investigated, then the appointed judge investigates x if and only if x [.429,.571], and he does not investigate x and permits it if x [,.429) and bans it if x (.571, 1]. We now turn to binding precedent. Figure 1 illustrates the investigation decision of the appointed judge for different values of L when R = 1 when no previous judge has investigated. As the figure shows, the cases that the appointed judge investigates is an interval for L sufficiently low and the investigation interval shrinks as L increases and eventually becomes empty, consistent with Propositions 5 and 6. Figure 2 also illustrates the investigation of the appointed judge for different values of L, but now R is fixed at.6. Similar to Figure 1, Figure 2 shows that 17

18 the investigation interval shrinks as L increases and eventually becomes empty. We can also compare the investigation intervals in the figures with the same value of L. Indeed, the investigation interval is larger when R = 1 than when R =.6 when L is fixed. (Note that since L < R, Figure 2 has fewer graphs displayed than Figure 1.) Under binding precedent, given the initial precedent (L 1, R 1 ) = (, 1), judge 1 investigates x 1 [a(l 1, R 1 ), b(l 1, R 1 )] where a(l 1, R 1 ) =.37 and b(l 1, R 1 ) =.63. We also calculate that â =.45 and ˆb =.55. Since under persuasive precedent, the appointed judge investigates x [a, b] where a =.429 and b =.571, we have (â, ˆb) [a, b] [a(l 1, R 1 ), b(l 1, R 1 )], consistent with Conjecture 1. Figure 3 illustrates the ruling decisions for different values of L when R = 1. As the figure shows, the ruling decision follows a cut-off rule: without investigation, there is a threshold such that the appointed judge permits any case below it and bans any case above it. 1. R= µ x L=. L=.2 L=.4 L=.6 L=.8 Figure 1: Investigation decision for different values of L when R = 1 18

19 1. R= µ x L=. L=.2 L=.4 Figure 2: Investigation decision for different values of L when R =.6 1. R= ρ x L=. L=.2 L=.4 L=.6 L=.8 Figure 3: Ruling decision for different values of L when R = 1 19

20 5 Appendix Proof of Lemma 1: First note that [ max{,xt} ] E [u(x t,, B) u(x t,, P )] = l ( x t )df () (x t )df (), min{x t, } (6) where l min{x t, } t)df () is judge t s expected payoff when he bans x t but x t <, and l max{,x t} (x t )df () is judge 3 s expected payoff when judge t permits x t but x t >. If x t, then clearly E [u(x t,, B) u(x t,, P )] > ; and if x t, then clearly E [u(x t,, B) u(x t,, P )] <. We consider x t (, ). Note that = = x t ( x t )df () xt (x t )df () x t df () x t [ F ( ) F (xt ) ] x t [F (x t ) F ()] + = e x t. df () x t xt df () It follows that E [u(x t,, B) u(x t,, P )](x t e ) = l(x t e ) 2 > for x t e. Proof of Lemma 2: Consider judge 3 first. If x 3 <, then judge 3 knows that > x 3, and therefore he permits the case without investigation. If x 3 >, then judge 3 knows that > x 3, and therefore he bans the case without investigation. For x 3 [, e ), if judge 3 does not investigate, he permits the case and his expected payoff is x 3 l(x 3 ) d α 3 = l (x 2α 3 ) 2. For x 3 ( e, ), if judge 3 does not investigate, he bans the case and his expected payoff is d 2 = l x 3 l( x 3 ) x 3 α = e, judge 3 s expected payoff if he does not investigate is αl 8 z < αl 8, then judge 3 investigates some cases. Specifically, let xl 3 = + ( x 2α 3 ) 2. When. Hence, if 2αz l and 2

21 x H 3 2αz =. If x l 3 [x L 3, x H 3 ], then judge 3 investigates case x 3. Now consider judge 2. Suppose judge 1 has not investigated. If judge 2 chooses to investigate in period 2, then his payoff in period 2 is z and his period-3 expected payoff is. If judge 2 chooses not to investigate in period 2, then by Lemma 1, he permits any case x 2 < e and bans any case x 2 > e. Note that if x 2 or if x 2, then judge 2 s payoff is if he does not investigate since he makes the correct decision. Consider < x 2 < e and suppose judge 2 does not investigate the case. Since judge 2 permits such a case, his expected payoff in period 2 is 1 α x2 l(x 2 )d = l(x 2 ) 2. 2α Similarly, for e < x 2 <, if judge 1 does not investigate the case, he bans it and in this case, his expected payoff in period 2 is 1 α l( x 2 )d = l( x 2) 2 x 2 2α Recall that judge 3 investigates x 3 if and only if x 3 [x L 3, x H 3 ] where x L 2αz 3 = + l and x H 2αz 3 =. l For x 3, judge 3 permits x 3 and judge 2 s payoff in period 3 is ; for x 3, judge 3 bans x 3 and judge 2 s payoff in period 3 is. Hence, the expected payoff of judge 2 in period 3 is x L 3 l 2α (x 2 ) 2 dx 2 + l x H 2α ( x 2) 2 dx 2 3 = l [ 1 2α 3 (xl 3 ) ] 3 ( xh 3 ) 3 2αz. = 2z 3 l 21

22 Now consider judge 2 s optimal strategy in period 2. For x 2 / [, ], if 2z 3 2αz l > z, then it is optimal for judge 2 not to investigate x 2 in period 2. Since z < αl, this is 8 satisfied. Hence judge 2 does not investigate x 2 if x 2 / [, ]. For < x 2 < e, if z < l 2α (x 1 ) 2 + 2z 2αz 3 l, then it is optimal for judge 2 not to investigate x 2 in period 2. Let x 2 = e. Then 2αz l RHS = αl + 2z 8 3 (, e ) that satisfies < z since z < αl 8. Hence, by continuity, there exists xl 2 z = l 2α (xl 2 ) 2 + 2z 2αz 3 l such that if x 2 (x L 2, e ], judge 2 investigates x 2 in period 1. Similarly, there exists x H 2 which satisfies z = l 2α ( xh 2 ) 2 + 2z 2αz 3 l such that if x 2 [ e, x H 2 ], judge 2 investigates x 2 in period 2. So the set of x 2 such that judge 2 investigates x 2 in period 2 is convex. It is [x L 2, x H 2 ]. Note that [x L 3, x H 3 ] [x L 2, x H 2 ]. Now consider judge 1. If judge 1 chooses to investigate in period 1, then his dynamic payoff is z. If he does not investigate in period 1, then he permits x 1 if x 1 < e and bans x 1 if x 1 > e and his expected continuation payoff is [ x L 2 l 2α (x 2 ) 2 2z ] 2αz dx l = l [ 1 2α 3 (xl 2 ) ] 3 ( x H 2 ) 3 2z 3 x H 2 [ l 2α ( x 2 ) 2 2z 3 2αz l ( x H 2 + x L 2 ). ] 2αz dx 2 l 22

23 For x 1 [, e ), judge 1 permits x 1 if he does not investigate it. Hence, his dynamic payoff is l 2α (x 1 ) 2 l [ 1 2α 3 (xl 2 ) ] 3 ( x H 2 ) 3 2z 2αz 3 l ( x H 2 + x L 2 ) and x L 1 satisfies z = l 2α (xl 1 ) 2 + l [ 1 2α 3 (xl 2 ) ] 3 ( x H 2 ) 3 + 2z 2αz 3 l ( x H 2 + x L 2 ). Similarly, for x 1 ( e, ], judge 1 bans x 1 if he does not investigate it and his dynamic payoff is l 2α ( x 1 ) 2 l [ 1 2α 3 (xl 2 ) ] 3 ( x H 2 ) 3 2z 2αz 3 l ( x H 2 + x L 2 ) and x H 1 satisfies z = l 2α ( x 1 ) 2 + l [ 1 2α 3 (xl 2 ) ] 3 ( x H 2 ) 3 + 2z 2αz 3 l ( x H 2 + x L 2 ). Substituting for x L 2 and x H 2, we can solve for when judge 1 investigates x 1. Proof of Lemma 3: Consider judge 3 first. Suppose no previous judge has investigated. Recall that under persuasive precedent, judge 3 investigates x 3 if and only if x 3 [x L 3, x H 3 ]. Since under binding precedent, investigation has no value if x 3 L 3 or if x 3 R 3, judge 3 investigates x 3 if x 3 [x L 3, x H 3 ] (L 3, R 3 ). Hence, the set of cases that judge 3 investigates is either empty or convex. Let k(l, R) denote a judge s expected payoff in period t under binding precedent when the precedents are (L, R) in period t conditional on being known where the expectation is taken over before it is revealed and over all possible cases x. Formally [ k(l, R) = l L L ( x)dg(x)df () + R R ] (x )dg(x)df () 23

24 where L is the (possibly degenerate) interval [, max{l, }] and R is the (possibly degenerate) interval [min{r, }, ]. Note that k(l, R) and k(l, R) < if L > or if R <. Note also that k(l, R) is decreasing in L and increasing in R. Let EV t (L, R) denote the expected equilibrium continuation payoff in period t given that the precedent in period t is (L, R). Claim 1. If EV t (L, R) is decreasing in L and increasing in R, then the set of cases that judge t 1 investigates in period t 1 is either empty or convex for any precedent in period t 1. Proof: Suppose that EV t (L, R) is decreasing in L and increasing in R. Fix the precedent in period t 1 and denote it by (L t 1, R t 1 ). Suppose that the judge investigates cases x and x > x in period t 1. We next show that the judge also investigates case ˆx [x, x ]. Let g p (L, R, x) be the appointed judge s current period payoff if he permits the case without investigation in state s = (L, R, x) and g b (s) be his current period payoff if he bans the case without investigation in state s. Note that for any (L, R), g p (L, R, x) is decreasing in x and g b (L, R, x) is increasing in x. Suppose ˆx (L t 1, R t 1 ). If the judge investigates ˆx, then his payoff is z + δk(l t 1, R t 1 ). Suppose the judge does not investigate ˆx and without loss of generality, suppose it is optimal for him to permit ˆx if he does not investigate it. Since the judge investigates x under precedent (L t 1, R t 1 ), we have z + δk(l t 1, R t 1 ) g p (L t 1, R t 1, x ) + δev (max{x, L t 1 }, R t 1 ). Since g p is decreasing in x, we have g p (L t 1, R t 1, x ) > g p (L t 1, R t 1, ˆx). Moreover, since ˆx > max{x, L t 1 } and EV t is decreasing in L, we have we have EV t (max{x, L t 1 }, R t 1 ) > EV (ˆx, R t 1 ). Hence, we have z + δk(l t 1, R t 1 ) g p (L t 1, R t 1, ˆx) + δev t (ˆx, R t 1 ), which implies that the judge investigates case ˆx. Suppose ˆx L t 1. Then judge t 1 has to permit ˆx regardless of whether he investigates it or not. Hence, judge t 1 investigates ˆx if z + δk(l t 1, R t 1 ) δev t (L t 1, R t 1 ). Since the judge investigates x < ˆx, we have z + δk(l t 1, R t 1 ) δev t (L t 1, R t 1 ), implying that the judge investigates ˆx. A similar argument shows that judge t 1 investigates ˆx if ˆx R t 1 as well. Hence, the set of cases that judge 24

25 t 1 investigates in period t 1 is either empty or convex for any precedent in period t 1. Now consider judge 2. Suppose judge 1 did not investigate. Since judge 3 investigates x if x (L 3, R 3 ) [x 3 1, x H 3 ], we have EV 3 (L 3, R 3 ) = k(max{l 3, x L 3 }, min{r 3, x H 3 }). Since k(l, R) is decreasing in L and increasing in R, it follows that EV 3 is decreasing in L 3 and increasing in R 3. By Claim 1, the set of cases that judge 2 investigates is either empty or convex. Now consider judge 1. To establish that EV 2 (L 2, R 2 ) is decreasing in L 2 and increasing in R 2, we show that if judge 2 investigates x 2 given the precedent (L 2, R 2 ), then he also investigates x 2 given the precedent (ˆL 2, ˆR 2 ) if ˆL 2 L 2 and ˆR 2 R 2 Suppose that judge 2 investigates x 2 given the precedent (L 2, R 2 ). First consider the case x 2 (L 2, R 2 ). Then we have the following inequality. z + δk(l 2, R 2 ) max{ x2 ( x 2 )df () + δev 3 (x 2, R 2 ), (x 2 )df () + δev 3 (L 2, x 2 )}. x 2 Since EV 3 (x 2, ˆR 2 ) = k(max{x 2, x L 3 }, min{x H 3, ˆR 2 }) and EV 3 (x 2, R 2 ) = k(max{x 2, x L 3 }, min{x H 3, R 2 }), we have k(ˆl 2, ˆR 2 ) k(l 2, R 2 ) EV 3 (x 2, ˆR 2 ) EV 3 (x 2, R 2 ). k(ˆl 2, ˆR 2 ) k(l 2, R 2 ) EV 3 (ˆL 2, x 2 ) EV 3 (L 2, x 2 ). It follows that z + δk(ˆl 2, ˆR 2 ) max{ x2 Similarly, we have ( x 2 )df () + δev 3 (x 2, ˆR 2 ), (x 2 )df () + δev 3 (ˆL 2, x 2 )} x 2 and therefore judge 2 investigates x 2 under precedent (ˆL 2, ˆR 2 ). Next consider the case x 2 L 2. Since judge 2 investigates x 2 under precedent (L 2, R 2 ), we have z + δk(l 2, R 2 ) EV 3 (L 2, R 2 ). Since k(ˆl 2, ˆR 2 ) k(l 2, R 2 ) EV 3 (ˆL 2, ˆR 2 ) EV 3 (L 2, R 2 ) and x 2 ( x 2)dF () <, it follows that z+δk(ˆl 2, ˆR 2 ) δev 3 (ˆL 2, ˆR 2 ) > x 2 ( x 2)dF ()+δev 3 (ˆL 2, ˆR 2 ). Hence, judge 2 investigates x 2 L 2 under precedent (ˆL 2, ˆR 2 ). A similar argument shows that if x 2 R 2 and judge 2 investigates x 2 under precedent (L 2, R 2 ), then judge 2 also investigates x 2 under precedent (ˆL 2, ˆR 2 ). Since the investigation set is smaller with a tighter precedent in period 2 and in 25

26 period 3, it follows that EV 2 (L 2, R 2 ) is decreasing in L 2 and increasing in R 2. By Claim 1, the set of cases that judge 1 investigates is either empty or convex. Proof of Proposition 1: Consider judge 3 first. Suppose no previous judge has investigated. As shown in the proof of Lemma 3, under binding precedent, judge 3 investigates x 3 if x 3 [x L 3, x H 3 ] (L 3, R 3 ). Now consider judge 2. Recall that under persuasive precedent, judge 2 investigates x 2 if and only if x 2 [x L 2, x H 2 ] where [x L 2, x H 2 ] [x L 3, x H 3 ]. First suppose [, ] [L 2, R 2 ]. Then the incentive of judge 2 is the same under binding precedent as under persuasive precedent. In this case, under binding precedent, judge 2 investigates x 2 if and only if x 2 [x L 2, x H 2 ]. Next suppose [, ] [L 2, R 2 ]. We show below that under binding precedent, judge 2 does not investigate case x L 2. Recall that judge 2 is indifferent between investigating and not investigating x L 2 under persuasive precedent. Hence, we have z = x L 2 ( x L 2 )df () + δk(x L 3, x H 3 ). Consider binding precedent. Suppose x L 2 (L 2, R 2 ). Then the difference in judge 2 s dynamic payoff between investigating and not investigating x L 2 is [ ] x L z + δk(max{l 2, x L 3 }, min{r 2, x H 2 3 }) ( x L 2 )df () + δk(max{x 2, x L 3 }, min{r 2, x H 3 } z x L 2 ( x L 2 )df () = δk(x L 3, x H 3 ) <. Hence, judge 2 does not investigate x L 2 in this case. Suppose x L 2 / (L 2, R 2 ). Then judge 2 has to follow the precedent when ruling on x L 2 and the precedent in period 3 does not change, that is, (L 3, R 3 ) = (L 2, R 2 ). Hence, the difference in judge 2 s dynamic payoff between investigating and not investigating x L 2 is z + δk(max{l 2, x L 3 }, min{r 2, x H 3 }) δk(max{l 2, x L 3 }, min{r 2, x H 3 }) = z <. Hence, judge 2 does not investigate x L 2 in this case either. A similar argument establishes that under binding precedent, judge 2 does not 26

27 investigate x H 2 for any precedent. Given the convexity of the set of cases that judge 2 investigates under either binding or persuasive precedent, this implies that the set of cases that judge 2 investigates under binding precedent is contained in the set of cases he investigates under persuasive precedent. Now consider judge 1. We show below that judge 1 investigates x L 1 under binding precedent. Recall that judge 1 is indifferent between investigating and not investigating x L 1 under persuasive precedent. Hence, we have z = x L 1 ( x L 1 )df () + δk(x L 2, x H 2 ) + δ 2 [G(x L 2 ) + 1 G(x H 2 )]k(x L 3, x H 3 ). Let a 2 (L, R) = inf{x : judge 2 investigates x under binding precedent (L, R)}, b 2 (L, R) = sup{x : judge 2 investigates x under binding precedent (L, R)}. Define a 3 (L, R) and b 3 (L, R) analogously. Since L 1 < < < R 1, if judge 1 investigates x L 1, then his dynamic payoff is equal to z under binding precedent. If judge 1 does not investigate x L 1 and permits it, then the precedent in period 2 becomes (x L 1, R 1 ) and judge 2 investigates cases in ((a(x L 1, R 1 ), b(x L 1, R 1 )). Note also that judge 1 s expected payoff in period 3 is weakly lower than k(x L 3, x H 3 ). It follows that if judge 1 does not investigate x L 1, his dynamic payoff is lower than x L 1 ( x L 1 )df ()+δk((a(x L 1, R 1 ), b(x L 1, R 1 ))+δ 2 [G(a(x L 1, R 1 ))+1 G(b(x L 1, R 1 )]k(x L 3, x H 3 ). As shown previously, a(x L 1, R 1 ) > x L 2 and b(x L 1, R 1 ) < x L 2. Since k(l, R) is decreasing in L and increasing in R, it follows that k((a(x L 1, R 1 ), b(x L 1, R 1 )) < k(x L 2, x H 2 ). Also, since k(x L 3, x H 3 ) <, we have [G(a(x L 1, R 1 )) + 1 G(b(x L 1, R 1 )]k(x L 3, x H 3 ) < [G(x L 2 ) + 1 G(x H 2 )]k(x L 3, x H 3 ). Hence, z > x L 1 ( x L 1 )df ()+δk((a(x L 1, R 1 ), b(x L 1, R 1 ))+δ 2 [G(a(x L 1, R 1 ))+1 G(b(x L 1, R 1 )]k(x L 3, x H 3 ), implying that judge 1 investigates x L 1 under binding precedent. A similar argument establishes that under binding precedent, judge 1 investigates 27

28 x H 1. Given the convexity of the set of cases that judge 1 investigates under either binding or persuasive precedent, this implies that the set of cases that judge 1 investigates under binding precedent contains the set of cases he investigates under persuasive precedent. Proof of Proposition 2: Since judge t investigates x 1 (E2-P), we have z max { l for x {x 1, x 2 }. max{x,} ( x)df (), l min{x, } (x )df () and x 2, by (E1-P) and } + δ 1 W (x )dg(x ). Suppose ˆx [x 1, x 2 ]. Since l max{x,} ( x)df () is decreasing in x, we have l max{ˆx,} ( ˆx)dF () l max{x1,} Since l (x )df () is increasing in x, we have min{x, } It follows that { z max l ( x 1 )df (). l (ˆx )df () l (x 2 )df (). min{ˆx, } min{x 2, } max{ˆx,} ( ˆx)dF (), l min{ˆx, } and therefore the judge investigates ˆx in equilibrium. (ˆx )df () } + δ 1 W (x )dg(x ) Proof of Proposition 3: We prove the result by contradiction. Suppose that there exists an equilibrium in which a <. Let W e = 1 W (x )dg(x ). Since a <, the appointed judge s dynamic payoff is z if he investigates x = a, and δw e if he does not investigate x = a. Since µ(a) = 1, we have z δw e. Since for any x >, the judge s dynamic payoff is z if he investigates, and δw e if he does not investigate, 28

29 it must be the case that the judge investigates any case x >. It follows that b = 1. Moreover, since a <, any appointed judge makes the correct decision for x < a. It follows that W e = a δw e dg(x) = δg(a)w e, which implies that W e =. Since z δw e, this is impossible. Proof of Proposition 4: For any s S, let HW (s) = max{ z + A(s), g p (s) + δ 1 W (π(s, 1), x )dx, g b (s)+δ 1 W (π(s, ), x )dx } and KW (s) = µ(s)z. So T W (s) = HW (s) + KW (s). Note that µ(s) = 1 if and only if HW (s) = z + A(s). Suppose that W 1, W 2 F and consider any s S. Without loss of generality, suppose that HW 1 (s) HW 2 (s). For notational convenience, define µ 1 and µ 2 relative to W 1 and W 2. There are three cases to consider. (i) Suppose that HW 1 (s) = z + A(s). Since HW 1 (s) HW 2 (s), we have HW 2 (s) = z + A(s). We also have that µ 1 (s) = 1 and µ 2 (s) = 1. It follows that T W 1 (s) T W 2 (s) =. (ii) Suppose that HW 1 (s) = g p (s) + δ 1 W 1 (π(s, P ), x )dg(x ). Then µ 1 (s) =. We have T W 1 (s) T W 2 (s) g p (s) + δ δ δ W 1 (π(s, 1), x )dg(x ) g p (s) δ [ W 1 (π(s, 1), x ) W 2 (π(s, 1), x ) ] dg(x ) [ W 1 (π(s, 1), x ) W 2 (π(s, 1), x ) ] dg(x )] δ W 1 W 2 1 W 2 (π(s, 1), x )dg(x ) (iii) Suppose that HW 1 (s) = g b (s) + δ 1 W 1 (π(s, ), x )dg(x ). Then a similar argument as in case (ii) shows that T W 1 (s) T W 2 (s) δ W 1 W 2. Since either T W 1 (s) T W 2 (s) = or T W 1 (s) T W 2 (s) δ W 1 W 2 for any s S in all three cases, we have T W 1 T W 2 δ W 1 W 2 and therefore T is a contraction. 29

30 Proof of Proposition 5: Recall that for any s S, we define HW (s) = max{ z + A(s), g p (s) + δ 1 W (π(s, 1), x )dx, g b (s) + δ 1 W (π(s, ), x )dx }, KW (s) = µ(s)z, and T W (s) = HW (s)+kw (s), where µ(s) = 1 if HW (s) = z +A(s) and µ(s) = otherwise. Let EW (L, R) = 1 W (L, R, x)dg(x). To prove the proposition, we first establish the following lemma. Lemma 4. If W F satisfies the following properties: (i) W is decreasing in L and increasing in R, (ii) EW (L, R) EW (ˆL, ˆR) C(L, R) C(ˆL, ˆR), and (iii) KW is decreasing in L and increasing in R, then, for z sufficiently low, T W also satisfies these properties, that is, (i) T W is decreasing in L and increasing in R, (ii) ET W (L, R) ET W (ˆL, ˆR) C(L, R) C(ˆL, ˆR), and (iii) KT W is decreasing in L and increasing in R. We first show that if W F satisfies properties (i), (ii), and (iii), then T W is decreasing in L and increasing in R. Note that A(s) is decreasing in L and increasing in R, g p (s) is constant in L and increasing in R, g b (s) is constant in R and decreasing in L. Suppose W F is decreasing in L and increasing in R. Then 1 W (π(s, 1), x )dx = 1 W ((max{l, x}, R), x )dx and 1 W (π(s, ), x )dx = 1 W ((L, min{r, x}), x )dx are decreasing in L and increasing in R. Hence, HW is decreasing in L and increasing in R. Since KW is decreasing in L and increasing in R, it follows that T W = HW + KW is decreasing in L and increasing in R. Let ŝ = (ˆL, ˆR, x). We next show that if W F satisfies properties (i), (ii), and (iii), then ET W (L, R) ET W (ˆL, ˆR) C(L, R) C(ˆL, ˆR). Consider the following cases. (a) Suppose µ(ŝ) = 1 so that T W (ŝ) = A(ŝ). Then, since KW is increasing in L and decreasing in R, we have µ(s) = 1 and therefore T W (s) = A(s). Hence T W (s) T W (ŝ) = A(s) A(ŝ). (b) Suppose µ(ŝ) = and T W (ŝ) = g p (ŝ) + EW (max{x, ˆL}, ˆR) > A(ŝ) z. Then we must have x < ˆR and g p (s) + EW (max{x, ˆL}, ˆR) > z + A(ŝ). Note that A(s) g p (s) + δ 1 W (π(s, 1), x )dx and A(s) g b (s) + δ 1 W (π(s, ), x )dx since A(s) is the appointed judge s dynamic payoff if she investigates in state s, not including the investigation cost. It follows that T W (s) A(s) and therefore T W (s) T W (ŝ) < A(s) + z A(ŝ). (c) 3

Information Acquisition under Persuasive Precedent versus Binding Precedent (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Information Acquisition under Persuasive Precedent versus Binding Precedent (Preliminary and Incomplete) Information Acquisition under Persuasive Precedent versus Binding Precedent (Preliminary and Incomplete) Ying Chen Hülya Eraslan March 25, 2016 Abstract We analyze a dynamic model of judicial decision

More information

Learning While Setting Precedents

Learning While Setting Precedents Learning While Setting Precedents Ying Chen and Hülya Eraslan February 24, 2018 Abstract A decision maker (DM) must address a series of problems over time. Each period, a random case arises and the DM

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Research Department Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Harold L. Cole and Narayana Kocherlakota Working Paper 604 September 2000 Cole: U.C.L.A. and Federal Reserve

More information

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. 14.126 GAME THEORY MIHAI MANEA Department of Economics, MIT, 1. Existence and Continuity of Nash Equilibria Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. Theorem 1. Suppose

More information

STOCHASTIC REPUTATION DYNAMICS UNDER DUOPOLY COMPETITION

STOCHASTIC REPUTATION DYNAMICS UNDER DUOPOLY COMPETITION STOCHASTIC REPUTATION DYNAMICS UNDER DUOPOLY COMPETITION BINGCHAO HUANGFU Abstract This paper studies a dynamic duopoly model of reputation-building in which reputations are treated as capital stocks that

More information

Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence

Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence A The infinite horizon model This section defines the equilibrium of the infinity horizon model described in Section III of the paper and characterizes

More information

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015 Best-Reply Sets Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis This version: May 2015 Introduction The best-reply correspondence of a game the mapping from beliefs over one s opponents actions to

More information

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Chapter 5 Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Until now we implicitly adopted a view that a Nash equilibrium is a desirable outcome of a strategic game. In this chapter we consider two alternative

More information

Online Appendix for Debt Contracts with Partial Commitment by Natalia Kovrijnykh

Online Appendix for Debt Contracts with Partial Commitment by Natalia Kovrijnykh Online Appendix for Debt Contracts with Partial Commitment by Natalia Kovrijnykh Omitted Proofs LEMMA 5: Function ˆV is concave with slope between 1 and 0. PROOF: The fact that ˆV (w) is decreasing in

More information

Game Theory: Normal Form Games

Game Theory: Normal Form Games Game Theory: Normal Form Games Michael Levet June 23, 2016 1 Introduction Game Theory is a mathematical field that studies how rational agents make decisions in both competitive and cooperative situations.

More information

Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix

Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix Barney Hartman-Glaser September 1, 2016 Appendix D. Non-Markov Perfect Equilibrium In this appendix, I consider the game when there is no honest-type

More information

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Ahmer Tarar Department of Political Science Texas A&M University 4348 TAMU College Station, TX 77843-4348 email: ahmertarar@pols.tamu.edu

More information

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments Kentaro Tomoeda October 31, 215 Abstract This article analyzes the implementability of efficient investments for two commonly used mechanisms in single-item

More information

ISSN BWPEF Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions. Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University of London.

ISSN BWPEF Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions. Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University of London. ISSN 1745-8587 Birkbeck Working Papers in Economics & Finance School of Economics, Mathematics and Statistics BWPEF 0701 Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 9, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria

More information

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves University of Illinois Spring 01 ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves Due: Reading: Thursday, April 11 at beginning of class

More information

BAYESIAN GAMES: GAMES OF INCOMPLETE INFORMATION

BAYESIAN GAMES: GAMES OF INCOMPLETE INFORMATION BAYESIAN GAMES: GAMES OF INCOMPLETE INFORMATION MERYL SEAH Abstract. This paper is on Bayesian Games, which are games with incomplete information. We will start with a brief introduction into game theory,

More information

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games University of Illinois Fall 2018 ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games Due: Tuesday, Sept. 11, at beginning of class Reading: Course notes, Sections 1.1-1.4 1. [A random

More information

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Kang Rong School of Economics, Shanghai University of Finance and Economic (SHUFE) August, 202 Abstract I analyze an alternating-offer model that integrates

More information

Equilibrium Price Dispersion with Sequential Search

Equilibrium Price Dispersion with Sequential Search Equilibrium Price Dispersion with Sequential Search G M University of Pennsylvania and NBER N T Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond March 2014 Abstract The paper studies equilibrium pricing in a product market

More information

Inter-Session Network Coding with Strategic Users: A Game-Theoretic Analysis of Network Coding

Inter-Session Network Coding with Strategic Users: A Game-Theoretic Analysis of Network Coding Inter-Session Network Coding with Strategic Users: A Game-Theoretic Analysis of Network Coding Amir-Hamed Mohsenian-Rad, Jianwei Huang, Vincent W.S. Wong, Sidharth Jaggi, and Robert Schober arxiv:0904.91v1

More information

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Online Appendix for Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Giacomo Rodano Bank of Italy Nicolas Serrano-Velarde Bocconi University December 23, 2014 Emanuele Tarantino University of Mannheim 1 1 Reorganization,

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies Chapter 10 Elimination by Mixed Strategies The notions of dominance apply in particular to mixed extensions of finite strategic games. But we can also consider dominance of a pure strategy by a mixed strategy.

More information

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Shingo Ishiguro Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University 1-7 Machikaneyama, Toyonaka, Osaka 560-0043, Japan August 2002

More information

INTERIM CORRELATED RATIONALIZABILITY IN INFINITE GAMES

INTERIM CORRELATED RATIONALIZABILITY IN INFINITE GAMES INTERIM CORRELATED RATIONALIZABILITY IN INFINITE GAMES JONATHAN WEINSTEIN AND MUHAMET YILDIZ A. We show that, under the usual continuity and compactness assumptions, interim correlated rationalizability

More information

Revenue Management Under the Markov Chain Choice Model

Revenue Management Under the Markov Chain Choice Model Revenue Management Under the Markov Chain Choice Model Jacob B. Feldman School of Operations Research and Information Engineering, Cornell University, Ithaca, New York 14853, USA jbf232@cornell.edu Huseyin

More information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 ECON 459 Game Theory Lecture Notes Auctions Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 These notes have been used and commented on before. If you can still spot any errors or have any suggestions for improvement, please

More information

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions.

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B eb Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B.1 Proofs of results about block correlated markets. This subsection provides proofs for Propositions A1, A2, A3 and A4, and the proof of Lemma A1. Proof of Proposition

More information

Hedonic Equilibrium. December 1, 2011

Hedonic Equilibrium. December 1, 2011 Hedonic Equilibrium December 1, 2011 Goods have characteristics Z R K sellers characteristics X R m buyers characteristics Y R n each seller produces one unit with some quality, each buyer wants to buy

More information

Economics 703: Microeconomics II Modelling Strategic Behavior

Economics 703: Microeconomics II Modelling Strategic Behavior Economics 703: Microeconomics II Modelling Strategic Behavior Solutions George J. Mailath Department of Economics University of Pennsylvania June 9, 07 These solutions have been written over the years

More information

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms On Existence of Equilibria in Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms Northwestern University April 23, 2014 Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms In allocation mechanisms, agents choose messages. The messages determine

More information

Answers to Problem Set 4

Answers to Problem Set 4 Answers to Problem Set 4 Economics 703 Spring 016 1. a) The monopolist facing no threat of entry will pick the first cost function. To see this, calculate profits with each one. With the first cost function,

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Leonardo Felli 7 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Contract Theory has become only recently a subfield of Economics. As the name suggest the main object of the analysis is a contract. Therefore

More information

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2013 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 14, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria Mixed Strategies

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, MsC Economics List of Problems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

1 x i c i if x 1 +x 2 > 0 u i (x 1,x 2 ) = 0 if x 1 +x 2 = 0

1 x i c i if x 1 +x 2 > 0 u i (x 1,x 2 ) = 0 if x 1 +x 2 = 0 Game Theory - Midterm Examination, Date: ctober 14, 017 Total marks: 30 Duration: 10:00 AM to 1:00 PM Note: Answer all questions clearly using pen. Please avoid unnecessary discussions. In all questions,

More information

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9 EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 24 November 2017 Bargaining Games: Recall Two players, i {A, B} are trying to share a surplus. The size of the surplus is normalized

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015. FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.) Hints for Problem Set 2 1. Consider a zero-sum game, where

More information

An Axiomatic Approach to Arbitration and Its Application in Bargaining Games

An Axiomatic Approach to Arbitration and Its Application in Bargaining Games An Axiomatic Approach to Arbitration and Its Application in Bargaining Games Kang Rong School of Economics, Shanghai University of Finance and Economics Aug 30, 2012 Abstract We define an arbitration problem

More information

Cooperation and Rent Extraction in Repeated Interaction

Cooperation and Rent Extraction in Repeated Interaction Supplementary Online Appendix to Cooperation and Rent Extraction in Repeated Interaction Tobias Cagala, Ulrich Glogowsky, Veronika Grimm, Johannes Rincke July 29, 2016 Cagala: University of Erlangen-Nuremberg

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH http://www.kier.kyoto-u.ac.jp/index.html Discussion Paper No. 657 The Buy Price in Auctions with Discrete Type Distributions Yusuke Inami

More information

The Core of a Strategic Game *

The Core of a Strategic Game * The Core of a Strategic Game * Parkash Chander February, 2016 Revised: September, 2016 Abstract In this paper we introduce and study the γ-core of a general strategic game and its partition function form.

More information

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson all 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) 1. Critique of subgame perfection. 1 Consider the following three-player sequential game. In the first

More information

Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano

Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano Department of Economics Brown University Providence, RI 02912, U.S.A. Working Paper No. 2002-14 May 2002 www.econ.brown.edu/faculty/serrano/pdfs/wp2002-14.pdf

More information

All-Pay Contests. (Ron Siegel; Econometrica, 2009) PhDBA 279B 13 Feb Hyo (Hyoseok) Kang First-year BPP

All-Pay Contests. (Ron Siegel; Econometrica, 2009) PhDBA 279B 13 Feb Hyo (Hyoseok) Kang First-year BPP All-Pay Contests (Ron Siegel; Econometrica, 2009) PhDBA 279B 13 Feb 2014 Hyo (Hyoseok) Kang First-year BPP Outline 1 Introduction All-Pay Contests An Example 2 Main Analysis The Model Generic Contests

More information

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Juyan Zhang and Yi Zhang February 20, 2011 Abstract We investigate hold-up in the case of both simultaneous and sequential investment. We show that if

More information

Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game

Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game Parkash Chander * and Myrna Wooders May 1, 2011 Abstract We propose a new concept of core for games in extensive form and label it the γ-core of an extensive

More information

Optimal retention for a stop-loss reinsurance with incomplete information

Optimal retention for a stop-loss reinsurance with incomplete information Optimal retention for a stop-loss reinsurance with incomplete information Xiang Hu 1 Hailiang Yang 2 Lianzeng Zhang 3 1,3 Department of Risk Management and Insurance, Nankai University Weijin Road, Tianjin,

More information

Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS Jan Werner University of Minnesota SPRING 2019 1 I.1 Equilibrium Prices in Security Markets Assume throughout this section that utility functions

More information

Game Theory Fall 2006

Game Theory Fall 2006 Game Theory Fall 2006 Answers to Problem Set 3 [1a] Omitted. [1b] Let a k be a sequence of paths that converge in the product topology to a; that is, a k (t) a(t) for each date t, as k. Let M be the maximum

More information

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS 4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS Marek Rutkowski School of Mathematics and Statistics University of Sydney Semester 2, 2016 M. Rutkowski (USydney) Slides 4: Single-Period Market Models 1 / 87 General Single-Period

More information

Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market. Jeffrey Gao

Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market. Jeffrey Gao Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market Jeffrey Gao ABSTRACT This paper extends a model of herd behavior developed by Bikhchandani and Sharma (000) to establish conditions for varying levels

More information

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3 EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3 Leonardo Felli 32L.G.06 26 January 2015 Failure of the Coase Theorem Recall that the Coase Theorem implies that two parties, when faced with a potential

More information

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Juyan Zhang and Yi Zhang December 20, 2010 Abstract We investigate hold-up with simultaneous and sequential investment. We show that if the encouragement

More information

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty Braz Camargo Dino Gerardi Lucas Maestri December 2015 Abstract We study efficiency in decentralized markets with aggregate uncertainty and

More information

OPTIMAL BLUFFING FREQUENCIES

OPTIMAL BLUFFING FREQUENCIES OPTIMAL BLUFFING FREQUENCIES RICHARD YEUNG Abstract. We will be investigating a game similar to poker, modeled after a simple game called La Relance. Our analysis will center around finding a strategic

More information

Economics 502 April 3, 2008

Economics 502 April 3, 2008 Second Midterm Answers Prof. Steven Williams Economics 502 April 3, 2008 A full answer is expected: show your work and your reasoning. You can assume that "equilibrium" refers to pure strategies unless

More information

Yao s Minimax Principle

Yao s Minimax Principle Complexity of algorithms The complexity of an algorithm is usually measured with respect to the size of the input, where size may for example refer to the length of a binary word describing the input,

More information

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria and Rational Expectations Equilibria 1 Basic Setup Two periods: 0 and 1 One riskless asset with interest rate r One risky asset which pays a normally distributed

More information

Socially-Optimal Design of Crowdsourcing Platforms with Reputation Update Errors

Socially-Optimal Design of Crowdsourcing Platforms with Reputation Update Errors Socially-Optimal Design of Crowdsourcing Platforms with Reputation Update Errors 1 Yuanzhang Xiao, Yu Zhang, and Mihaela van der Schaar Abstract Crowdsourcing systems (e.g. Yahoo! Answers and Amazon Mechanical

More information

AMH4 - ADVANCED OPTION PRICING. Contents

AMH4 - ADVANCED OPTION PRICING. Contents AMH4 - ADVANCED OPTION PRICING ANDREW TULLOCH Contents 1. Theory of Option Pricing 2 2. Black-Scholes PDE Method 4 3. Martingale method 4 4. Monte Carlo methods 5 4.1. Method of antithetic variances 5

More information

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games Game Theory Wolfgang Frimmel Repeated Games 1 / 41 Recap: SPNE The solution concept for dynamic games with complete information is the subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium (SPNE) Selten (1965): A strategy

More information

Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games

Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games Michael Ummels ummels@logic.rwth-aachen.de FSTTCS 2006 Michael Ummels Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction 1 / 15 Infinite

More information

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Research Department Staff Report 287 March 2001 Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Harold L. Cole University of California, Los Angeles and Federal Reserve Bank

More information

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games CPSC 532l Lecture 10 Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games CPSC 532l Lecture 10, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Stochastic Games 3 Bayesian Games 4 Analyzing Bayesian

More information

Political Lobbying in a Recurring Environment

Political Lobbying in a Recurring Environment Political Lobbying in a Recurring Environment Avihai Lifschitz Tel Aviv University This Draft: October 2015 Abstract This paper develops a dynamic model of the labor market, in which the employed workers,

More information

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009. Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Do not forget to write Problems 1 and 2 in the first Blue Book and Problems 3 and 4 in the second Blue Book. 1 Econ 101A

More information

INTERIM CORRELATED RATIONALIZABILITY IN INFINITE GAMES

INTERIM CORRELATED RATIONALIZABILITY IN INFINITE GAMES INTERIM CORRELATED RATIONALIZABILITY IN INFINITE GAMES JONATHAN WEINSTEIN AND MUHAMET YILDIZ A. In a Bayesian game, assume that the type space is a complete, separable metric space, the action space is

More information

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk Kenneth Mirkin and Marek Pycia June 2015. Preliminary Draft. Abstract We study directed search in a frictional two-sided matching market in which each seller

More information

A Core Concept for Partition Function Games *

A Core Concept for Partition Function Games * A Core Concept for Partition Function Games * Parkash Chander December, 2014 Abstract In this paper, we introduce a new core concept for partition function games, to be called the strong-core, which reduces

More information

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE Answers to Problem Set 2 [1] (a) This is standard (we have even done it in class). The one-shot Cournot outputs can be computed to be A/3, while the payoff to each firm can

More information

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version)

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) July 4, 2017 1. Person A lexicographically prefers good x to good y, i.e., when comparing two bundles of x and y, she strictly prefers

More information

PhD Qualifier Examination

PhD Qualifier Examination PhD Qualifier Examination Department of Agricultural Economics May 29, 2014 Instructions This exam consists of six questions. You must answer all questions. If you need an assumption to complete a question,

More information

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2 Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2 Jörgen Weibull February 4, 2010 Two topics today: 1. Existence of Nash equilibria (Lecture notes Chapter 10 and Appendix A) 2. Relations between equilibrium and rationality

More information

EconS Games with Incomplete Information II and Auction Theory

EconS Games with Incomplete Information II and Auction Theory EconS 424 - Games with Incomplete Information II and Auction Theory Félix Muñoz-García Washington State University fmunoz@wsu.edu April 28, 2014 Félix Muñoz-García (WSU) EconS 424 - Recitation 9 April

More information

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2013 *********************************************** COVER SHEET ***********************************************

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to GAME THEORY PROBLEM SET 1 WINTER 2018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to andrey.zhukov@aalto.fi. Materials from Osborne and Rubinstein

More information

Existence of Nash Networks and Partner Heterogeneity

Existence of Nash Networks and Partner Heterogeneity Existence of Nash Networks and Partner Heterogeneity pascal billand a, christophe bravard a, sudipta sarangi b a Université de Lyon, Lyon, F-69003, France ; Université Jean Monnet, Saint-Etienne, F-42000,

More information

Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining

Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining Model September 30, 2010 1 Overview In these supplementary

More information

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we 6 Mixed Strategies In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we postponed discussing the option that a player may choose to randomize between several of his pure strategies.

More information

Kutay Cingiz, János Flesch, P. Jean-Jacques Herings, Arkadi Predtetchinski. Doing It Now, Later, or Never RM/15/022

Kutay Cingiz, János Flesch, P. Jean-Jacques Herings, Arkadi Predtetchinski. Doing It Now, Later, or Never RM/15/022 Kutay Cingiz, János Flesch, P Jean-Jacques Herings, Arkadi Predtetchinski Doing It Now, Later, or Never RM/15/ Doing It Now, Later, or Never Kutay Cingiz János Flesch P Jean-Jacques Herings Arkadi Predtetchinski

More information

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi 10.1287/mnsc.1110.1334ec e-companion ONLY AVAILABLE IN ELECTRONIC FORM informs 2011 INFORMS Electronic Companion Trust in Forecast Information Sharing by Özalp Özer, Yanchong Zheng,

More information

UCLA Department of Economics Ph.D. Preliminary Exam Industrial Organization Field Exam (Spring 2010) Use SEPARATE booklets to answer each question

UCLA Department of Economics Ph.D. Preliminary Exam Industrial Organization Field Exam (Spring 2010) Use SEPARATE booklets to answer each question Wednesday, June 23 2010 Instructions: UCLA Department of Economics Ph.D. Preliminary Exam Industrial Organization Field Exam (Spring 2010) You have 4 hours for the exam. Answer any 5 out 6 questions. All

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 5 [1] Consider an infinitely repeated game with a finite number of actions for each player and a common discount factor δ. Prove that if δ is close enough to zero then

More information

Dynamic signaling and market breakdown

Dynamic signaling and market breakdown Journal of Economic Theory ( ) www.elsevier.com/locate/jet Dynamic signaling and market breakdown Ilan Kremer, Andrzej Skrzypacz Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305, USA

More information

Information Disclosure and Real Investment in a Dynamic Setting

Information Disclosure and Real Investment in a Dynamic Setting Information Disclosure and Real Investment in a Dynamic Setting Sunil Dutta Haas School of Business University of California, Berkeley dutta@haas.berkeley.edu and Alexander Nezlobin Haas School of Business

More information

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core Camelia Bejan and Juan Camilo Gómez September 2011 Abstract The paper shows that the aspiration core of any TU-game coincides with

More information

Q1. [?? pts] Search Traces

Q1. [?? pts] Search Traces CS 188 Spring 2010 Introduction to Artificial Intelligence Midterm Exam Solutions Q1. [?? pts] Search Traces Each of the trees (G1 through G5) was generated by searching the graph (below, left) with a

More information

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu June 16th, 2016 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics)

More information

Game Theory for Wireless Engineers Chapter 3, 4

Game Theory for Wireless Engineers Chapter 3, 4 Game Theory for Wireless Engineers Chapter 3, 4 Zhongliang Liang ECE@Mcmaster Univ October 8, 2009 Outline Chapter 3 - Strategic Form Games - 3.1 Definition of A Strategic Form Game - 3.2 Dominated Strategies

More information

Debt Contracts and Cooperative Improvements

Debt Contracts and Cooperative Improvements Debt Contracts and Cooperative Improvements Stefan Krasa Tridib Sharma Anne P. Villamil February 9, 2004 Abstract In this paper we consider a dynamic game with imperfect information between a borrower

More information

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders Michael Ostrovsky Setup n risk-neutral players, i = 1,..., n Finite set of states of the world Ω Random variable ( security ) X : Ω R Each

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Leonardo Felli 9 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Consider now a different cause for the failure of the Coase Theorem: the presence of transaction costs. Of course for this to be an interesting

More information

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5 Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5 The basic idea prisoner s dilemma The prisoner s dilemma game with one-shot payoffs 2 2 0

More information