Short Selling, Earnings Management, and Firm Value

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Short Selling, Earnings Management, and Firm Value"

Transcription

1 Short Selling, Earnings Management, and Firm Value Jinzhi Lu October 23, 2018 Abstract This paper studies the interaction between short selling and earnings management (misreporting). I show informed short selling and uninformed short selling play different interaction roles. Ex post, informed short selling facilitates the detection of misreporting, whereas uninformed short selling distorts the detection of misreporting. Ex ante, short selling can affect the manager s choice of misreporting level. The main conclusions of this paper are as follows: (1) Whether uninformed short selling should be banned can depend on the trade-off between the ex-ante reduction in misreporting and the ex-post increase in distortion; (2) banning informed short selling may reduce misreporting, but always reduces firm value. I am grateful to Pingyang Gao for his guidance and support. I also appreciate helpful comments from Philip Berger, Miao Liu, Haresh Sapra, and the PhD students at the University of Chicago Booth School of Business. 1

2 1 Introduction Should short selling be encouraged or restricted? Some proponents of short selling argue that informed short selling leads to more informative stock prices that better guide firms real decisions. The mechanism behind their argument is the feedback effect. Feedback happens when outsiders of firms know information insiders don t know. Outsiders trade on their information, and therefore stock prices contain useful information that can guide insiders decisions (empirical evidence includes Durnev et al. (2004), Chen, Goldstein, and Jiang (2007), and Luo (2005)). Examples of theses proponents include Diamond and Verrecchia (1987), Leland (1992), and Goldstein and Guembel (2008). In these models, bad news is better reflected in stock prices if informed short selling is allowed. Managers learn from the stock prices and cancel negative NPV projects. Other proponents argue that informed short selling helps uncover accounting fraud. For example, in his account of short selling in Allied Capital, Inc., hedge fund manager David Einhorn argues short sellers help uncover financial reporting violations. Although opponents of short selling may not object to the role informed short sellers play, they argue that uninformed short sellers can reduce firm values through the self-fulfilling prophesy of short selling. For example, Goldstein and Guembel (2008) present a model in which the feedback effect generates equilibria in which uninformed speculators sell. Such uninformed short selling reduces the informativeness of stock price and leads to the cancellation of positive NPV projects, hence reducing firm value. Integrating the arguments of proponents and opponents, one might believe that informed short selling should be encouraged and uninformed short selling should be discouraged. However, such arguments focus only on the ex-post consequences of short selling. I argue that short selling also affects ex-ante actions. For example, consider the situation in which the shareholders of a firm are evaluating a manager s performance. The manager can inflate his 2

3 performance in such a way that the observed performance diverges from his true performance. Fortunately, a speculator exists who knows the manager s true performance and trades accordingly. The speculator s trading has two effects: (1) ex-post, it helps shareholders correctly evaluate the manager s performance; (2) ex-ante, it affects the manager s willingness to engage in performance inflation. I focus on the second channel. A common example of performance inflation is earnings management. In this paper, I develop a model to study the interaction between short selling and earnings management. Specifically, I consider a setting where the current shareholders of a firm are deciding whether to fire a manger. The manager s type can be good or bad. If no earnings management is present, a good manager produces a good report and a bad manager produces a bad report. However, if a bad manager can engage in costly manipulation to issue a good report, earnings reports are not a perfect signal of the manager s type. This scenario leaves some room for the shareholders to learn from the trading in the financial market. As in Goldstein and Guembel (2008), in the stock market, a speculator exists who may have private information about the manager s type and trades on this information. Noisy traders are also present in the market. As in Kyle (1985), the market maker can only observe the sum of order flows the noise traders and the speculator submit. Based on his information, the market maker sets a stock price that is equal to the expected value of the manager. Under this market structure, the speculator s trading orders can partially reveal his private information and provide useful feedback to the shareholders. My model predicts that banning short selling (either informed or uninformed) can increase or decrease the manager s choice of misreporting level. The intuition is as follows. First, note the shareholders are making the decision based on two information sources: the earnings report and stock price. Whereas a bad report reveals a bad manager perfectly, a good report can come from a bad or a good manager. Upon a good report, because the shareholders can 3

4 only observe the stock price, and not the speculator s type, and because a higher stock price indicates a better manager, the shareholders will unconditionally retain the manager if and only if the stock price is higher than a certain threshold. If short selling is banned, then ex post, the stock price will be higher, and issuing a good report will be more rewarding for the bad manager. However, shareholders rationally anticipate the higher stock price and will set the equilibrium threshold higher. A higher threshold implies less incentive to misreport. How the misreporting level changes depends on the trade-off between the higher stock price and the higher threshold. The trade-off can go both directions. In addition, I show uninformed short selling and informed short selling play fundamentally different roles in affecting firm value. First, I show banning uninformed short selling can reduce firm value because of the possible increase in misreporting. Second, I show banning informed short selling always reduces firm value, even though it can reduce misreporting. I discuss what tool policy makers can use to restrict short selling. If the ideal policy goal is to allow both informed and uninformed short sellers, a policy maker can achieve this goal through imposing no restrictions on short selling. On the other hand, based on my results, the ideal policy goal could also be to allow informed short sellers and ban uninformed ones. As Goldstein and Guembel (2008) suggested, a policy maker can achieve the goal through imposing short-selling costs. According to them, this policy can work because informed short sellers make more profit than uninformed short sellers. By setting a short-selling cost in the middle range, a policy maker is able to predict an equilibrium outcome in which the uninformed speculators do not trade, and the negatively unformed speculators sell. I formally prove this result in the paper. To sum up, the contribution of this study is threefold. First, it establishes a theory to explain how short selling affects misreporting and firm value. Second, it shows banning uninformed short selling can increase misreporting and reduce firm value. Third, it proves 4

5 banning informed short selling can reduce misreporting, but always reduces firm value. 1.1 Related literature The feedback effect assumption is implicit behind the debate on short selling, because if short selling does not affect firms real decisions, then at the firm level, no efficiency gain or loss will be associated with short selling. Many empirical studies support the feedback mechanism. For example, Durnev et al. (2004) document a robust cross-sectional positive association between stock return variation and investment efficiency, suggesting that a more informative stock price leads to better investment. Luo (2005) finds the market reaction to a merger and acquisition announcement affects the firm s later decision on the deal. Chen et al. (2007) find informed trading has a strong positive effect on the sensitivity of corporate investment to stock price. Durnev and Mangen (2009) find restatement in a firm s financial report is related to its competitors investment decisions. All this evidence points to the fact that outside information sources can guide firms real decisions. On the other hand, analytical studies in the feedback effect literature typically start with simplified assumptions on firms insiders. First, they often assume that insiders know nothing about firms future prospects. Second, the studies typically assume that no agency conflict exists between managers and shareholders. For example, in the models of Goldstein and Guembel (2008), Khanna and Mathews (2012), and Edmans et al. (2015), managers are uninformed and take actions to maximize firm value. Although insider information and agency conflicts are not the focus of these studies, exploring settings where they are incorporated remains interesting. Gao and Liang (2013) relax the first assumption and show disclosure by firm insiders lowers outsiders incentive to acquire information. Dow and Gorton (1997) relax the second assumption and explore the moral hazard problem where the existence of informed outsiders may lower managers incentives to acquire information. In my model, I relax the agency assumption to explore the interaction between short selling and earnings management. 5

6 My study is directly related to recent empirical studies such as Massa et al. (2015) and Fang et al. (2015). These two studies show short selling curbs earnings management. My model provides a theoretical framework to interpret their empirical results, and shows their results can arise from the trade-off of several forces. I organize the paper as follows. In section 2, I describe the model and define the equilibrium concept. In section 3, I explore the basic properties of the equilibrium and the conditions under which uninformed short selling exists. In section 4, I show the main results. First, I show banning uninformed short selling can increase misreporting and reduce firm value. Second, I show banning informed short selling always reduces firm value. Section 5 concludes. 2 Model The model introduces earnings management into a simplified Goldstein and Guembel (2008) setting. The current shareholders of a firm are deciding whether to fire a manager. Two signals about the type of the manager are generated: a public earnings report and a private signal that only a speculator learns. The speculator trades in the stock market, and therefore the stock price partially reflects the speculator s private information. The shareholders make the decision based on the earnings report and the stock price. All players are risk neutral. Details of the model are described below. 2.1 Setup The manager knows his ability θ {L, H}, which is equally likely ex ante. An H manager (good manager) increases the shareholder value by V, and an L manager (bad manager) destroys shareholder value by V. The manager receives an extra benefit of 1 from retaining the job. Without earnings management, an earnings report r(θ) = θ is disclosed. However, the manager can manipulate the report at a cost. In particular, a low-ability manager can issue an H report with probability β at a private cost of c(β) = 1 2 cβ2, where c is a parameter 6

7 that catches the magnitude of the cost. 1 2 Although the ex-ante mean of θ is 0, conditional on r = H, the expectation of θ is positive, as can be seen from E[θ r = H] = 1 β 1+β V 0. 3 In other words, r = H indicates a good manager on average. Hence, without looking at the stock price, the shareholders will retain the manager for sure when r = H and fire the manager for sure when r = L. The game has 3 additional players: a speculator, a noise trader, a market maker. I now describe their roles in detail. The speculator, who has no initial position in the firm s stock and will trade to maximize profit, receives a signal about the manager s type. With probability α, the speculator receives a perfect signal s = l if θ = L, s = h if θ = H. With probability 1 α, the speculator receives no information. For simplicity, I use the term positively informed to describe the speculator who gets s = h. Similarly, negatively informed and uninformed speculator describe the speculators who get s = l and s =, respectively. Trading occurs for only one period in which the speculator submits an endogenous order d { 1, 0, 1} (short-selling, no trade, buying) based on his information. Following Kyle (1985), the noise trader submits an exogenous order n f(n), where f is some distribution that has support (, ). I assume f(n) satisfies the following assumptions. Assumption 1 Suppose f(.) has the following properties: (1) (MLRP) f(n 1) f(n) is increasing in n. (2) (boundary condition) lim n f(n 1) f(n) = 0. 1 An alternative setup could be the following. The firm needs to decide whether to continue a project or not. The manager knows the quality of the project θ {L, H}, which is equally likely ex ante. An H project generates a future profit of V > 0, and an L project generates a future loss of V. The manager receives a rent of 1 if the firm invests in the project. Without earnings management, r(θ) = θ is disclosed. However, the manager can manipulate the report at a cost. In particular, if θ = L, the manager can issue an H report with probability β at a private cost of c(β) = 1 2 cβ2, where c is a parameter that catches the magnitude of the cost. 2 The main results of the paper still hold as long as the cost function is convex. 3 Hence, assuming E[θ] = 0 does not hurt the model s ability to illustrate how short sellers can destroy a good firm. 7

8 (3) (symmetry) f(n) = f( n), n. A typical example of f(.) is the normal distribution with mean 0. Only one round of trading occurs. The market maker observes the total order flow Q = n + d and sets the price based on the total order flow and manager s report: p(r, Q) = max(e[θ r, Q], 0). For simplicity, I assume the shareholders can also observe the total order flow Q. Because the shareholders are risk neutral, they will fire the manager if and only if E[θ r, Q] < 0. If the manager is retained, the speculator makes a profit of d(e[θ s, r] p(r, Q)). If the manager is fired, the speculator s profit is 0. Figure 1: information structure 2.2 Time line of the model The time line of the events is as follows: t=1, manager s ability θ {L, H} is realized, type L manager chooses management level β and pays a cost of c(β) = 1 2 cβ2. t=2, the speculator receives his private signal s. Manager s report r is generated. Everyone can observe the report r. The noise trader and the speculator submit trading orders d and n. 8

9 Only the total order flow Q = d + n is observed. t=3, Based on order flow Q and report r, the market maker sets price as the expected value of the manager: p(q, r) = max(e[θ Q, r], 0). The shareholders, who can also observe Q and r, will fire the manager if and only if p < Definition of the equilibrium The equilibrium concept that will be used is a Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE). It is defined as follows: (i) The speculator s trading strategy maximizes his expected profit, given his private signal s, the price-setting rule of the market maker, and the decision strategy of the shareholders. (ii) Type L manager s choice of earnings management level maximizes his expected payoff, given the strategy of the shareholders. (iii) A decision strategy the by the shareholders that maximizes their expected payoff, based on order flow Q and earnings report r, and given all other strategies. (iv) A price-setting rule p = E[θ Q, r] that allows the market maker to break even. (v) Players use Bayes rule to update their beliefs whenever possible. (vi) Each player s has a rational belief about other players strategies. 3 The Equilibrium The main goal of this paper is to study the interaction between short selling and earnings management and whether informed and uninformed short selling play different interaction roles. But when do informed and uninformed short selling exist? In this section, I investigate the basic properties of the equilibrium and derive conditions under which the uninformed speculators short sells. Such preparation work is needed for further analysis. 9

10 3.1 Basic properties of the equilibrium Lemma 1 below pins down the equilibrium strategies of the positively informed and the negatively informed speculators and states that informed short selling always exists in my model. It is extremely useful throughout the paper. Lemma 1 If no restriction is placed on trading, the positively informed speculator (s = h) plays d = 1 with probability 1, and the negatively informed speculator (s = l) plays d = 1 with probability 1. Lemma 1 is intuitive. The positively informed speculator wants to buy because he knows for sure the manager is of good type and his valuation of the firm is thus V. If his private information (s = h) is fully revealed through Q, then the price p will be set to V and he makes 0 profit. If his private information is not fully revealed through Q, p < V and he makes a positive profit. By not trading, he makes 0 profit, and by short selling, he makes negative profit. Therefore, the only possible action for type s = h is buying (d = 1). The intuition for the negatively informed speculator s action is similar. Now, I use β to denote the equilibrium level of earnings management. Proposition 1 below shows that in the equilibrium, the shareholders follow a threshold strategy. That is, upon seeing r = H, they will retain the manager if and only if the order flow Q is above some threshold q. Proposition 1 If no restriction is placed on trading, then in any equilibrium, (1) A threshold q 0 (q can be ) exists such that the manager will be retained if and only if r = H and q q. Besides, when β = 1, q = 0. 10

11 (2) The MM s equilibrium pricing function is p(q = q, r = H) = E[θ Q = q, r = H] > 0, if q > q ; p(q = q, r = H) = 0, if q q ; p(q = q, r = L) = 0, q. The intuition for proposition 1 is as follows. Note the shareholders are making the decision based on two information sources: earnings report and the order flow. Whereas a bad report reveals a bad manager perfectly, a good report can come from a bad or a good manager. Upon a good report (r = H), because the shareholders can only observe the order flow, not the speculator s type, and because a higher order flow indicates a better manager, the shareholders will unconditionally retain the manager if and only if the order flow is bigger than a certain threshold. Also note that q 0. The intuition is as follows. By the symmetry property of f(n), relative to r = H alone, Q > 0 and r = H implies a better manager, whereas Q < 0 and r = H implies a worse manager. Because E[θ r = H, Q = q ] = 0 < E[θ r = H], q must be negative. 3.2 Existence of uninformed short selling Lemma 2 presents some clues about the strategy of the uninformed speculator. Lemma 2 If no restriction is placed on trading, the uninformed speculator plays d = 1 with probability 0. Lemma 2 says the uninformed speculator will never buy in the equilibrium. The intuition is as follows. If he plays d = 1, he makes a positive profit when Q < 0. However, Q < 0 happens when n < 1, which happens with probability less than 1 2. When n > 1, which happens with probability larger than 1 2, he makes a negative profit. Therefore, overall, he loses if he buys. 11

12 Now I study the conditions for the existence of uninformed short selling. Let c 0 = 1 F (1). In lemma 6 of the appendix, I show c c 0 implies β = 1. To avoid this uninteresting case, I assume c > c 0 for the rest of the paper. Proposition 2 c > c 0 exists such that if c (c 0, c ), then β (0, 1) and the uninformed speculator plays d = 1 with probability 1 in the equilibrium. Proposition 2 is the main result of this section. I now explain the intuition in detail. If the total order flow turns out to be Q = q > 0, the uninformed speculator s short position is established at a price higher than his valuation and therefore he makes a positive profit. If the total order flow turns out to be q < Q = q < 0, the uninformed speculator s short position is established at a price lower than his valuation and therefore he makes a negative profit. If the total order flow turns out to be Q = q < q, the uninformed speculator s short position is established at a price of 0 and he makes 0 profit. Hence, the speculator s gain and loss are not symmetric, because the region for gain is q (0, + ), whereas the region for loss is q (q, 0). When Q < q, the manager will be fired and the uninformed speculator can guarantee 0 loss. If q is close enough to zero, which happens when β is close to 1 or the cost of earnings management is low enough (close to c 0 ), the gain should outweigh the loss and the speculator can lock in a strictly positive profit by short selling. In other words, the uninformed speculator short sells and hopes two things: (1) the total order flow is high; and (2) even if the total order flow is low, he won t lose much. In this way, he is guaranteed a positive expected profit on average. We can see that when the total order flow is low, the uninformed speculator really wants a good manager to be fired because his profit will otherwise be negative, instead of zero. 12

13 Similar to Goldstein and Guembel (2008), in my model, the uninformed speculator s shortselling strategy (d = 1) is manipulative in nature. This is because, based on the uninformed speculator s information set, E[θ r = H, s = ] = E[θ r = H] = 1 β 1+β V > 0. By short-selling, he pools with the negatively informed speculator, which leads to a higher probability that the shareholders fire a good manager. But why only short selling can destroy a good manager, not selling? In fact, the assumption that the speculator has no initial position is crucial for proposition 2. If the uninformed speculator has an initial position in the firm, his profit from selling is the difference between the price he receives if he sells today and the price he receives if he waits until the next period (after the decision on manager is made). If the uninformed speculator sells (d = 1) and this leads to the firing of the manager, today s price will be zero. On the other hand, if the uninformed speculator plays d = 0 instead of d = 1, then the price for the next period will more likely be positive because the manager is less likely to be fired. Hence, if the uninformed speculator has an initial position, he would prefer d = 0 (no trade), as destroying a good manager is not what he wants. 3.3 Introducing a short-selling cost into the model One natural way to study the effects of short selling is to compare the case where short selling is banned and the case in which short selling is allowed. However, using such a method, separating the effect of uninformed short selling from the effect of informed short selling would be hard. Is looking at their effects separately feasible? As Goldstein and Guembel (2008) suggested, imposing the short-selling cost can do the trick. I formalize the result in this subsection. Assumption 2 Suppose an additional player, a decision maker (DM), enters the game before t = 1. The DM aims to maximize expected firm value and can impose a short selling cost 13

14 κ 0. Proposition 3 Suppose c (c 0, c ), (1) if κ = 0, then d(s = h) = 1, d(s = l) = 1, and d(s = ) = 1 (buy-sell-sell, or BSS equilibrium). (2) κ 1 > 0 exists such that if κ = κ 1, then d(s = h) = 1, d(s = l) = 1, and d(s = ) = 0 (buy-sell-no trade, or BSN equilibrium). (3) κ 2 > 0 exists such that if κ = κ 2, then d(s = h) = 1, d(s = l) = 0, and d(s = ) = 0 (buy-no trade-no trade, or BNN equilibrium). The key intuition behind proposition 3 is that the negatively informed speculator makes more profit than the uninformed speculator. Hence, they can be separated by a short selling cost that is higher than the profit of the uninformed speculator but lower than the profit of the negatively informed short seller. Of course, if the short-selling cost is high enough, then both of them will be discouraged from short selling. Based on the definitions, the comparison between the BSS equilibrium and the BSN equilibrium reveals the role of uninformed short selling. The comparison between the BNN equilibrium and the BSN equilibrium reveals the role of informed short selling. From now on, I define the ban on uninformed short selling as the switch from κ = 0 to κ = κ 1. I define the ban on informed short selling as the switch from κ = κ 1 to κ = κ 2. 4 Main Results With the preparation work in the previous section, in this section, I return to the main research question of this paper: the interaction between short selling and earnings management. More specifically, first, I will investigate the effect of banning short selling on earnings management. 14

15 Second, I will investigate the efficiency of banning short selling (i.e., whether firm value increases or decreases due to the ban on short selling). 4.1 Uninformed short selling A natural way to study the effect of banning uninformed short selling is to compare the BSS equilibrium with the BSN equilibrium. Proposition 4 below replicates the main result of Goldstein and Guembel (2008). It shows that if the earnings management level β is exogenous, uninformed short selling reduces firm value. Proposition 4 If the misreporting level β is exogenous, the DM prefers κ = κ 1 to κ = 0; The intuition for proposition 4 is as follows. Because conditional on r = H, the manager is more likely to be good, the uninformed short speculators distort shareholders decision by trading in the wrong direction, which leads to a higher chance that a good manager is fired. Hence, from an ex-post perspective, banning uninformed short selling is always efficient. To sum up, if the level of earnings management β is exogenous, the firm value in the BSN equilibrium is the highest. However, if the level of earnings management β is endogenously determined, the conclusion of proposition 4 may no longer hold. In fact, the level of earnings management can be ex-ante affected through two channels. These two channels are discussed below. The first channel is the stock price (order-flow) channel. As we can see from proposition 1, in the equilibrium, conditional on r = H, the shareholders will retain the manager if and only if the total order flow is bigger than a certain threshold. If uninformed short selling is banned, then ex post, the order flow will be higher, and issuing a r = H report will be more rewarding for the type L manager. The second channel is the threshold channel. If uninformed short selling is banned, then 15

16 in the equilibrium, the threshold q will adjust accordingly. Because q can go up or down, the incentive for earnings management could be more or less. Based on these two channels, if uninformed short selling is banned, the level of earnings management can go up or down. Proposition 5, however, shows that if the cost of earnings management is sufficiently low and if uninformed short selling is banned, earnings management level will become higher and firm value will become lower. For notation purposes, I use β 1 and β 2 to denote the equilibrium earnings management level in the BSS and the BSN equilibrium, respectively. Proposition 5 c (c 0, c ] exists such that when c (c 0, c), (1) the decision maker prefers κ = 0 to κ = κ 1, and (2) 0 < β 1 < β 2 = 1. The intuition for proposition 5 is as follows. First, when the cost of earnings management (c) is low, namely when β is large and close to 1, the threshold q should be close to 0, and therefore the room for q to change is minimal. Therefore, banning uninformed short selling will mainly cause the stock price to become higher. That is to say, the stock price channel will dominate the threshold channel. As a result, if uninformed short selling is banned, the low-type manager understands he is more likely to be retained if he can issue a high report. In other words, the marginal benefit of engaging in earnings management becomes higher if uninformed short selling is banned. For this reason, ex-ante, a higher level of earnings management will be chosen. Second, although banning uninformed short selling benefits the shareholders ex-post decision, ex ante, the ban of uninformed short selling leads to a higher level of earnings management. When the cost of earnings management (c) is low, the choice of earnings management is more elastic and therefore the ex-ante effect dominates. As a result, when c is low, firm 16

17 value goes down if uninformed short selling is banned. Therefore, the decision maker prefers κ = 0 over κ = κ 1. In fact, proposition 5 is equivalent to saying that uninformed short selling can deter earnings management. To understand this deterring effect, first note that ex-post, both uninformed short selling and informed short selling drive down stock price. Hence, when shareholders see a low stock price, they are not able to tell whom it comes from and have to fire the manager unconditionally if the fraction of informed speculators is large enough. The low-type manager anticipates the shareholders action and knows that even if he issues a high report, his chance of being retained becomes lower because the uninformed speculator drives down the stock price. Hence, in this case, the natural consequence of allowing uninformed short selling is less earnings management An Example One might be concerned proposition 5 relies on corner solution (β 2 = 1). Here I provide an analytically tractable example that does not rely on corner solution but delivers the same intuition as proposition 5. Suppose the distribution of noise trading (f(n)) is as follows: Noisy trading n Probability Noe the random variable n is now discrete, but its distribution f(n) still satisfies the MLRP property and the symmetry property. The random variable n can be decomposed as n = n 1 + n 2, where n 1 and n 2 are i.i.d. and take the value { 1, 0, 1} with probability 1 3 each. In other words, we can think of noise trading as submitted by two independent noise traders who buy, sell, and don t trade with equal probability. For notation purposes, I still use β 1 and β 2 for the level of earnings management in the BSS and the BSN equilibrium, respectively. Similar to proposition 2, proposition 6 shows that when c is sufficiently small, the BSS 17

18 equilibrium is the only possible outcome. Proposition 6 If κ = 0, the uninformed speculator short sells with probability 1 in any PBE if and only if c (0, 1 3 2α ). Further, β (0, 1) for c ( 1 3, 1 3 2α ). Proposition 7 illustrates that uninformed short selling can deter earnings management and save firm value. Proposition 7 Suppose c ( 1 3, 1 3 2α ), then (1) 0 < β 1 < β 2 < 1. (2) If α ( 1 4 (9 33), 1) and c ( 3 α 3, 1 3 2α ), the decision maker prefers κ = κ 1 to κ = 0. (3) Otherwise, if c ( 1 3, 3 α 3 ), the decision maker prefers κ = 0 to κ = κ 1. The intuition for proposition 7 is similar to that for proposition 5. Ex ante, uninformed short selling deters earnings management, as can be seen from β 1 < β 2. Ex post, uninformed short selling distorts shareholders decisions. Hence, whether uninformed short selling should be banned depends on the severity of the earnings management problem. When c is low, indicating a severe problem, uninformed short selling should be allowed as a weapon against earnings management. 4.2 Informed short selling This subsection compares the BSN equilibrium with the BNN equilibrium. Such comparison reveals the role of informed short selling Can banning informed short selling reduce misreporting? As one would expect, informed short selling can also affect β through two channels. The stock price (order-flow) channel is identical to the stock price channel in section 4.1. That is, banning informed short selling raises order flow and makes earnings management more rewarding. 18

19 The threshold channel, however, differs from the threshold channel in section 4.1. Here, if informed short selling is banned, the shareholders rationally understand that even a high stock price (order flow) may contain considerable amount of bad news. Hence, they tend to raise the equilibrium threshold. A higher threshold implies less incentive to misreport. Hence, depending on the trade-off between the two channels, the earnings management level can go up or down. Proposition 8 below gives an example in which banning informed short selling reduces the earnings management level. Proposition 8 Consider the same example in section If c ( 1 3, 1 3 α ), then the switch from κ = κ 1 (the BSN equilibrium) to κ = κ 2 (the BNN equilibrium) will (1) raise the threshold from q = 0 to q = 1. (2) reduce the earnings management level from β = ( α)/c to β = 1 3c. To understand proposition 8, first note q = 1 is a very high threshold, requiring the shareholders to have a very pessimistic belief about the manager even if r = H. Only when the shareholders suspect a high level of β, will they update their belief pessimistically. Hence, to sustain a high q in a rational expectation equilibrium, β has to be in the high range and therefore c has to be low, which explains the c < 1 3 α condition. But why does the earnings management level drop after informed short selling is banned? To understand this, remember that upon r = H, the shareholders will retain the manager if and only if the total order flow Q is higher than the threshold q. Also remember the manager will manage earnings only when his type is bad. Conditional on the manager being bad, the speculator can only be negatively informed or uninformed. The negatively informed speculator s order flow increases from 1 to 0 after informed short selling is banned. However, the threshold also increases by 1 (from q = 0 to q = 1). These two effects exactly offset each other. Hence, if the speculator is negatively informed, the ban on informed short selling will not change the bad manager s incentive to engage in earnings management. Nevertheless, 19

20 the threshold change is independent of the speculator s type. After informed short selling is banned, the uninformed speculator s order flow remains at 0 while the threshold still increases. Hence, if the speculator is uninformed, the ban on informed short selling will lower the bad manager s incentive to engage in earnings management. As a result, because the bad manager understands the speculator is either negatively informed or uninformed, overall, he will have less incentive to engage in earnings management Can banning informed short selling increase firm value? One might expect that because banning informed short selling can reduce the earnings management level, it can also increase firm value. However, the proposition below gives us the result that banning informed short selling always reduces firm value. Proposition 9 If α > 0, the firm value in the BSN equilibrium is strictly higher than the firm value in the BNN equilibrium. Proposition 9 tells us that although banning informed short selling may help discipline ex-ante misreporting, it actually distorts the ex-post detection of misreporting so much that firm value always decreases. Based on the results so far, from the ex-post perspective, both allowing uninformed short selling and banning informed short selling reduces firm value because both of them reduce the informativeness of stock price. From the ex-ante perspective, both allowing uninformed short selling and banning informed short selling can deter earnings management. However, when the ex-post and the ex-ante effects are both considered, banning informed short selling always reduces firm value, whereas allowing uninformed short selling can increase firm value. Why is the difference between the efficiency roles of informed and uninformed short selling so big? 20

21 To answer this question, we need to go back to the mechanism for uninformed short selling. Uninformed short sellers can profit from destroying firm value, because decision makers cannot distinguish them from informed short sellers. If a sufficient fraction of informed speculators is in the market, a low stock price implies a sufficient degree of negative information. As a consequence, even if a project can be good conditional on the speculator being uninformed, it will still be canceled. However, if no one is informed in the market and this information is common knowledge, uninformed speculators cannot profit from short selling, because a low stock price would no longer suggest negative information. Hence, uninformed short selling can distort ex-post decision making only when informed short selling provides a sufficient amount of useful information. Therefore, the distorting role of uninformed short-selling is secondary to the information-providing role of informed short selling, which explains why banning informed short selling always reduces firm value whereas allowing uninformed short selling can increase firm value. 5 Conclusions Although the ex-post role of short selling has been widely studied, the ex-ante role has not. In this paper, I link the ex-ante role of short selling to manager s misreporting problem, or earnings management. Specifically, I introduce managers misreporting incentive into the Goldstein and Guembel (2008) model. Similar to their results, the feedback effect generates the equilibrium whereby the uninformed speculator short sells. Such short-selling strategy decreases ex-post firm value because it increases the fraction of good managers fired (type I error). Hence, ex post, uninformed short-selling reduces firm value. On the ex-ante roles of short selling, my model predicts banning short selling can increase or reduce misreporting. Given that misreporting reduces firm value, I conjecture and prove 21

22 that banning uninformed short selling can reduce firm value. However, informed short selling are fundamentally different from uninformed short selling. I show that even though banning informed short selling can reduce misreporting, it always reduces firm value. This conclusion is equivalent to claiming the primary role of informed short selling is to convey bad news to the decision makers in the firms. References [1] Chen, Qi, Itay Goldstein, and Wei Jiang. Price informativeness and investment sensitivity to stock price. Review of Financial Studies 20.3 (2007): [2] Diamond, Douglas W., and Robert E. Verrecchia. Constraints on short-selling and asset price adjustment to private information. Journal of Financial Economics 18.2 (1987): [3] Dow, James, and Gary Gorton. Stock market efficiency and economic efficiency: is there a connection? Journal of Finance Vol. 52, No. 3: [4] Durnev, Art, and Claudine Mangen. Corporate investments: Learning from restatements. Journal of Accounting Research 47.3 (2009): [5] Durnev, Art, Randall Morck, and Bernard Yeung. Valueenhancing capital budgeting and firmspecific stock return variation. The Journal of Finance 59.1 (2004): [6] Edmans, Alex, Jiang Wei, and Itay Goldstein. Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage. The American Economic Review (2015): [7] Fang, Vivian W., Allen H. Huang, and Jonathan M. Karpoff. Short selling and earnings management: A controlled experiment. The Journal of Finance (2015). 22

23 [8] Gao, Pingyang, and Pierre Jinghong Liang. Informational Feedback, Adverse Selection, and Optimal Disclosure Policy. Journal of Accounting Research 51.5 (2013): [9] Goldstein, Itay, and Alexander Guembel. Manipulation and the allocational role of prices. The Review of Economic Studies 75.1 (2008): [10] Khanna, Naveen, and Richmond D. Mathews. Doing battle with short sellers: The conflicted role of blockholders in bear raids. Journal of Financial Economics (2012): [11] Kyle, Albert S. Continuous auctions and insider trading. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society (1985): [12] Luo, Yuanzhi. Do insiders learn from outsiders? Evidence from mergers and acquisitions. The Journal of Finance 60.4 (2005): [13] Massa, Massimo, Bohui Zhang, and Hong Zhang. The Invisible Hand of Short Selling: Does Short Selling Discipline Earnings Management?. Review of Financial Studies 28.6 (2015): A Appendix A.1 proof of proposition 1 Lemma 3 (monotone likelihood ratio property) In any PBE, the ratio Pr(Q=q θ=h) Pr(Q=q θ=l) increasing in q. Further, Pr(Q=q θ=h) Pr(Q=q θ=l) q=0 = 1. is Proof: By lemma 1, the positively informed speculator buys and the negatively informed speculator short sells. Suppose that in equilibrium, the uninformed speculator buys, doesn t 23

24 trade, and short sells with probability µ 1, µ 2, and µ 3, respectively. Hence, Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = L) = αf(q 1) + (1 α)(µ 1f(q 1) + µ 2 f(q) + µ 3 f(q + 1) αf(q + 1) + (1 α)(µ 1 f(q 1) + µ 2 f(q) + µ 3 f(q + 1) = (α + (1 α)µ 1)f(q 1)/f(q + 1) + (1 α)µ 2 f(q)/f(q + 1) + (1 α)µ 3 (1 α)µ 1 f(q 1)/f(q + 1) + (1 α)µ 2 f(q)/f(q + 1) + α + (1 α)µ 3 α(f(q 1)/f(q + 1) 1) = 1 + (1 α)µ 1 f(q 1)/f(q + 1) + (1 α)µ 2 f(q)/f(q + 1) + α + (1 α)µ 3 α = 1 + (1 α)µ 1 + (1 α)µ 2 f(q)/f(q 1) + (α + (1 α)µ 3 )f(q + 1)/f(q 1) α. (1 α)µ 1 f(q 1)/f(q + 1) + (1 α)µ 2 f(q)/f(q + 1) + α + (1 α)µ 3 By the MLRP property, both the second and the third term is increasing in q, and we conclude d Pr(Q=q θ=h) Pr(Q=q θ=l) dq > 0. Q.E.D. Now, upon observing r = H and Q = q, the shareholders will retain the manager if and only if E[θ Q = q, r = H] 0 Pr(θ = H Q = q, r = H)V Pr(θ = L Q = q, r = H)V 0 Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = H) + β Pr(Q = q θ = L) V β Pr(Q = q θ = L) Pr(Q = q θ = H) + β Pr(Q = q θ = L) V 0 Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = L) β From the proof of lemma 2 we know Pr(Q = q θ = H) lim q 0 Pr(Q = q θ = L) = 1 lim q Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = L) = (1 α)µ 3 α + (1 α)µ 3. Pr(Q=q θ=h) If lim q Pr(Q=q θ=l) < β, q (, 0] exists such that Pr(Q=q θ=h) Pr(Q=q θ=l) β if and only if q q. The following equation determines the cut-off q : Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = L) = β. (1) If lim q Pr(Q=q θ=h) Pr(Q=q θ=l) β, the manager will always be retained, which means q =. Besides, by lemma 4, we know that when β = 1, only q = 0 satisfies (1). Q.E.D. 24

25 A.2 proof of lemma 2 Suppose that in equilibrium, the uninformed speculator buys, doesn t trade, and short sells with probability µ 1, µ 2, and µ 3, respectively. The goal is to show µ 3 = 0. I use proof by contradiction. Suppose otherwise that µ 3 > 0, then the uninformed speculator s profit from buying is π d=1 = = V V + q + (E[θ r = H] E[θ Q = q, r = H])f(q 1)dq 1 Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) f(q 1)dq q Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L)/β + β + Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) f(q 1)dq. Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L)/β + β + Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) + 1 (2) + The last step is due to q 0 and Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) < 1 when q < 0. Now I decompose (2) into the following two components. RHS of (2) = V V Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) f(q 1)dq+ Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L)/β + β + Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) f(q 1)dq Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L)/β + β + Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) + 1 When q > 0, f(q 1) > f(q + 1). Therefore, the denominator in the first term is less than the denominator in the second term. Therefore, RHS of (2) < 0 and π d=1 RHS of (2) < 0, which is a contradiction because, by deviating to d = 0, the uninformed speculator can increase his profit to 0. Hence, we must have µ 3 = 0. Q.E.D. A.3 proof of proposition 2 A.3.1 step 1: preparation I use µ 1, µ 2 to denote the probability that the uninformed speculator plays d = 0 and d = 1. Therefore, in equilibrium, conditional on r = H, the probability that a type L manager will 25

26 be retained is (I use the notation γ) γ(q, µ 1, µ 2 ) = µ 1 (1 F (q )) + µ 2 ((1 α)(1 F (q + 1))) + α(1 F (q + 1)). (3) Further, I use π d= 1, π d=0 to denote the uninformed speculator s profit in the equilibrium if he plays d = 1 and d = 0, respectively. Note π d=0 = 0. Lemma 4 (1) Any pure strategy equilibrium with interior earnings management level β is determined by the following conditions: cβ = γ(q, µ 1, µ 2 ), Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = L) = β, µ 1 = 1 if π d=0 = 0 π d= 1, and µ 2 = 1 if π d= 1 π d=0 = 0. (2) Any mixed-strategy equilibrium with interior earnings management level β is determined by the following conditions: cβ = γ(q, µ 1, µ 2 ), Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = L) = β, and µ 1 = µ 2 > 0 if π d=0 = π d= 1 = 0. Proof: Type L manager s problem is max β βγ(ˆq) 1 2 cβ2 FOC cβ = γ(ˆq, µ 1, µ 2 ), where ˆq is the manager s guess of q. Applying the equilibrium condition q = ˆq, the FOC becomes cβ = γ(q, µ 1, µ 2 ). (4) 26

27 In addition, the threshold level q is determined by Pr(Q = q θ = H) Pr(Q = q θ = L) = β. (5) The equilibrium is thus determined by (4), (5), and the non-deviation conditions. Lemma 5 In any PBE, E[θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H] > 0 if and only if q > 0. Further, when q > 0, E[θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H] increases in β. Hence, when q > 0, we could write g(q, β) E[θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H] with g 1 > 0 and g 2 > 0. Proof: To start, note Pr(Q = q θ = H) E[θ Q = q, r = H] = Pr(Q = q θ = H) + β Pr(Q = q θ = L) V β Pr(Q = q θ = L) Pr(Q = q θ = H) + β Pr(Q = q θ = L) V = Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) + β V β Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) + β V. Hence, E[θ Q = q, r = H] increases in Pr(Q=q θ=h) Pr(Q=q θ=l), which increases in q by lemma 3. As a result, E[θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H] increases in q. Because when q = 0, Pr(Q=q θ=h) Pr(Q=q θ=l) = 1 and E[θ Q = q, r = H] = 1 β 1+β V = E[θ r = H]. Therefore, E[θ Q = q, r = H] > E[θ r = H] if and only of q > 0. It remains to show E[θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H] increases in β when q > 0. Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) β E[θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H] = Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) + β V 1 β 1 + β V. β(pr(q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) 1) = (Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) + β)(1 + β) Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) 1 = Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L)/β + β + Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) + 1. When q > 0, Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L) > 1 and that Pr(Q = q θ = H)/ Pr(Q = q θ = L)/β + β decreases in β. Therefore, E[θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H] increases in β when q > 0. This completes the proof of lemma 6. Lemma 6 Let c 0 = γ(0, 0, 1) = 1 F (1). If c c 0, β = 1, then µ 1 = 0 and µ 2 = 1. 27

28 Proof: Use proof by contradiction. Suppose otherwise that β < 1. Then cβ c 0 β < c 0 = 1 F (1) γ(q, µ 1, µ 2 ), which suggests the marginal benefit of earnings management exceeds the marginal cost. Therefore, β = 1, which is a contradiction. Hence we must have β = 1 and q = 0. By lemma 4, when q = 0, the uninformed speculator earns a strictly positive profit from short selling. If he does not trade, he earns zero. If he buys, he makes a strictly negative profit. Hence he must short sell with probability 1. Lemma 7 δ > 0 exists such that when c (c 0, c 0 + δ), the equilibrium β, µ 1, and µ 2 are all functions of c. We could thus write β = β(c), µ 1 = µ 1 (c), µ 2 = µ 2 (c), and they are all continuous functions. Proof: The implicit function theorem. A.3.2 step 2: the uninformed speculator short sells with probability 1 Suppose otherwise that the uninformed speculator does not trade with strictly positive probability. Let s consider the deviation from no trading to short selling. By making this deviation, the uninformed speculator s profit is: π d= 1 = = + q = (E d=0 [θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H])f(q + 1)dq q (E d=0 [θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H])f(q + 1)dq+ (E d=0 [θ Q = q, r = H] E[θ r = H])f(q + 1)dq q (g(q, β))f(q + 1)dq (g(q, β))f(q + 1)dq. Now, because lim c c0 β = 1, we know for any ɛ 1 > 0, δ 1 > 0 exists such that when c (c 0, c 0 + δ 1 ), β > 1 ɛ 1. By lemma 5, the integrand in the second integral is always positive 28

29 and takes its smallest value when β = 1 ɛ 1. That is, when q > 0, g(q, β) g(q, 1 ɛ 1 ) > 0. Therefore, we know + 0 g(q, β)f(q + 1)dq + 0 g(q, 1 ɛ 1 )f(q + 1)dq M 2. We know when c c 0, β 1 and q 0. Hence, for ɛ (0, 1), δ 2 > 0 exists such that c 0 < c < c 0 + δ 2 implies 0 Now for c 0 < c < c 0 + δ 2, we have π d= 1 > q (E[θ r = H] E(θ Q = q, r = H))f(q + 1)dq ɛm 2. 0 q (E[θ r = H] E(θ Q = q, r = H))f(q + 1)dq + M q (E[θ r = H] E(θ Q = q, r = H))f(q + 1)dq + ɛm 2 Take c = min(c 0 + δ, c 0 + δ 1, c 0 + δ 2 ). We know when c (c 0, c ), short selling guarantees strictly positive expected profit for the uninformed speculator. He will thus deviate to short selling with probability 1 and this completes step 2. Q.E.D. A.4 proof of proposition 3 By proposition 2, when κ = 0 and when c (c 0, c ), the uninformed speculator short sells with probability 1. Let κ 1 = + 0 V f(q + 1)dq. In any equilibrium, the uninformed speculator s profit from short-selling is: π s= + d= 1 = (E(θ Q = q, r = H) E[θ r = H])f(q + 1)dq < q (E(θ Q = q, r = H) E[θ r = H])f(q + 1)dq V f(q + 1)dq = κ. 29

30 Hence when κ = κ 1, the uninformed speculator will not short sell. Besides, for the negatively informed speculator, his profit from short selling is + d= 1 = (E(θ Q = q, r = H) + V )f(q + 1)dq π s=l > q (E(θ Q = q, r = H) + V )f(q + 1)dq V f(q + 1)dq = κ. Therefore, when κ = κ 1 the negatively informed speculator still short sells with probability 1. Finally, let κ 2 = 2V. It can be easily seen that when κ κ 2, both the uninformed and the negatively informed speculator play d = 0. A.5 proof of proposition 4 I use q 1 and q 2 to denote the equilibrium threshold q in the BSS and the BSN equilibrium, respectively. If β is exogenous, then by equation (1), q 1 and q 2 are determined by α f(q 1 1) + (1 α) = β. f(q 1 + 1) (6) αf(q 2 1) + (1 α)f(q 2 ) = β. αf(q 2 + 1) + (1 α)f(q 2 ) (7) I use v 1 (q) and v 2 (q) to denote the ex-ante firm value as a function of the threshold q, under the BSS and the BSN, respectively. We have v 1 (q) = 1 2 V ((1 α)(1 F (q + 1)) + α(1 F (q 1))) 1 }{{} 2 V β(1 F (q + 1)) }{{} the probability that the good manager is retained the probability that the bad manager is retained (8) v 2 (q) = 1 2 V ((1 α)(1 F (q )) + α(1 F (q 1))) 1 }{{} 2 V β((1 α)(1 F (q )) + α(1 F (q + 1))). }{{} the probability that the good manager is retained the probability that the bad manager is retained (9) I want to show v 2 (q 2 ) v 1 (q 1 ). I first prove a lemma. Lemma 8 v 1 (q 1 ) v 2 (q 2 ), v 2 (q 2 ) v 1 (q 1 ). 30

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure Feedback Effect and Capital Structure Minh Vo Metropolitan State University Abstract This paper develops a model of financing with informational feedback effect that jointly determines a firm s capital

More information

Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness

Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness James Dow Itay Goldstein Alexander Guembel London Business University of University of Oxford School Pennsylvania European Central Bank, 15-16 May, 2006

More information

Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Financial Fragility and Coordination Failures What makes financial systems fragile? What causes crises

More information

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Shingo Ishiguro Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University 1-7 Machikaneyama, Toyonaka, Osaka 560-0043, Japan August 2002

More information

PROBLEM SET 6 ANSWERS

PROBLEM SET 6 ANSWERS PROBLEM SET 6 ANSWERS 6 November 2006. Problems.,.4,.6, 3.... Is Lower Ability Better? Change Education I so that the two possible worker abilities are a {, 4}. (a) What are the equilibria of this game?

More information

The Effect of Speculative Monitoring on Shareholder Activism

The Effect of Speculative Monitoring on Shareholder Activism The Effect of Speculative Monitoring on Shareholder Activism Günter Strobl April 13, 016 Preliminary Draft. Please do not circulate. Abstract This paper investigates how informed trading in financial markets

More information

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders Michael Ostrovsky Setup n risk-neutral players, i = 1,..., n Finite set of states of the world Ω Random variable ( security ) X : Ω R Each

More information

Bid-Ask Spreads and Volume: The Role of Trade Timing

Bid-Ask Spreads and Volume: The Role of Trade Timing Bid-Ask Spreads and Volume: The Role of Trade Timing Toronto, Northern Finance 2007 Andreas Park University of Toronto October 3, 2007 Andreas Park (UofT) The Timing of Trades October 3, 2007 1 / 25 Patterns

More information

Financial Market Feedback and Disclosure

Financial Market Feedback and Disclosure Financial Market Feedback and Disclosure Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Information in prices A basic premise in financial economics: market prices are very informative about

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

Optimal Disclosure and Fight for Attention

Optimal Disclosure and Fight for Attention Optimal Disclosure and Fight for Attention January 28, 2018 Abstract In this paper, firm managers use their disclosure policy to direct speculators scarce attention towards their firm. More attention implies

More information

Evaluating Strategic Forecasters. Rahul Deb with Mallesh Pai (Rice) and Maher Said (NYU Stern) Becker Friedman Theory Conference III July 22, 2017

Evaluating Strategic Forecasters. Rahul Deb with Mallesh Pai (Rice) and Maher Said (NYU Stern) Becker Friedman Theory Conference III July 22, 2017 Evaluating Strategic Forecasters Rahul Deb with Mallesh Pai (Rice) and Maher Said (NYU Stern) Becker Friedman Theory Conference III July 22, 2017 Motivation Forecasters are sought after in a variety of

More information

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard December 5, 2012 Question 1 (Comparative Performance Evaluation) Consider the same normal linear model as in Question 1 of Homework 1. This time the principal employs

More information

Manipulation, Panic Runs, and the Short Selling Ban

Manipulation, Panic Runs, and the Short Selling Ban Manipulation, Panic Runs, and the Short Selling Ban Pingyang Gao Booth School of Business The University of Chicago pingyang.gao@chicagobooth.edu Xu Jiang Fuua School of Business Duke University xu.jiang@duke.edu

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH http://www.kier.kyoto-u.ac.jp/index.html Discussion Paper No. 657 The Buy Price in Auctions with Discrete Type Distributions Yusuke Inami

More information

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games CPSC 532l Lecture 10 Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games CPSC 532l Lecture 10, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Stochastic Games 3 Bayesian Games 4 Analyzing Bayesian

More information

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms On Existence of Equilibria in Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms Northwestern University April 23, 2014 Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms In allocation mechanisms, agents choose messages. The messages determine

More information

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome.

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome. AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED Alex Gershkov and Flavio Toxvaerd November 2004. Preliminary, comments welcome. Abstract. This paper revisits recent empirical research on buyer credulity

More information

(Some theoretical aspects of) Corporate Finance

(Some theoretical aspects of) Corporate Finance (Some theoretical aspects of) Corporate Finance V. Filipe Martins-da-Rocha Department of Economics UC Davis Part 6. Lending Relationships and Investor Activism V. F. Martins-da-Rocha (UC Davis) Corporate

More information

Auditing in the Presence of Outside Sources of Information

Auditing in the Presence of Outside Sources of Information Journal of Accounting Research Vol. 39 No. 3 December 2001 Printed in U.S.A. Auditing in the Presence of Outside Sources of Information MARK BAGNOLI, MARK PENNO, AND SUSAN G. WATTS Received 29 December

More information

Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment

Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment Suehyun Kwon CESIFO WORKING PAPER NO. 6280 CATEGORY 12: EMPIRICAL AND THEORETICAL METHODS DECEMBER 2016 An electronic version of the paper may be downloaded

More information

Information and Evidence in Bargaining

Information and Evidence in Bargaining Information and Evidence in Bargaining Péter Eső Department of Economics, University of Oxford peter.eso@economics.ox.ac.uk Chris Wallace Department of Economics, University of Leicester cw255@leicester.ac.uk

More information

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions? March 3, 215 Steven A. Matthews, A Technical Primer on Auction Theory I: Independent Private Values, Northwestern University CMSEMS Discussion Paper No. 196, May, 1995. This paper is posted on the course

More information

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University \ins\liab\liabinfo.v3d 12-05-08 Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas December

More information

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009. Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Do not forget to write Problems 1 and 2 in the first Blue Book and Problems 3 and 4 in the second Blue Book. 1 Econ 101A

More information

Credit Rating Inflation and Firms Investments

Credit Rating Inflation and Firms Investments Credit Rating Inflation and Firms Investments Itay Goldstein 1 and Chong Huang 2 1 Wharton, UPenn 2 Paul Merage School, UCI June 13, 2017 Goldstein and Huang CRA June 13, 2017 1 / 32 Credit Rating Inflation

More information

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring Holmstrom and Tirole (JPE, 1993) The main idea A firm would like to issue shares in the capital market because once these shares are publicly traded, speculators

More information

STOCHASTIC REPUTATION DYNAMICS UNDER DUOPOLY COMPETITION

STOCHASTIC REPUTATION DYNAMICS UNDER DUOPOLY COMPETITION STOCHASTIC REPUTATION DYNAMICS UNDER DUOPOLY COMPETITION BINGCHAO HUANGFU Abstract This paper studies a dynamic duopoly model of reputation-building in which reputations are treated as capital stocks that

More information

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam Summer 2018 Microeconomics Qualifying Exam There are 100 points possible on this exam, 50 points each for Prof. Lozada s questions and Prof. Dugar s questions. Each professor asks you to do two long questions

More information

PhD Qualifier Examination

PhD Qualifier Examination PhD Qualifier Examination Department of Agricultural Economics May 29, 2015 Instructions This exam consists of six questions. You must answer all questions. If you need an assumption to complete a question,

More information

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion Davit Khantadze September 30, 017 Abstract We are interested in optimal signals for the sender when the decision maker (receiver) has to make two separate decisions.

More information

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Corporate Control Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Managerial Discipline and Takeovers Managers often don t maximize the value of the firm; either because they are not capable

More information

Accounting Conservatism, Market Liquidity and Informativeness of Asset Price: Implications on Mark to Market Accounting

Accounting Conservatism, Market Liquidity and Informativeness of Asset Price: Implications on Mark to Market Accounting Journal of Applied Finance & Banking, vol.3, no.1, 2013, 177-190 ISSN: 1792-6580 (print version), 1792-6599 (online) Scienpress Ltd Accounting Conservatism, Market Liquidity and Informativeness of Asset

More information

ISSN BWPEF Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions. Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University of London.

ISSN BWPEF Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions. Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University of London. ISSN 1745-8587 Birkbeck Working Papers in Economics & Finance School of Economics, Mathematics and Statistics BWPEF 0701 Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University

More information

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium Let us consider the following sequential game with incomplete information. Two players are playing

More information

Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market. Jeffrey Gao

Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market. Jeffrey Gao Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market Jeffrey Gao ABSTRACT This paper extends a model of herd behavior developed by Bikhchandani and Sharma (000) to establish conditions for varying levels

More information

Loss-leader pricing and upgrades

Loss-leader pricing and upgrades Loss-leader pricing and upgrades Younghwan In and Julian Wright This version: August 2013 Abstract A new theory of loss-leader pricing is provided in which firms advertise low below cost) prices for certain

More information

Feedback E ects and the Limits to Arbitrage

Feedback E ects and the Limits to Arbitrage Feedback E ects and the Limits to Arbitrage Alex Edmans Wharton and NBER Itay Goldstein Wharton May 3, 0 Wei Jiang Columbia Abstract This paper identi es a limit to arbitrage that arises from the fact

More information

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition Kai Hao Yang /2/207 In this lecture, we will apply the concepts in game theory to study oligopoly. In short, unlike

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE Answers to Problem Set 2 [1] (a) This is standard (we have even done it in class). The one-shot Cournot outputs can be computed to be A/3, while the payoff to each firm can

More information

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Research Department Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Harold L. Cole and Narayana Kocherlakota Working Paper 604 September 2000 Cole: U.C.L.A. and Federal Reserve

More information

Strategic Information Revelation and Capital Allocation

Strategic Information Revelation and Capital Allocation Strategic Information Revelation and Capital Allocation ALVARO PEDRAZA University of Maryland THIS VERSION: November 8, 2013 Abstract It is commonly believed that stock prices help firms managers make

More information

BEAR RAIDS AND SHORT SALE BANS: IS GOVERNMENT INTERVENTION JUSTIFIABLE? Naveen Khanna and Richmond D. Mathews. October 30, 2009

BEAR RAIDS AND SHORT SALE BANS: IS GOVERNMENT INTERVENTION JUSTIFIABLE? Naveen Khanna and Richmond D. Mathews. October 30, 2009 BEAR RAIDS AND SHORT SALE BANS: IS GOVERNMENT INTERVENTION JUSTIFIABLE? Naveen Khanna and Richmond D. Mathews October 30, 2009 Abstract. If managers, creditors, or other firm counterparties use stock prices

More information

Bernanke and Gertler [1989]

Bernanke and Gertler [1989] Bernanke and Gertler [1989] Econ 235, Spring 2013 1 Background: Townsend [1979] An entrepreneur requires x to produce output y f with Ey > x but does not have money, so he needs a lender Once y is realized,

More information

Can Stock Price Manipulation be Prevented by Granting More Freedom to Manipulators

Can Stock Price Manipulation be Prevented by Granting More Freedom to Manipulators International Journal of Economics and Finance; Vol. 7, No. 3; 205 ISSN 96-97X E-ISSN 96-9728 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education Can Stock Price Manipulation be Prevented by Granting

More information

Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness

Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness PRELIMINARY DRAFT Comments welcome James Dow Itay Goldstein London Business School Wharton School University of Pennsylvania Alexander Guembel Said Business

More information

Lecture 3: Information in Sequential Screening

Lecture 3: Information in Sequential Screening Lecture 3: Information in Sequential Screening NMI Workshop, ISI Delhi August 3, 2015 Motivation A seller wants to sell an object to a prospective buyer(s). Buyer has imperfect private information θ about

More information

Leader or Follower? A Payoff Analysis in Quadratic Utility Harsanyi Economy

Leader or Follower? A Payoff Analysis in Quadratic Utility Harsanyi Economy Leader or Follower? A Payoff Analysis in Quadratic Utility Harsanyi Economy Sai Ma New York University Oct. 0, 015 Model Agents and Belief There are two players, called agent i {1, }. Each agent i chooses

More information

Homework 3: Asymmetric Information

Homework 3: Asymmetric Information Homework 3: Asymmetric Information 1. Public Goods Provision A firm is considering building a public good (e.g. a swimming pool). There are n agents in the economy, each with IID private value θ i [0,

More information

Corporate Strategy, Conformism, and the Stock Market

Corporate Strategy, Conformism, and the Stock Market Corporate Strategy, Conformism, and the Stock Market Thierry Foucault (HEC) Laurent Frésard (Maryland) November 20, 2015 Corporate Strategy, Conformism, and the Stock Market Thierry Foucault (HEC) Laurent

More information

A Theory of Asset Prices based on Heterogeneous Information and Limits to Arbitrage

A Theory of Asset Prices based on Heterogeneous Information and Limits to Arbitrage A Theory of Asset Prices based on Heterogeneous Information and Limits to Arbitrage Elias Albagli USC Marhsall Christian Hellwig Toulouse School of Economics Aleh Tsyvinski Yale University September 20,

More information

Internet Appendix for Back-Running: Seeking and Hiding Fundamental Information in Order Flows

Internet Appendix for Back-Running: Seeking and Hiding Fundamental Information in Order Flows Internet Appendix for Back-Running: Seeking and Hiding Fundamental Information in Order Flows Liyan Yang Haoxiang Zhu July 4, 017 In Yang and Zhu (017), we have taken the information of the fundamental

More information

Persuasion in Global Games with Application to Stress Testing. Supplement

Persuasion in Global Games with Application to Stress Testing. Supplement Persuasion in Global Games with Application to Stress Testing Supplement Nicolas Inostroza Northwestern University Alessandro Pavan Northwestern University and CEPR January 24, 208 Abstract This document

More information

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions.

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B eb Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B.1 Proofs of results about block correlated markets. This subsection provides proofs for Propositions A1, A2, A3 and A4, and the proof of Lemma A1. Proof of Proposition

More information

A Theory of Endogenous Liquidity Cycles

A Theory of Endogenous Liquidity Cycles A Theory of Endogenous Günter Strobl Kenan-Flagler Business School University of North Carolina October 2010 Liquidity and the Business Cycle Source: Næs, Skjeltorp, and Ødegaard (Journal of Finance, forthcoming)

More information

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty Braz Camargo Dino Gerardi Lucas Maestri December 2015 Abstract We study efficiency in decentralized markets with aggregate uncertainty and

More information

An optimal board system : supervisory board vs. management board

An optimal board system : supervisory board vs. management board An optimal board system : supervisory board vs. management board Tomohiko Yano Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo January 10, 2006 Abstract We examine relative effectiveness of two kinds

More information

In Diamond-Dybvig, we see run equilibria in the optimal simple contract.

In Diamond-Dybvig, we see run equilibria in the optimal simple contract. Ennis and Keister, "Run equilibria in the Green-Lin model of financial intermediation" Journal of Economic Theory 2009 In Diamond-Dybvig, we see run equilibria in the optimal simple contract. When the

More information

Where do securities come from

Where do securities come from Where do securities come from We view it as natural to trade common stocks WHY? Coase s policemen Pricing Assumptions on market trading? Predictions? Partial Equilibrium or GE economies (risk spanning)

More information

The Effects of The Target s Learning on M&A Negotiations

The Effects of The Target s Learning on M&A Negotiations The Effects of The Target s Learning on M&A Negotiations Chong Huang 1 and Qiguang Wang 1 1 University of California, Irvine October 20, 2013 Abstract This paper studies the role of the target s learning

More information

Market Size Matters: A Model of Excess Volatility in Large Markets

Market Size Matters: A Model of Excess Volatility in Large Markets Market Size Matters: A Model of Excess Volatility in Large Markets Kei Kawakami March 9th, 2015 Abstract We present a model of excess volatility based on speculation and equilibrium multiplicity. Each

More information

Homework 3. Due: Mon 9th December

Homework 3. Due: Mon 9th December Homework 3 Due: Mon 9th December 1. Public Goods Provision A firm is considering building a public good (e.g. a swimming pool). There are n agents in the economy, each with IID private value θ i [0, 1].

More information

Haiyang Feng College of Management and Economics, Tianjin University, Tianjin , CHINA

Haiyang Feng College of Management and Economics, Tianjin University, Tianjin , CHINA RESEARCH ARTICLE QUALITY, PRICING, AND RELEASE TIME: OPTIMAL MARKET ENTRY STRATEGY FOR SOFTWARE-AS-A-SERVICE VENDORS Haiyang Feng College of Management and Economics, Tianjin University, Tianjin 300072,

More information

Financial Market Feedback:

Financial Market Feedback: Financial Market Feedback: New Perspective from Commodities Financialization Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Information in prices A basic premise in financial economics: market

More information

Online Appendix for "Optimal Liability when Consumers Mispredict Product Usage" by Andrzej Baniak and Peter Grajzl Appendix B

Online Appendix for Optimal Liability when Consumers Mispredict Product Usage by Andrzej Baniak and Peter Grajzl Appendix B Online Appendix for "Optimal Liability when Consumers Mispredict Product Usage" by Andrzej Baniak and Peter Grajzl Appendix B In this appendix, we first characterize the negligence regime when the due

More information

Doing Battle with Short Sellers: The Role of Blockholders in Bear Raids. Naveen Khanna and Richmond D. Mathews. September 24, 2010

Doing Battle with Short Sellers: The Role of Blockholders in Bear Raids. Naveen Khanna and Richmond D. Mathews. September 24, 2010 Doing Battle with Short Sellers: The Role of Blockholders in Bear Raids Naveen Khanna and Richmond D. Mathews September 24, 2010 Abstract. If short sellers can destroy firm value by manipulating prices

More information

COUNTRY RISK AND CAPITAL FLOW REVERSALS by: Assaf Razin 1 and Efraim Sadka 2

COUNTRY RISK AND CAPITAL FLOW REVERSALS by: Assaf Razin 1 and Efraim Sadka 2 COUNTRY RISK AND CAPITAL FLOW REVERSALS by: Assaf Razin 1 and Efraim Sadka 2 1 Introduction A remarkable feature of the 1997 crisis of the emerging economies in South and South-East Asia is the lack of

More information

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models IEOR E4707: Foundations of Financial Engineering c 206 by Martin Haugh Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models These notes develop the theory of martingale pricing in a discrete-time,

More information

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions Microeconomics: Pricing 3E00 Fall 06. True or false: Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions (a) Since a durable goods monopolist prices at the monopoly price in her last period of operation, the prices must

More information

working paper 1717 Early Birds and Second Mice in the Stock Market Julio A. Crego Jin Huang November 2017

working paper 1717 Early Birds and Second Mice in the Stock Market Julio A. Crego Jin Huang November 2017 working paper 77 Early Birds and Second Mice in the Stock Market Julio A. Crego Jin Huang November 207 CENTRO DE ESTUDIOS MONETARIOS Y FINANCIEROS Casado del Alisal 5, 2804 Madrid, Spain www.cemfi.es CEMFI

More information

Aggressive Corporate Tax Behavior versus Decreasing Probability of Fiscal Control (Preliminary and incomplete)

Aggressive Corporate Tax Behavior versus Decreasing Probability of Fiscal Control (Preliminary and incomplete) Aggressive Corporate Tax Behavior versus Decreasing Probability of Fiscal Control (Preliminary and incomplete) Cristian M. Litan Sorina C. Vâju October 29, 2007 Abstract We provide a model of strategic

More information

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02 Topic 5: Information Economics 21, Summer 2002 Andreas Bentz Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02 Introduction

More information

Dynamic signaling and market breakdown

Dynamic signaling and market breakdown Journal of Economic Theory ( ) www.elsevier.com/locate/jet Dynamic signaling and market breakdown Ilan Kremer, Andrzej Skrzypacz Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305, USA

More information

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2013 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Making Money out of Publicly Available Information

Making Money out of Publicly Available Information Making Money out of Publicly Available Information Forthcoming, Economics Letters Alan D. Morrison Saïd Business School, University of Oxford and CEPR Nir Vulkan Saïd Business School, University of Oxford

More information

Problems with seniority based pay and possible solutions. Difficulties that arise and how to incentivize firm and worker towards the right incentives

Problems with seniority based pay and possible solutions. Difficulties that arise and how to incentivize firm and worker towards the right incentives Problems with seniority based pay and possible solutions Difficulties that arise and how to incentivize firm and worker towards the right incentives Master s Thesis Laurens Lennard Schiebroek Student number:

More information

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria and Rational Expectations Equilibria 1 Basic Setup Two periods: 0 and 1 One riskless asset with interest rate r One risky asset which pays a normally distributed

More information

Estimating Market Power in Differentiated Product Markets

Estimating Market Power in Differentiated Product Markets Estimating Market Power in Differentiated Product Markets Metin Cakir Purdue University December 6, 2010 Metin Cakir (Purdue) Market Equilibrium Models December 6, 2010 1 / 28 Outline Outline Estimating

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 017 1. Sheila moves first and chooses either H or L. Bruce receives a signal, h or l, about Sheila s behavior. The distribution

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Leonardo Felli 9 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Consider now a different cause for the failure of the Coase Theorem: the presence of transaction costs. Of course for this to be an interesting

More information

Sequential Financial Market Trading: The Role of Endogenous Timing

Sequential Financial Market Trading: The Role of Endogenous Timing Sequential Financial Market Trading: The Role of Endogenous Timing Andreas Park University of Toronto July 2004 Abstract The paper analyses a simplified version of a Glosten-Milgrom style specialist security

More information

New product launch: herd seeking or herd. preventing?

New product launch: herd seeking or herd. preventing? New product launch: herd seeking or herd preventing? Ting Liu and Pasquale Schiraldi December 29, 2008 Abstract A decision maker offers a new product to a fixed number of adopters. The decision maker does

More information

Sabotage in Teams. Matthias Kräkel. University of Bonn. Daniel Müller 1. University of Bonn

Sabotage in Teams. Matthias Kräkel. University of Bonn. Daniel Müller 1. University of Bonn Sabotage in Teams Matthias Kräkel University of Bonn Daniel Müller 1 University of Bonn Abstract We show that a team may favor self-sabotage to influence the principal s contract decision. Sabotage increases

More information

Global Games and Financial Fragility:

Global Games and Financial Fragility: Global Games and Financial Fragility: Foundations and a Recent Application Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Outline Part I: The introduction of global games into the analysis of

More information

Counterfeiting substitute media-of-exchange: a threat to monetary systems

Counterfeiting substitute media-of-exchange: a threat to monetary systems Counterfeiting substitute media-of-exchange: a threat to monetary systems Tai-Wei Hu Penn State University June 2008 Abstract One justification for cash-in-advance equilibria is the assumption that the

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

All Equilibrium Revenues in Buy Price Auctions

All Equilibrium Revenues in Buy Price Auctions All Equilibrium Revenues in Buy Price Auctions Yusuke Inami Graduate School of Economics, Kyoto University This version: January 009 Abstract This note considers second-price, sealed-bid auctions with

More information

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk Kenneth Mirkin and Marek Pycia June 2015. Preliminary Draft. Abstract We study directed search in a frictional two-sided matching market in which each seller

More information

Strategic trading against retail investors with disposition effects

Strategic trading against retail investors with disposition effects University of New Orleans ScholarWorks@UNO Department of Economics and Finance Working Papers, 1991-2006 Department of Economics and Finance 1-1-2004 Strategic trading against retail investors with disposition

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, MsC Economics List of Problems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market Meng-Wei Chen Department of Economics, Indiana University at Bloomington April 21, 2011 Abstract This paper studies the information transmission

More information

Contagious Adverse Selection

Contagious Adverse Selection Stephen Morris and Hyun Song Shin European University Institute, Florence 17 March 2011 Credit Crisis of 2007-2009 A key element: some liquid markets shut down Market Con dence I We had it I We lost it

More information

Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix

Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix Barney Hartman-Glaser September 1, 2016 Appendix D. Non-Markov Perfect Equilibrium In this appendix, I consider the game when there is no honest-type

More information

Up till now, we ve mostly been analyzing auctions under the following assumptions:

Up till now, we ve mostly been analyzing auctions under the following assumptions: Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2007 Lecture 7 Sept 27 2007 Tuesday: Amit Gandhi on empirical auction stuff p till now, we ve mostly been analyzing auctions under the following assumptions:

More information

Strategic Information Revelation and Capital Allocation

Strategic Information Revelation and Capital Allocation Policy Research Working Paper 6995 WPS6995 Strategic Information Revelation and Capital Allocation Alvaro Pedraza Morales Public Disclosure Authorized Public Disclosure Authorized Public Disclosure Authorized

More information

Auctions in the wild: Bidding with securities. Abhay Aneja & Laura Boudreau PHDBA 279B 1/30/14

Auctions in the wild: Bidding with securities. Abhay Aneja & Laura Boudreau PHDBA 279B 1/30/14 Auctions in the wild: Bidding with securities Abhay Aneja & Laura Boudreau PHDBA 279B 1/30/14 Structure of presentation Brief introduction to auction theory First- and second-price auctions Revenue Equivalence

More information

Credible Ratings. University of Toronto. From the SelectedWorks of hao li

Credible Ratings. University of Toronto. From the SelectedWorks of hao li University of Toronto From the SelectedWorks of hao li 2008 Credible Ratings ettore damiano, University of Toronto hao li, University of Toronto wing suen Available at: https://works.bepress.com/hao_li/15/

More information

Market Manipulation with Outside Incentives

Market Manipulation with Outside Incentives Market Manipulation with Outside Incentives Yiling Chen Harvard SEAS yiling@eecs.harvard.edu Xi Alice Gao Harvard SEAS xagao@seas.harvard.edu Rick Goldstein Harvard SEAS rgoldst@fas.harvard.edu Ian A.

More information