Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I"

Transcription

1 Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I Solutions to Homework 1. (A Strategic Role of Futures Contracts) Consider example 1 in Lecture 1, part I, where firms 1 and can costlessly produce a product and engage in Cournot competition with the inverse demand being, in the relevant range, P (q 1 + q ) = 1 q 1 q. This problem is a modification of the above Cournot game. (i) Assume that there are two dates. The two firms will compete at date 1, but at date 0, both firms can correctly expect the date-1 inverse demand function, which is the P ( ) defined above. At date 0, the futures market opens for the product produced by the two firms. There are price-competitive investors in the futures market, who, just like the two firms, are risk neutral without time preferences (that is, there will be no discounting for anyone). The extensive game is as follows. At date 0, (only) firm 1 can sign a futures contract with the competitive investors. In the futures contract, firm 1 promises to deliver f 1 units of the product at date 1 to one of the investors (say, Mr. A), and Mr. A promises to pay the price F (referred to as the date-0 futures price of the product). We assume that firm 1 announces f 1, and the competitive investors then determine the futures price F. Assume that investors have ratinal expectations; that is, upon seeing f 1, they can use backward induction to anticipate the date-1 price of the product (called the date-1 spot price of the product), and to rule out arbitrage opportunities, in the date- 0 equilibrium, F must equal the anticipated date-1 price P (q 1, q ) so that Mr. A would get zero profits from futures trading. At date 1, upon seeing firm 1 s date-0 futures contract (f 1, F ), the two firms choose q 1 and q simultaneously. Then, after firms set q 1 and q, firm 1 must deliver f 1 units of the product to Mr. A, and Mr. A must pay firm 1 F f 1 dollars. 1

2 Then, consumers arrive, and they purchase f 1 units of the product from Mr. A, q 1 f 1 units from firm 1, and q units from firm. Since consumers purchase q 1 + q units in total, the date-1 spot transaction price is P (q 1, q ). Mr. A s profit is then [P (q 1, q ) F ]f 1. Firm 1 s profit as a function of q 1, q is Π 1 (q 1, q ; f 1 ) = [1 q 1 q ][q 1 f 1 ] + F f 1. Firm s profit function is still Π (q 1, q ) = [1 q 1 q ]q. Find the SPNE of this extensive game. Explain why firm 1 may benefit from futures trading. 1 (ii) Now, suppose that both firms can engage in futures trading at date 0, with f 1 and f units sold respectively at the futures price F determined at date 0. Again, assume that all investors in the futures market have rational expectations when they compete in price to determine F. Re-derive the SPNE. Explain why the two firms might be hurt by the availability of futures trading. 1 Hint: Use backward induction. First consider the date-1 subgame with f 1 given. This is just a Cournot game with the two firms profit functions being Π 1 and Π specified above. Let the subgame equilibrium be (q 1(f 1 ), q (f 1 )), which depends on f 1. Now move backwards to consider firm 1 s date-0 choice of f 1. Remember that the investors in the futures market can rationally expect the date-1 spot price of the product, which is P ((q 1(f 1 ), q (f 1 )), and given f 1, they will compete in price so that in the date-0 futures market equilibrium, F = P ((q 1(f 1 ), q (f 1 )). Given that F = P ((q 1(f 1 ), q (f 1 )), find firm 1 s optimal f 1. Hint: Again, consider the date-1 subgame with f 1, f given. Now for i = 1,,, firm i s profit function becomes Π i (q i, q j ; f i ) = [1 q i q j ][q i f i ] + F f i. Find the Nash equilibrium (q1(f 1, f ), q(f 1, f ))for this subgame. Now return to the date-0 futures market, where the two firms must simultaneously choose f 1 and f. For each pair (f 1, f ) announced, the investors can correctly expect the date-1 spot price, which must be P ((q1(f 1, f ), q(f 1, f )). Knowing that the futures price will be such that F = P ((q1(f 1, f ), q(f 1, f )), the two firms choices (f 1, f ) must form a Nash equilibrium at date 0.

3 Solution. Consider part (i). It is straightforward to show that the two firms date-1 reaction functions are r 1 1(q ; f 1 ) = 1 + f 1 q Hence we have the subgame equilibrium, r(q 1 1 ) = 1 q. q 1(f 1 ) = f 1, q (f 1 ) = f 1. Now consider firm 1 s date-0 choice of f 1. Since F = P ((q 1(f 1 ), q (f 1 )) (a no-arbitrage condition!), at date 0 firm 1 seeks to max f 1 P ((q 1(f 1 ), q (f 1 ))q 1(f 1 ) = 1 3 (1 f 1)( f 1), for which the necessary and sufficient first-order condition gives implying that, in equilibrium, f 1 = 1 4, F = P = 1 4, q 1 = 1, q = 1 4, Π 1 = 1 8, Π = Next consider part (ii). Given (f 1, f ), now the subgame equilibrium becomes q 1(f 1, f ) = f f, q (f 1, f ) = f 1 3 f 1, P (f 1, f ) P (q 1(f 1, f ), q (f 1, f )) = 1 3 (1 f 1 f ). Now consider the date-0 futures market equilibrium. Firm i s problem is to, given the conjectured f j, max P (qi (f i, f j ), qj (f i, f j ))qi (f i, f j ) = 1 f i 3 (1 f i f j )( f i 1 3 f j). 3

4 The necessary and sufficient first-order condition gives firm i s date-0 reaction function Thus the date-0 equilibrium is implying that ri 0 (f j ) = 1 f j, i, j = 1,, i j. 4 f 1 = f = 1 5, q 1 = q = 5, F = P = 1 5, Π 1 = Π = 5. Remark. In part (i), firm 1 is better off with futures trading. The reason is that after commtting to sell f 1 units at a fixed price F, which will not fall when firm 1 expands output at date 1, firm 1 has an incentive to choose a higher total output at date 1. This fact results in firm lowering output accordingly (because output choices are strategic substitutes). In essense, firm 1 s selling futures contracts serves as a commitment that tells its rival that its reaction function is now shifted upwards. Consequently, firm 1 benefits from futures trading, which hurts firm at the same time. Compared to the Cournot equilibrium profit, however, both firms are worse off in part (ii). The reason is that, as in the game of prisoner s dilemma, here each firm intends to hold a short position in the futures contract as an attempt to force its rival to produce less. With the short positions in the futures contract, both firms are faced with a residual inverse demand with lower elasticity to their output expansion. Consequently, both firms choose to produce more in the subgame where futures contracts have been signed, leading to a lower spot and futures price for the product, and lower profit for each firm. 3. (A Strategic Role of Option Contracts) This exercise can be applied to joint ventures, but we shall consider a simpler interpretation. 3 This exercise is adapted from Biaise Allaz and Jean-Luc Vila, 1993, Cournot Competition, Forward Markets and Efficiency, Journal of Economic Theory, 59,

5 There are two players in this sequential game, a landlord (L) and a tenant (T). The landlord can first spend a [0, 1] to build a house, and then after the tenant moves in, the tenant can spend b [0, 1] to make improvements on the house. The resale value of the house is v(a, b) = a f + b h, where the constants f, h (0, 1). (Of course the landlord charges a rent from the tenant, say r, for renting the house for a given period, say a year, but this rental transaction has nothing to do with our main analysis and so we shall forget about it at this moment.) Let us call the social benefit, and the solution S(a, b) v(a, b) a b (a, b ) = arg max S(a, b) a,b [0,1] will be called the first-best investments. We shall assume that a, b can only be observed by the landlord and the tenant but not by the court of law (i.e., they are non-verifiable variables), and hence cannot be put into a legally binding contract. Moreover, S(a, b) is not verifiable either. 4 What L and T can do is to sign a contract to decide who owns the house. The timing of the game is as follows. The two first sign 4 We claim that if instead S(a, b) is verifiable, then there exists a simple sharing rule that gives L and T respectively the payoffs αs(a, b ) and (1 α)s(a, b ) for some α [0, 1], and that contract induces L and T to choose respectively a and b. To see this, recall that v(a, b) is verifiable, and if S(a, b) is verifiable also, then a + b must also be verifiable. Consider the following contract: If S(a, b) = S(a, b ), and if a + b = a + b also, then T would get a fraction (1 λ) of the proceeds v(a, b ) from selling the house, where λ satisfies both L s and T s individual rationality conditions; and in any other event regarding (a, b), both L and T would get nothing from the proceeds of selling the house (the entire v(a, b) would be donated to charity). Now, given λ, define α associated with this λ as such that (1 α)s(a, b ) + b = (1 λ)v(a, b ). Now, if L chooses any a a, then by the uniqueness of (a, b ), it is in T s interest to choose b = 0 rather than any b > 0 such that S(a, b ) = S(a, b ), as there is not other pair (a, b ) satisfying both a + b = a + b and S(a, b ) = S(a, b ). Thus by choosing some a a, S would get the payoff a. On the other hand, if L chooses a = a, then it is obviously in T s interest to choose b = b. Thus with the above contract, in equilibrium L and T get respectively αs(a, b ) and (1 α)s(a, b ). 5

6 an ownership contract, and then given the contract L first chooses a, and upon seeing a, T must choose b. Then the house is sold after the rental period, and the two people share the proceeds according to the ownership contract. (i) Compute a, b. Suppose first that a, b are contractible. Show that if L and T are both rational, they will put a = a, b = b in the contract. From now on, return to our initial assumption that a, b cannot be verified in the court of law, and hence L and T can only try to implement efficient a, b by choosing a smart ownership contract. (ii) Suppose that L owns the house exclusively (so that T cannot share a cent when the house is sold), determine the a, b and v(a, b) by backward induction. (iii) Suppose that before building the house, L sells the house to T by making a take-it-or-leave-it offering price q (so that L cannot share a cent when the house is sold). Determine the a, b and v(a, b) by backward induction. Find q. (iv) Suppose that before building the house, T agrees to pay L some money z to jointly own the house with L, and L and T will subsequently receive respectively λv(a, b) and (1 λ)v(a, b) when selling the house (where λ is exogenously given). Determine the a, b and v(a, b) by backward induction. Find z, assuming that L has all the bargaining power in determining z. (v) Finally, consider the following contingent ownership contract: L owns the house initially, and he gives an option for free (why for free?) to T, and the option allows T to buy the house at the exercise price p = v(a, b ) b after L chooses a but before T chooses b. Find the SPNE by backward induction. Determine the equilibrium a, b and 6

7 v(a, b). (vi) Explain why the contingent ownership contract attains the firstbest efficiency, while the other ownership contracts do not. (vii) Now suppose instead that after L chooses a but before T decides to or not to exercise the option, L can offer a new contract to T. (We call this re-contracting event a renegotiation. ) This new contract will replace the existing option contract if and only if both L and T agree to do so. The new contract states a (probably) different exercise price p that allows T to pay p to L and get the house before T chooses b. Find the equilibrium a and b chosen by L and T respectively. Solution. Consider part (i). The first-best investment levels (a, b ) must solve the following maximization problem max S(a, b) = v(a, b) a b = a f + b h a b. a,b The necessary and sufficient first-order conditions yield a = f 1/(1 f) and b = h 1/(1 h). Since rational people must sign a Pareto efficient contract, these will be L and T s choices if they can sign complete contracts. Consider part (ii). Obviously, T will choose b = 0 since he cannot share the proceeds from selling the house. Thus L seeks to max v(a, 0) a = a f a. a The solution is a = a. Hence when L owns the house exclusively, v(a, b) = v(a, 0) and L s payoff is S(a, 0) < S(a, b ). Consider part (iii). Suppose that T has already paid q to L before L chooses a. Then L will choose a = 0. Thus T seeks to max v(0, b) b = b h b, b 7

8 yielding b = b. Thus, the proceeds from selling the house will be v(0, b ). For T to be willing to pay q for the house in the first place, it must be that q v(0, b ) b. Thus L optimaly chooses q = v(0, b ) b. It follows that L s payoff is S(0, b ) < S(a, b ). Consider part (iv). Consider the subgame where T has already paid z to L for the right of jointly owning the house. Given that L has chosen a, T seeks to max b (1 λ)v(a, b) b = (1 λ)(a f + b h ) b. Thus T optimally chooses b = [(1 λ)h] 1/(1 h) b(λ). Rationally expecting T s behavior, in choosing a, L seeks to max a λv(a, b(λ)) a = λ{a f + [b(λ)] h } a. The solution is a = (λf) 1/(1 f) a(λ). The proceeds from selling the house will thus be v(a(λ), b(λ)). Thus T will accept z if and only if z (1 λ)v(a(λ), b(λ)) b(λ). Consequently, L will choose z = (1 λ)v(a(λ), b(λ)) b(λ), which yields for L the payoff S(a(λ), b(λ)). It is easy to see that S(a(λ), b(λ)) < S(a, b ). Consider part (v). If T does not exercise the option, then he must choose b = 0 because he does not get to share the proceeds from selling the house. If T exercises the option, then given any a he will choose b to max v(a, b) b = a f + b h b, b since he exclusively owns the house. Thus T will choose b = b after he exercises the option. Should T exercise the option? T knows that he will choose b = b if he exercises the option, and hence he chooses to exercise the option if and only if v(a, b ) b p = v(a, b ) b [v(a, b ) b ] 0 a a. The result is not surprising. The house value depends not only on b but also on a. From T s perspective, given the strike price, the house 8

9 is worth buying only if a is large enough. Indeed, the higher the strike price chosen by L, the higher a must be in order to induce T to exercise the option. By wisely setting p = v(a, b ) b, L knows that T will exercise the option if and only if L chooses some a a. Now, what is L s optimal choice about a? If L chooses some a < a, then T will not exercise the option, and T will subsequently choose b = 0, leading to the payoff S(a, 0) for L. If L chooses some a a, then T will exercise the option and L s payoff would become S(a, b ). Thus L s optimal choice is a = a, which generates for L the first-best payoff S(a, b ). An interesting question here is why L offers the option for free? In fact, regardless of the strike price chosen by L, T will refuse to pay anything for the option. Why? Note that after T obtains the option, L will choose some a that makes T feel indifferent between to and not to excercise the option. In other words, L will choose some a that ensures that T makes zero profits by exercising the option. Therefore, for any strike price chosen by L, T will attach zero value to the option. Consider part (vi). The above discussion shows that the first-best efficiency is attained in part (v) but not in parts (ii), (iii), or (iv). There is a free-rider problem in parts (ii), (iii) and (iv), which prevents the first-best efficiency from prevailing. On the other hand, in part (v), T s incentive to choose b can be ensured by making T the sole owner at the time the house is sold (or equivalently, making T the sole residual claimant). For L, on the other hand, by wisely choosing the strike price v(a, b ) b for the option, L can be induced to choose a = a. This explains how the first best efficiency is attained in part (v). Finally, consider part (vii). Note that in part (v), given the existing option contract T will not exercise the option if a < a, which is not efficient because b = 0 rather than b will then be chosen by T. We have assumed in part (v) that the existing option contract cannot be renegotiated, even though such inefficiency may exist. What if L and T can renegotiate the existing option contract? Does the opportunity of renegotiating an inefficient old contract undermine our result that option contracts can help attain the first-best efficiency? 9

10 Recall from part (v) that T will exercise the option if and only if v(a, b ) b p = v(a, b ) b [v(a, b ) b ] 0 a a. Now, if a new contract specifies a strike price p > p, T will never agree to replace the old contract p by this new contract p. Thus if L wants to offer a new contract to T, he must choose some p p. Suppose that L has already spent some a a. Since T is willing to exercise the option under old contract, L will optimally choose p = p in this case, so that contract renegotiation does not arise in this case. What if L has spent some a < a? To induce T to agree to replace the old contract p by this new contract p, it is necessary and sufficient that the new strike price p satisfies v(a, b ) b p 0. Hence from L s perspective the optimal p = v(a, b ) b. Therefore, if L has chosen some a < a, he will offer a new contract that yields for L the payoff v(a, b ) b a = S(a, b ). It follows that L should optimally choose a = a! Our conclusion is that, allowing renegotiation does not change our main result that option contracts can help resolve the free-rider problem and attain the first-best efficiency. Remark. As we explained in part (vi), the free-rider problem in parts (ii), (iii) and (iv) that prevents the first-best efficiency from prevailing is removed in part (v), where T has the correct incentive to choose b because T is the residual claimant) when choosing b and the wisely chosen strike price v(a, b ) b induces L to optimally choose a = a. The problem with this wisely designed contract is that it leads to b = 0 even if a is only slightly lower than a, an outcome which is not productive efficient. Thus subgame perfection implies that L and T may wish to replace this contract by a new one as a remedy, if it did happen that somehow L has chosen a < a. By giving L full bargaining power in contract renegotiation, we show that (a, b ) are still the two players equilibrium choices, even if they are allowed to replace an old contract by a new one after a is chosen. The idea here is that L knows that he will get all the surplus (and T 10

11 will get zero surplus) generated from the replacement of p by p, given that he has all the bargaining power against T in the regenotiation subgame, and for this reason L should choose a to maximize the social benefit (given that, by backward induction, T will always choose b after T agrees to exercise the new option under the price p ). Although we have assumed in this exercise a special functional form for v(a, b), the above results stand valid rather generally even if v is not additively separable in a and b (Borrowing Bank Loan or Issuing Corporate Bond?) An entrepreneur needs to invest 1 dollar to build a firm at date 0, while he has only w < 1 dollars. There are two types of investors in the financial market: households and commerical banks. The entrepreneur and all investors are risk neutral without time preferences; that is, they all seek to maximize expected profits and future cash flows are never discounted. The difference between the two types of investors is that banks have committed to spend a cost c > 0 to monitor each borrowing firm s operations, but households do not have the expertise that is required to oversee the firm s operations. Because banks will have to spend on monitoring, either the entrepreneur chooses to borrow 1 w from households only, or he must borrow (at least partially) from banks, and in the latter case, he needs to raise 1 w + c, instead of 1 w. After the entrepreneur gets the funding, he can incur a private cost ϕ 0 to determine the quality p of the firm s investment project at date 1. For simplicity, suppose that a project of quality p may generate Y dollars with probability p and nothing with probability 1 p at date 3, where the constant Y > 1. The personal cost ϕ is a function of p, and let us assume that, for some constant K > Y, ϕ(p) = K p, p [0, 1]. If a bank lends to the firm at date 0, then it can see p after spending 5 This exercise is adapted from George Nöldeke and Klaus M. Schmidt, 1998, Sequential Investments and Options to Own, Rand Journal of Economics, 9,

12 c > 0 before date. The firm can be liquidated at date, and its (nonnegative) liquidation value is L < 1. Let p be the first-best project quality; that is, 6 p = arg max py ϕ(p). p [0,1] Assume that py ϕ(p) > 1. (A) First suppose that banks do not exist. In this case, the entrepreneur can first decide to or not to offer a financial contract to a household, and in case he does, the household can either accept or reject it. A financial contract, or a corporate bond, is defined as (I, Q, R), such that, according to this contract, (i) the household needs to give the entrepreneur I dollars at date 0; (ii) the household (or, the bondholder) can choose to or not to liquidate the firm at date ; (iii) the household will get Q [0, L] in the event that the firm is liquidated at date ; and (iv) the household will get R [0, Y ] in the event that the firm is not liquidated at date, and it generates Y at date 3. Show that there exists w (0, 1) such that in equilibrium the entrepreneur chooses to borrow from a household and the household is willing to lend I = 1 w if and only if w w. From now on, assume the following numerical values: K = 7, Y = 13, L = 3 5, w = 1. 6 Verify that p = Y K and hence the assumption py ϕ(p) > 1 reduces to Y > K. Given Y, this last inequality holds for some K if Y >. 1

13 Let π E be the entrepreneur s expected wealth and p the equilibrium project quality. Show that under the optimal corporate bond (I, Q, R), 7 p = 1 8, R = 4, π E = (B) Next suppose that the entrepreneur can only borrow from banks. In this case, the entrepreneur can first decide to or not to offer a financial contract to a bank, and in case he does, the bank can either accept or reject it. A financial contract, or a bank loan, is defined as (i, q, r), such that, according to this contract, (i) the bank needs to give the entrepreneur i dollars at date 0; (ii) the bank can choose to or not to liquidate the firm at date, after it sees the firm s choice of p at date 1; (iii) the bank will get q [0, L] in the event that the firm is liquidated at date ; and 7 Hint: Since the household must decide to or not to liquidate the firm before knowing the entrepreneur s equilibrium choice p, the game between the entrepreneur and the household is a simultaneous game. Given (I, Q, R), and given p (which the household did not observe but can conjecture correctly in equilibrium), the household should liquidate the firm if and only if Q p R. On the other hand, the entrepreneur will choose p = 0 if he believes that the household will subsequently liquidate the firm, and he will choose p =argmax p [0,1] p(y R) ϕ(p) if he expects no liquidation. Note that there may exist multiple Nash equilibria for the subgame where the household has already lent to the entrepreneur. Verify that for this subgame it is an equilibrium where the household always liquidates the firm and the entrepreneur always picks p = 0. However, the household would not have lent to the entrepreneur in the first place if they expect this bad subgame equilibrium to subsequently prevail. In other words, bond financing is feasible only if the household expects the entrepreneur to pick p > 0 and only if the household can at least break even (that is, p R 1 w). 13

14 (iv) the bank will get r [0, Y ] in the event that the firm is not liquidated at date, and it generates Y at date 3. Show that the first-best p can be attained in equilibrium if L 1 w + c. 8 Show that, with the above specified numerical values, under the optimal bank loan contract (i, q, r), p = p = 13 7, π E = c, so that the entrepreneur prefers borrowing bank debt to issuing a corporate bond if c < 1 9. Solution. Consider part (A). Consider the subgame where the household has already lent 1 w to the firm, and the entrepreneur is about to choose p. Assuming that the household will not liquidate the firm subsequently (forward induction!), the entrepreneur seeks to max p(y R) ϕ(p), p so that p = Y R K. At the time the household lends to the entrepreneur, the household rationally expects the entrepreneur to choose p = Y R, given R. Hence K the entrepreneur should offer the household the contract (I, Q, R) that satisfies 8 Hint: The bank can see the entrepreneur s choice p before it decides to or not to liquidate the firm. Thus the game between the entrepreneur and the lending bank is a sequential game. The bank gets q L by liquidating the firm, and the bank gets pr by letting the firm continue its operations. If the contract (i, q, r) is such that 1 w + c = q = pr, then the bank will liquidate the firm if and only if p < p. Facing this credible threat, the entrepreneur s best response is p = p, fulfilling the productive efficiency. The only problem is q must not exceed L, and hence such a wisely designed contract is feasible if and only if L 1 w + c. 14

15 This implies that either Rp = R( Y R K ) = 1 w. R = Y + Y 4K(1 w) or R = Y Y 4K(1 w). It also follows that either p = Y + Y 4K(1 w) K or p = Y Y 4K(1 w). K Apparently, the entrepreneur prefers to implement a higher p. Thus we conclude that with bond financing we must have p = Y + Y 4K(1 w) K R = Y Y 4K(1 w). In equilibrium, by lending 1 w at date 0, the household expects to receive p R = Y [Y 4K(1 w)] = 1 w, 4K so that the household does break even. Note that we have assumed that Y 4K(1 w) is well-defined, or equivalently, w w 1 Y 4K > 1 Y 4. 15

16 If w < w, then for all R [0, Y ], Rp = R( Y R K ) < 1 w, so that the household can never break even from lending to the entrepreneur. Note also that, for p to be a legitimate probability, p must lie between zero and one, which is true: 0 < p = Y + Y 4K(1 w) K < Y + Y K = Y K 1. With the specified numerical values, we have p = 1 8, R = 4, implying that π E = p (Y R ) ϕ(p ) = Now, consider part (B). Under the optimal (i, q, r), the first-best quality p = 13 will be implemented, so that the total social surplus is 7 py ϕ(p) = Thus we have π E = (1 w) c = c, which is greater than 9 16 if and only if c 1 9. Remark. Forward induction tells us that either bond financing does not work, or following bond financing the bondholders would never force the firm to liquidate early. Thus the entrepreneur is free to choose any p that he likes. Since an overly low p would not allow bondholders 16

17 to break even, and since the entrepreneur would choose a high p only if the returns generated by the project will mostly be accrued to the entrepreneur, bond financing is feasible if and only if the entrepreneur himself can finance a large portion of the project; that is, w must be sufficiently close to 1. When bond financing is feasible, the chosen p is always lower than its first-best level p. Bank financing has the merit that the lending bank can force early liquidation after seeing the p chosen by the entrepreneur. The lending bank may have an incentive to let the firm continue (because continuation may generate for the bank a higher payoff than liquidation), but it is generally possible to design a contract that induces the bank to choose liquidation over contiuation whenever the entrepreneur chooses an overly low p. Given such a bank-loan contract, the entrepreneur knows that choosing an overly low p will result in the firm being liquidated, and he will not get much in the latter event. Thus bank financing can force the entrepreneur to choose a high p. Indeed, we have seen that it is sometimes (i.e. when L 1 w + c) possible to force the entrepreneur to implement p using bank financing. However, this productive efficiency comes at a cost: the bank must spend c to do auditing, which could be spared if the project were instead financed by issuing a bond. Given w, when c is small and L large, bank financing is apparently better than bond financing because it ensures the first-best productive efficiency. This exercise offers an explanation regarding why most firms are bankfinanced in a developing economy like Taiwan in the period. During that time most Taiwanese firms were small in size (and hence relatively easy to monitor, implying a small c) and possessed mostly general-purpose tangible assets (like factories and physical equipments that are valuable in most traditional business lines), which tend to have higher liquidation values L than intangible assets (like human capital or goodwill) or industry-specific tangible assets possessed by, say, a hightech company. As bank financing tends to dominate bond financing for a developing economy, it also renders an explanation regarding the late development of a bond market in a developing economy. 9 9 This exercise is adapted from Repullo, R., and J. Suarez, 1998, Monitoring, Liquida- 17

18 4. (Currency Attack.) This exercise concerns the strategic interactions between the government of a nation and a group of speculators in the foreign exchange market. 10 The state of the economy is denoted by θ, which is uniformly distributed over the unit interval [0, 1]. The exchange rate in the absence of government intervention is f(θ), with f ( ) > 0, so that a higher realization of θ represents a stronger state of the economy. The exchange rate is initially pegged by the government at e. Facing the government is a continuum of identical speculators located at the unit interval: for each a [0, 1], there is exactly one speculator located at a. Thus the total population of speculators is one. Each speculator may either attack the currency by selling short one unit of the currency, or refrain from trading. Short-selling costs t to the speculator. If a speculator short-sells the currency and the government abandons the exchange rate peg, then the speculator s payoff is e f(θ) t; but if the government defends the peg, then the speculator gets t. Assume that 11 e f(1) > e t = f(θ) > f(0). If the speculator chooses not to attack the currency, his payoff is zero. tion, and Security Design, Review of Financial Studies, 11, The following story can be found on the internet: The Quantum Group of Funds are privately owned hedge funds based in Curacao (Netherlands Antilles) and Cayman Islands. They are currently advised by George Soros through his company Soros Fund Management. Soros started the fund in 1973 in partnership with Jim Rogers. The shareholders of the funds are not publicly disclosed although it is known that the Rothschild family and other wealthy Europeans put $6 million into the funds in In 199, the lead fund, Soros Quantum Fund, became famous for breaking the Bank of England, forcing it to devalue the pound. Soros had bet his entire fund in a short sale on the ultimately fulfilled prediction that the British currency would drop in value, a coup that netted him a profit of $1 billion. In 1997, Soros was blamed for forcing sharp devaluations in Southeast Asian currencies. In July 011, the Quantum Fund announced they would be ending the fund, and will be returning all outside money by the end of 011. The fund will now exclusively manage Soros family money. 11 That is, given that the government would defend the peg, attacking the currency is worthwhile to a speculator if and only if the state of economy is weaker than or equal to θ. 18

19 The government s payoff to abandoning the exchange rate is zero, while the payoff to defending the exchange rate is v c(α, θ), where α is the population of speculators who choose to attack the currency, v is a positive constant representing the value of maintaining the peg, and c(, ) is continuously differentiable and such that c α > 0 > c θ ;1 c(1, 1) > v; 13 c(0, θ) < c(0, θ) = v < c(0, 0). 14 The game proceeds as follows. All speculators and the government first observe the realization of θ. Then, all speculators simultaneously decide whether to spend c and attack the currency. Then the government learns the population α of speculators that have chosen to attack the currency. The government then decides to or not to abandon the peg. The game ends after the government makes the decision. Assume that a speculator will not attack the currency if he feels indifferent about attacking or not attacking, and that the government will abandon the peg if it feels indifferent about abandoning or not abandoning the peg. (i) Suppose that θ [0, θ]. Does the government abandon the peg in equilibrium? Determine the equilibrium α. 1 That is, it is less costly for the government to defend the currency if the economy is in a stronger state or if there are fewer speculators choosing to attack the currency. 13 That is, when all speculators choose to attack the currency, the government s cost of defending the currency falls short of its value, regardless of the state of the economy. 14 That is, when the economy is in the weakest state, it is never worthwhile for the government to defend the peg; and when no speculators choose to attack the currency, there exists a benchmark state θ < θ of the economy such that the government would defend the peg if and only if θ θ. 19

20 (ii) Suppose that θ (θ, θ). Does the government abandon the peg in equilibrium? Determine the equilibrium α. 15 (iii) Suppose that θ [θ, 1]. Does the government abandon the peg in equilibrium? Determine the equilibrium α. Solution. that Consider part (i). For θ [0, θ], we have by c α > 0 > c θ v = c(0, θ) c(0, θ) c(α, θ), α [0, 1], and hence it is the government s dominant strategy to not defend the peg. Rationally expecting that the government will not defend the peg, a speculator can get e t f(θ) = f(θ) f(θ) > 0 by attacking the currency, since f ( ) > 0 and θ θ < θ. Thus in equilibrium we have α = 1, and the government will abandon the peg with probability one. Next, consider part (iii). Given that θ [θ, 1], a speculator would get e t f(θ) = f(θ) f(θ) 0 by attacking the currency, and hence no speculator chooses to attack the currency. Thus we have α = 0 in equilibrium. It follows from c > 0 > c and α θ θ θ > θ 15 Unlike in part (i) and part (iii), there may be multiple equilibria in part (ii). 0

21 that v = c(0, θ) > c(0, θ) c(0, θ), and hence the government chooses to defend the peg in equilibrium. Finally, consider part (ii). We claim that the equilibria obtained in respectively part (i) and part (iii) are both equilibria in part (ii). Indeed, if a single speculator expects all his fellow speculators will attack the currency, so that α = 1, then since v < c(1, 1) < c(1, θ), θ (θ, θ), the government will abandon the peg upon seeing α = 1. It follows that by joining his fellow speculators to attack the currency, that single speculator would get e t f(θ) = f(θ) f(θ) > 0, which implies that the single speculator had better follow suit. This proves that there does exist an equilibrium with α = 1. On the other hand, if a single speculator expects all his fellow speculators will not attack the currency, so that α = 0, 16 then since v = c(0, θ) > c(0, θ), θ (θ, θ), the government will defend the peg upon seeing α = 0, which implies that the single speculator had better follow suit and not attack the currency either. This proves that there does exist an equilibrium with α = With a continuum of speculators (represented by the unit interval), each single speculator is of zero Lebesgue measure. In other words, the equilibrium α is independent of the equilibrium behavior of a single speculator. 1

22 If we remove the assumption that the government will abandon the peg if it feels indifferent about abandoning or not abandoning the peg, and if we assume instead that the government may adopt a mixed strategy in the latter situation, then there also exists an equilibrium for part (ii) where the government randomizes between defending and abandoning the peg. Given θ (θ, θ), we can define two constants a(θ) and π(θ) as follows. By the monotonicity and continuity of c(, θ), and by the intermediate value theorem, there must exist a unique a(θ) (0, 1) such that c(1, θ) > v = c(a(θ), θ) > c(0, θ), since v < c(1, 1) < c(1, θ), θ (θ, θ), and v = c(0, θ) > c(0, θ), θ (θ, θ). Now, define π(θ) (0, 1) as the solution to the following equation (1 π)[f(θ) f(θ)] πt = 0 π(θ) = f(θ) f(θ) f(θ) f(θ) + t. Then, for each θ (θ, θ), there exists an equilibrium where (A) all speculators feel indifferent about attacking or not attacking the currency, and in equilibrium a group of speculators with population a(θ) choose to attack the currency; and (B) upon seeing α = a(θ), the government feels indifferent about defending or abandoning the peg, and in equilibrium the government may defend the peg with probability π(θ).

23 Remarks. This exercise is taken from Morris and Shin (1998, Unique Equilibrium in a Model of Self-Fulfilling Currency Attacks, American Economic Review). The multiplicity of equilibrium in part (ii) is disturbing, because the government cannot develop effective anti-attack strategies without knowing which equilibrium will prevail. The authors show that if the speculators do not observe θ directly but instead each receives a private signal about θ, then the problem of equilibrium multiplicity disappears. For this reason, the government has reasons to withhold some detailed information about the true state of the economy from the public investors. We shalll come back to this point after we talk about games with incomplete information. Observe that the likelihood of currency attacks decreases when the economy grows stronger; in particular, as shown in part (iii), when θ θ, we have α = 0 in equilibrium. In this sense, high real productivity guards financial stability. 5. (Price Competition in a Hotelling Model.) Consider a linear city where consumers uniformly reside on the unit interval [0, 1], and two firms A and B are located respectively at 0 and at 1 (the left and the right endpoints of the unit interval). Firm j produces a single product j costlessly, j {A, B}, and each consumer may either buy 1 unit of product A, or buy 1 unit of product B, or buy nothing. At each point t [0, 1], there exists exactly one consumer, whom we shall refer to as consumer t. Consumer t would obtain a surplus v p A tc if he buys from firm A, and a surplus v p B (1 t)c if he buys from firm B, where v > 0 is the gross utility that consumer t derives from consuming 1 unit of product A or product B, c > 0 represents the unit transportation cost facing the consumer, and p j is the retail price chosen by firm j. A consumer gets zero surplus if he buys nothing. The game proceeds as follows. The two firms must simultaneously announce retail prices, and upon (costlessly) learning about the two retail prices, consumers must simultaneously decide whether to visit one retailer and make a purchase, or to stay home and buy nothing. We shall concentrate on the pure-strategy Nash equilibria for this game. 3

24 (i) Suppose that (p A, p B) is a pure-strategy equilibrium. with this equilibrium, define for j = A, B, Associated T j {t [0, 1] : Buying product j is an equilibrium best response for consumer t}. (i-1) Show that for j {A, B}, either T j = or T j is a closed interval, where in the latter case, for some t a, t b [0, 1], T A = [0, t a ] and T B = [t b, 1]. (i-) Show that either T A TB = or there exists a unique t [0, 1] such that T A TB = {t }. 17 (i-3) Show that T A T B. (i-4) Show that if in a pure-strategy NE, T A TB =, then t a < t b, and consumer t a gets zero surplus from buying product A and consumer t b gets zero surplus from buying product B. (i-5) Suppose that in the pure-strategy NE (p A, p B), T A TB =. Show that, given any tiny ϵ, if given p B firm A deviates and prices at p A + ϵ instead, then firm A s payoff would become L(ϵ) (p A + ϵ) 1 c (v p A ϵ), so that in equilibrium we must have L (0) = 0, proving that p A = v. Likewise, show that p B = v. Show that (p A, p B) = ( v, v ) is indeed a pure-strategy NE if and only if 0 < v < c. 17 Note that in the former case, some consumers are left unserved in equilibrium. 4

25 (i-6) Suppose that in the pure-strategy NE (p A, p B), T A TB = {t }, where 0 t 1. Show that this implies that consumer t can obtain a non-negative surplus from buying either product, which in turn implies that c max(p A p B, p B p A). Show that given p B, firm A s payoff as a function of p A is p A ( p B p A c + 1 ); and given p A, firm B s payoff as a function of p B is p B ( p A p B c + 1 ). Show that in such an equilibrium, necessarily (p A, p B) = (c, c), and this pure-strategy NE exists if and only if v 3c. (ii) Now, on top of the above extensive game, let us add an earlier stage where firms must decide simultaneously whether to provide a presale service. Providing such a service will cost k j to firm j, where we assume that k B = k > k A = 0, and with firm j providing this service, a consumer s gross utility from buying product j rises from v to v + s. From now on, we shall assume that the unit transportation cost is c = 1, and that v is very large (so that T A TB is always non-empty). Suppose further that 0 < k < s 3 s 9, s < 3. Does firm B provide the presale service in the unique SPNE? Does the provision of presale services enhance the profits of the two firms? 5

26 Solution. Consider (i-1). We shall prove the assertion for the case j = A, and the case j = B can be analogously proved. If T A is nonempty, then either T A = {0}, which is a closed interval, or T A contains t > 0, and in the latter case, we claim that for all non-negative t < t, t T A also. Indeed, note that t T A if and only if and (IR) v p A tc 0; (IC) v p A tc v p B (1 t)c. If t > 0 satisfies both of these inequalities, then so does any t with 0 t < t. Hence T A must be an interval taking the form of [0, t a ) or [0, t a ]. Note that the two functions and f(t) v p A tc g(t) [v p A tc] [v p B (1 t)c] are both continuous in t, and that t T A if and only if f(t) 0 and g(t) 0. This implies that T A must be a closed set: let {t n } be a sequence in T A such that lim n t n = t a, then we have f(t a ) = f(lim t n ) = lim f(t n ) 0, g(t a ) = g(lim t n ) = lim g(t n ) 0, proving that t a T A also. Thus T A must take the form of [0, t a ]. Consider (i-). If T A TB contains t and t with t < t, then by (IC) we have v p A tc = v p B (1 t)c and which yields a contradiction. v p A t c = v p B (1 t )c, 6

27 Consider (i-3). We shall prove the assertion for the case j = A, and the case j = B can be analogously proved. Suppose that T A =. Note that this can happen only if either or (IC ) p A + tc p B + (1 t)c, t [0, 1], (IR ) p A + tc > v, t [0, 1]. By (IC ) and the fact that p B 0, we have implying that By (IR ), we have implying that p A (1 t)c, t [0, 1], p A c. p A v tc, t [0, 1], p A v. Note that firm A s equilibrium payoff is zero, and yet given p B, firm A can deviate and price at, for example, p = 1 min(v, c), and obtain a strictly positive payoff. Indeed, when firm A announces p A = p, even if p B = 0, consumer t would strictly prefer buying product A to buying product B if t max( v c, v c 1, 1 v 4c, 1 4 ), implying for firm A a deviation payoff of at least p > 0, which contradicts the assumption that p A is firm A s equilibrium best response 4 against p B. Hence in a pure-strategy NE, T A must be non-empty. Consider (i-4). In a pure-strategy NE where T A TB is empty, apparently we must have t a < t b, which follows directly from (i-1). Now, suppose that consumer t a gets a strictly positive equilibrium payoff from buying product A; i.e., v p A t a c > 0. 7

28 Then for e > 0 such that e < t b t a, e < 1 c (v p A) t a, obviously consumer t a + e should also be an element of T A, which contradicts the definition of t a! The same argument applies to consumer t b. Consider (i-5). By (i-4), we know that for ϵ R such that ϵ is sufficiently small, we have t a + ϵ < t c b, so that consumer t a + ϵ would c get a negative surplus if he accepts p B and buys product B. Thus consumer t a + ϵ would either purchase product A or buy nothing. By c changing its price from p A to p A ϵ, therefore, firm A s sales volume would change from t a to t a + ϵ, so that its payoff would then change c from its equilibrium payoff L(0) to L( ϵ). Since ϵ = 0 is an interior optimum for firm A s problem of maximizing L in a small neighborhood around ϵ = 0, we must have L (0) = 0 (the first-order condition), which gives rise to p A = v. The same analysis can be conducted on the part of firm B. Hence, necessarily, (p A, p B) = ( v, v ) in such an equilibrium. For such an NE to actually prevail, we must also require that t a = v < t c b = 1 v, or equivalently that c > v. c Consider (i-6). Note that buying either product is an equilibrium best response for consumer t, as t T A TB, and hence v p A t c = v p B (1 t )c, implying that t = p B p A c and for t to lie in [0, 1], we must have + 1, c max(p A p B, p B p A). Given p B, firm A s payoff, by changing p A slightly from p A, would be p A ( p B p A c + 1 ), 8

29 so that its best response p A must satisfy p A = p B + c. The same analysis on the part of firm B gives rise to p B = p A + c. Thus, necessarily (p A, p B) = (c, c), implying that t = 1. For consumer t to obtain a non-negative surplus, we must have v 3c. Finally, consider part (ii). By backward induction, we must consider 4 subgames when analyzing the two firms price competition (as in part (i)): (1) the subgame where both firms have spent on service provision; () the subgame where neither has chosen to provide the presale service; (3) the subgame where only firm A has spent on service provision; and (4) the subgame where only firm B has spent on service provision. Now we summarize the subgame equilibria. In the subgame where both firms have spent for service provision, p A = p B = c = 1, and the firms equilibrium payoffs are Π A = 1 4 and Π B = 1 4 k. In the subgame where both firms have chosen not to spend for service provision, p A = p B = c = 1, and the firms equilibrium payoffs are Π A = 1 and Π 4 B = 1. 4 In the subgame where only firm A has chosen to spend for service provision, p A = 1 + s, p 3 B = 1 s, and the firms equilibrium 3 payoffs are Π A = [ 1 + s 3 ] and Π B = [ 1 s 3 ]. In the subgame where only firm B has chosen to spend for service provision, p A = 1 s, p 3 B = 1 + s, and the firms equilibrium 3 payoffs are Π A = [ 1 s 3 ] and Π B = [ 1 + s 3 ] k. 9

30 By assumption, we have k < s s, and hence in equilibrium even firm 3 9 B chooses to spend for service provision. This equilibrium is Pareto inefficient for the firms (but not from the perspective of the entire society, because consumers benefit from service provision obviously), since the two firms would be better off if they could coordinate and commit to not spending on service provision. What happens here is that when v is very large, in the symmetric pricing equilibrium the firms prices depend only on c but not on v, and hence raising v by providing a presale service is totally wasteful from the firms perspective. In equilibrium, however, out of the fear that it might lose too big a market share to firm A if it did not provide the service, firm B chooses to spend on service provision also. 6. (Duopolistic Firms Submitting Supply Curves.) Recall the Cournot game in Example 1 of Lecture 1, Part I. Assume that c = F = 0 and the inverse demand in the relevant range is P (Q) = 1 Q, 0 Q = q 1 + q 1. Now consider a similar but different game, where the two firms must simultaneously choose supply curves instead of supply quantities. 18 That is, the two firms first choose supply functions at the same time, where for i = 1,, firm i s supply curve is denoted by S i (P ), and after they submit their supply functions, the product price P is determined via the following market-clearing condition S 1 (P ) + S (P ) = D(P ), where, from the inverse demand function, the demand curve is D(P ) = 1 P. 18 If we interpret the firms as financial institutions selling a stock, and consumers as market makers absorbing the financial institutions sell orders, then we are assuming in the Cournot game that financial institutions can only submit market orders, whereas in the current example, the financial institutions can submit either market orders or any number of limit orders. This exercise thus shows that large strategic traders in the stock market can manipulate the stock price by submitting limit orders. 30

31 (i) A linear Nash equilibrium is one in which both firms submit linear supply functions; that is, S i (P ) = a i + b i P, i = 1,, for some constants a 1, a R and b 1, b 0. In such an equilibrium, expecting firm j to submit the supply curve S j (P ) = a j + b j P, firm i optimally submits the supply curve S i (P ) = a i + b i P in equilibrium. Now, look for a symmetric linear Nash equilibrium, where symmetry means a 1 = a = a and b 1 = b = b 0. (ii) Determine if firms are better off in equilibrium because they can choose supply curves rather than supply quantities. (iii) We have confined attention to equilibria where b 1, b 0. What 31

32 would your answer to part (ii) become if we allow b 1, b < 0? 19 (iv) Show that, in fact, when the firms can submit any linear supply curves (with a 1, a, b 1, b R), every non-negative output pair (q 1, q ) with q 1 + q 1 can be sustained in some Nash equilibrium. Solution. Consider part (i). In order to solve for the Nash equilibrium, observe that given firm j s supply curve S j ( ), firm i becomes a monopoly facing the following residual demand curve D i (P ) D(P ) S j (P ), and all firm i needs to do is to find a point on this residual demand at which its profit is maximized. After such a point is found, any supply curve S i ( ) that passes through that point is one optimal supply curve 19 Hint: In order to solve the Nash equilibrium, observe that given firm j s supply curve S j ( ), firm i becomes a monopoly facing the following residual demand curve D(P ) S j (P ), and all firm i needs to do is to find a point on this residual demand at which its profit is maximized. After such a point is found, any supply curve S i ( ) that passes through that point is one optimal supply curve for firm i! However, we cannot just use any supply curve that passes through that point; we need to find for firm i a linear supply curve passing through that point and inducing firm j to optimally adopt S j ( ) in the first place. In particular, if firm i believes that firm j will submit S j (P ) = a j + b j P, show that firm i should select the point P (a j, b j ) = 1 a j + b j on its residual demand curve. Any linear S i ( ) passing through this point on firm i s residual demand curve is one best response for firm i, and such a supply curve must satisfy a i + b i P (a j, b j ) = S i (P (a j, b j )) = 1 a j (1 + b j )P (a j, b j ), so that after you impose symmetry (a i = a j = a and b i = b j = b), you will get a continuum of equilibria, where for each b 0, a is determined by a(b) = b 1 3. For part (ii), notice that when b = 0, this equilibrium coincides with Cournot equilibrium. 3

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I Homework 1, due in recitation on 10/18/2018. 1. Consider the following strategic game: player 1/player 2 L R U 1,1 0,0 D 0,0 3,2 Any NE can be

More information

HW Consider the following game:

HW Consider the following game: HW 1 1. Consider the following game: 2. HW 2 Suppose a parent and child play the following game, first analyzed by Becker (1974). First child takes the action, A 0, that produces income for the child,

More information

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average) Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, 2016 1. In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average) cost. To investigate the consequences of markup pricing,

More information

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercise - Quantity competition 1 Take firm 1 s perspective Total revenue is R(q 1 = (4 q 1 q q 1 and, hence, marginal revenue is MR 1 (q 1 = 4 q 1 q Marginal cost is MC

More information

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4) Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4) Outline: Modeling by means of games Normal form games Dominant strategies; dominated strategies,

More information

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercise. (U, R).. (U, L) and (D, R). 3. (D, R). 4. (U, L) and (D, R). 5. First, eliminate R as it is strictly dominated by M for player. Second, eliminate M as it is strictly

More information

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Problem Set 1 These questions will go over basic game-theoretic concepts and some applications. homework is due during class on week 4. This [1] In this problem (see Fudenberg-Tirole

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers Econ 5001 Spring 2018 Prof. James Peck The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers Note: There were 4 versions of the test: A, B, C, and D, based on player 1 s

More information

Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma

Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma Recap Last class (September 20, 2016) Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma Today (October 13, 2016) Finitely

More information

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE Answers to Problem Set 2 [1] (a) This is standard (we have even done it in class). The one-shot Cournot outputs can be computed to be A/3, while the payoff to each firm can

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Theory EC104

Advanced Microeconomic Theory EC104 Advanced Microeconomic Theory EC104 Problem Set 1 1. Each of n farmers can costlessly produce as much wheat as she chooses. Suppose that the kth farmer produces W k, so that the total amount of what produced

More information

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions Econ 711 Homework 1 s January 4, 014 1. 1 Symmetric, not complete, not transitive. Not a game tree. Asymmetric, not complete, transitive. Game tree. 1 Asymmetric, not complete, transitive. Not a game tree.

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Leonardo Felli 7 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Contract Theory has become only recently a subfield of Economics. As the name suggest the main object of the analysis is a contract. Therefore

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Part 2. Dynamic games of complete information Chapter 1. Dynamic games of complete and perfect information Ciclo Profissional 2 o Semestre / 2011 Graduação em Ciências Econômicas

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 017 1. Sheila moves first and chooses either H or L. Bruce receives a signal, h or l, about Sheila s behavior. The distribution

More information

Answers to Problem Set 4

Answers to Problem Set 4 Answers to Problem Set 4 Economics 703 Spring 016 1. a) The monopolist facing no threat of entry will pick the first cost function. To see this, calculate profits with each one. With the first cost function,

More information

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games Game Theory Wolfgang Frimmel Repeated Games 1 / 41 Recap: SPNE The solution concept for dynamic games with complete information is the subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium (SPNE) Selten (1965): A strategy

More information

Lecture Notes on Adverse Selection and Signaling

Lecture Notes on Adverse Selection and Signaling Lecture Notes on Adverse Selection and Signaling Debasis Mishra April 5, 2010 1 Introduction In general competitive equilibrium theory, it is assumed that the characteristics of the commodities are observable

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 07. (40 points) Consider a Cournot duopoly. The market price is given by q q, where q and q are the quantities of output produced

More information

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Answers to Problem Set [] In part (i), proceed as follows. Suppose that we are doing 2 s best response to. Let p be probability that player plays U. Now if player 2 chooses

More information

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009. Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Do not forget to write Problems 1 and 2 in the first Blue Book and Problems 3 and 4 in the second Blue Book. 1 Econ 101A

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to GAME THEORY PROBLEM SET 1 WINTER 2018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to andrey.zhukov@aalto.fi. Materials from Osborne and Rubinstein

More information

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Do not forget to write Problems 1 in the first Blue Book and Problems 2, 3 and 4 in the second Blue Book. 1 Econ 101A Final

More information

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

Game Theory: Additional Exercises Game Theory: Additional Exercises Problem 1. Consider the following scenario. Players 1 and 2 compete in an auction for a valuable object, for example a painting. Each player writes a bid in a sealed envelope,

More information

In Class Exercises. Problem 1

In Class Exercises. Problem 1 In Class Exercises Problem 1 A group of n students go to a restaurant. Each person will simultaneously choose his own meal but the total bill will be shared amongst all the students. If a student chooses

More information

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations? Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 7, 0. Consider an individual faced with two job choices: she can either accept a position with a fixed annual salary of x > 0 which requires L x units of labor

More information

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9 EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 24 November 2017 Bargaining Games: Recall Two players, i {A, B} are trying to share a surplus. The size of the surplus is normalized

More information

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves University of Illinois Spring 01 ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves Due: Reading: Thursday, April 11 at beginning of class

More information

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015. FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.) Hints for Problem Set 3 1. Consider the following strategic

More information

Problem Set 2 Answers

Problem Set 2 Answers Problem Set 2 Answers BPH8- February, 27. Note that the unique Nash Equilibrium of the simultaneous Bertrand duopoly model with a continuous price space has each rm playing a wealy dominated strategy.

More information

Notes for Section: Week 4

Notes for Section: Week 4 Economics 160 Professor Steven Tadelis Stanford University Spring Quarter, 2004 Notes for Section: Week 4 Notes prepared by Paul Riskind (pnr@stanford.edu). spot errors or have questions about these notes.

More information

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Reputations arise in situations where there is an element of repetition, and also where coordination between players is possible. One definition of leadership is that

More information

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Corporate Control Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Managerial Discipline and Takeovers Managers often don t maximize the value of the firm; either because they are not capable

More information

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Online Appendix for Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Giacomo Rodano Bank of Italy Nicolas Serrano-Velarde Bocconi University December 23, 2014 Emanuele Tarantino University of Mannheim 1 1 Reorganization,

More information

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Shingo Ishiguro Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University 1-7 Machikaneyama, Toyonaka, Osaka 560-0043, Japan August 2002

More information

Repeated Games. September 3, Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality. Finitely Repeated Games. Infinitely Repeated Games

Repeated Games. September 3, Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality. Finitely Repeated Games. Infinitely Repeated Games Repeated Games Frédéric KOESSLER September 3, 2007 1/ Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality Finitely Repeated Games Infinitely Repeated Games Automaton Representation of Strategies The One-Shot

More information

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition Kai Hao Yang /2/207 In this lecture, we will apply the concepts in game theory to study oligopoly. In short, unlike

More information

EC 202. Lecture notes 14 Oligopoly I. George Symeonidis

EC 202. Lecture notes 14 Oligopoly I. George Symeonidis EC 202 Lecture notes 14 Oligopoly I George Symeonidis Oligopoly When only a small number of firms compete in the same market, each firm has some market power. Moreover, their interactions cannot be ignored.

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015 CUR 41: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 015 Instructions: Please write your name in English. This exam is closed-book. Total time: 10 minutes. There are 4 questions,

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 More on strategic games and extensive games with perfect information Block 2 Jun 11, 2017 Auctions results Histogram of

More information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 ECON 459 Game Theory Lecture Notes Auctions Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 These notes have been used and commented on before. If you can still spot any errors or have any suggestions for improvement, please

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO May 22, 2015 Announcements HW #3 is due next week. Ch. 6.1: Ultimatum Game This is a simple game that can model a very simplified

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, MsC Economics List of Problems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

Solution Problem Set 2

Solution Problem Set 2 ECON 282, Intro Game Theory, (Fall 2008) Christoph Luelfesmann, SFU Solution Problem Set 2 Due at the beginning of class on Tuesday, Oct. 7. Please let me know if you have problems to understand one of

More information

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions? March 3, 215 Steven A. Matthews, A Technical Primer on Auction Theory I: Independent Private Values, Northwestern University CMSEMS Discussion Paper No. 196, May, 1995. This paper is posted on the course

More information

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions Microeconomics: Pricing 3E00 Fall 06. True or false: Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions (a) Since a durable goods monopolist prices at the monopoly price in her last period of operation, the prices must

More information

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

Answer Key: Problem Set 4 Answer Key: Problem Set 4 Econ 409 018 Fall A reminder: An equilibrium is characterized by a set of strategies. As emphasized in the class, a strategy is a complete contingency plan (for every hypothetical

More information

Lecture 9: Basic Oligopoly Models

Lecture 9: Basic Oligopoly Models Lecture 9: Basic Oligopoly Models Managerial Economics November 16, 2012 Prof. Dr. Sebastian Rausch Centre for Energy Policy and Economics Department of Management, Technology and Economics ETH Zürich

More information

AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July time : 1 hour. Do all 4 questions. All count equally.

AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July time : 1 hour. Do all 4 questions. All count equally. AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July 2017 time : 1 hour Do all 4 questions. All count equally. Q1. Monopoly is inefficient because the monopoly s owner makes high profits, and the monopoly s

More information

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership Attila Tasnádi Department of Mathematics, Budapest University of Economic Sciences and Public Administration, H-1093 Budapest, Fővám tér 8, Hungary

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Leonardo Felli 9 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Consider now a different cause for the failure of the Coase Theorem: the presence of transaction costs. Of course for this to be an interesting

More information

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1 . Economic Applications of Game Theory Fall 00 TA: Youngjin Hwang Problem 3 Solutions. (a) There are three subgames: [A] the subgame starting from Player s decision node after Player s choice of P; [B]

More information

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1 M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term.. Private Provision of Public Good. Consider the following public good game:

More information

Game Theory: Global Games. Christoph Schottmüller

Game Theory: Global Games. Christoph Schottmüller Game Theory: Global Games Christoph Schottmüller 1 / 20 Outline 1 Global Games: Stag Hunt 2 An investment example 3 Revision questions and exercises 2 / 20 Stag Hunt Example H2 S2 H1 3,3 3,0 S1 0,3 4,4

More information

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization An Application in Industrial Organization February 23, 2015 One form of collusive behavior among firms is to restrict output in order to keep the price of the product high. This is a goal of the OPEC oil

More information

ECO410H: Practice Questions 2 SOLUTIONS

ECO410H: Practice Questions 2 SOLUTIONS ECO410H: Practice Questions SOLUTIONS 1. (a) The unique Nash equilibrium strategy profile is s = (M, M). (b) The unique Nash equilibrium strategy profile is s = (R4, C3). (c) The two Nash equilibria are

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO May 24, 2016 Announcements Homework #4 is due next week. Review of Last Lecture In extensive games with imperfect information,

More information

Economics 171: Final Exam

Economics 171: Final Exam Question 1: Basic Concepts (20 points) Economics 171: Final Exam 1. Is it true that every strategy is either strictly dominated or is a dominant strategy? Explain. (5) No, some strategies are neither dominated

More information

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati. Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati. Module No. # 06 Illustrations of Extensive Games and Nash Equilibrium

More information

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information May 6, 2015 Example 2, 2 A 3, 3 C Player 1 Player 1 Up B Player 2 D 0, 0 1 0, 0 Down C Player 1 D 3, 3 Extensive-Form Games With Imperfect Information Finite No simultaneous moves: each node belongs to

More information

Eco AS , J. Sandford, spring 2019 March 9, Midterm answers

Eco AS , J. Sandford, spring 2019 March 9, Midterm answers Midterm answers Instructions: You may use a calculator and scratch paper, but no other resources. In particular, you may not discuss the exam with anyone other than the instructor, and you may not access

More information

Infinitely Repeated Games

Infinitely Repeated Games February 10 Infinitely Repeated Games Recall the following theorem Theorem 72 If a game has a unique Nash equilibrium, then its finite repetition has a unique SPNE. Our intuition, however, is that long-term

More information

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2013 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Economics 51: Game Theory

Economics 51: Game Theory Economics 51: Game Theory Liran Einav April 21, 2003 So far we considered only decision problems where the decision maker took the environment in which the decision is being taken as exogenously given:

More information

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 ANSWER KEY

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 ANSWER KEY ECONS 44 STRATEGY AND GAE THEORY IDTER EXA # ANSWER KEY Exercise #1. Hawk-Dove game. Consider the following payoff matrix representing the Hawk-Dove game. Intuitively, Players 1 and compete for a resource,

More information

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Chapter 33: Public Goods Chapter 33: Public Goods 33.1: Introduction Some people regard the message of this chapter that there are problems with the private provision of public goods as surprising or depressing. But the message

More information

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3 EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3 Leonardo Felli 32L.G.06 26 January 2015 Failure of the Coase Theorem Recall that the Coase Theorem implies that two parties, when faced with a potential

More information

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017 G5212: Game Theory Mark Dean Spring 2017 Bargaining We will now apply the concept of SPNE to bargaining A bit of background Bargaining is hugely interesting but complicated to model It turns out that the

More information

Econ 101A Final exam Th 15 December. Do not turn the page until instructed to.

Econ 101A Final exam Th 15 December. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Econ 101A Final exam Th 15 December. Do not turn the page until instructed to. 1 Econ 101A Final Exam Th 15 December. Please solve Problem 1, 2, and 3 in the first blue book and Problems 4 and 5 in the

More information

ECON106P: Pricing and Strategy

ECON106P: Pricing and Strategy ECON106P: Pricing and Strategy Yangbo Song Economics Department, UCLA June 30, 2014 Yangbo Song UCLA June 30, 2014 1 / 31 Game theory Game theory is a methodology used to analyze strategic situations in

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 5 [1] Consider an infinitely repeated game with a finite number of actions for each player and a common discount factor δ. Prove that if δ is close enough to zero then

More information

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms On Existence of Equilibria in Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms Northwestern University April 23, 2014 Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms In allocation mechanisms, agents choose messages. The messages determine

More information

MS&E 246: Lecture 5 Efficiency and fairness. Ramesh Johari

MS&E 246: Lecture 5 Efficiency and fairness. Ramesh Johari MS&E 246: Lecture 5 Efficiency and fairness Ramesh Johari A digression In this lecture: We will use some of the insights of static game analysis to understand efficiency and fairness. Basic setup N players

More information

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015. FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.) Hints for Problem Set 2 1. Consider a zero-sum game, where

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

University at Albany, State University of New York Department of Economics Ph.D. Preliminary Examination in Microeconomics, June 20, 2017

University at Albany, State University of New York Department of Economics Ph.D. Preliminary Examination in Microeconomics, June 20, 2017 University at Albany, State University of New York Department of Economics Ph.D. Preliminary Examination in Microeconomics, June 0, 017 Instructions: Answer any three of the four numbered problems. Justify

More information

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati Module No. # 03 Illustrations of Nash Equilibrium Lecture No. # 04

More information

Competition and risk taking in a differentiated banking sector

Competition and risk taking in a differentiated banking sector Competition and risk taking in a differentiated banking sector Martín Basurto Arriaga Tippie College of Business, University of Iowa Iowa City, IA 54-1994 Kaniṣka Dam Centro de Investigación y Docencia

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation

On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation May 1, 1997 On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation Yoshitsugu Kanemoto 1 Faculty of Economics, University of Tokyo 7-3-1 Hongo, Bunkyo-ku, Tokyo 113 Japan Abstract The most important drawback

More information

GAME THEORY: DYNAMIC. MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell. Frank Cowell: Dynamic Game Theory

GAME THEORY: DYNAMIC. MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell. Frank Cowell: Dynamic Game Theory Prerequisites Almost essential Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium GAME THEORY: DYNAMIC MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell April 2018 1 Overview Game Theory: Dynamic Mapping the temporal

More information

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Do not forget to write Problems 1 in the first Blue Book and Problems 2, 3 and 4 in the second Blue Book. 1 Econ 101A Final

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 23, 2015 Administrative Stuff Homework 2 is due next week. Due to the change in material covered, I have decided to change the grading system

More information

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati Module No. # 03 Illustrations of Nash Equilibrium Lecture No. # 02

More information

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Ahmer Tarar Department of Political Science Texas A&M University 4348 TAMU College Station, TX 77843-4348 email: ahmertarar@pols.tamu.edu

More information

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two MATH 321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two Course Instructor: Prof. Y.K. Kwok 1. (a) Suppose that an iterated dominance equilibrium s is not a Nash equilibrium, then there exists s i of some player

More information

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5 Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5 The basic idea prisoner s dilemma The prisoner s dilemma game with one-shot payoffs 2 2 0

More information

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02 Topic 5: Information Economics 21, Summer 2002 Andreas Bentz Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02 Introduction

More information

Problem Set: Contract Theory

Problem Set: Contract Theory Problem Set: Contract Theory Problem 1 A risk-neutral principal P hires an agent A, who chooses an effort a 0, which results in gross profit x = a + ε for P, where ε is uniformly distributed on [0, 1].

More information

Static Games and Cournot. Competition

Static Games and Cournot. Competition Static Games and Cournot Competition Lecture 3: Static Games and Cournot Competition 1 Introduction In the majority of markets firms interact with few competitors oligopoly market Each firm has to consider

More information

ECON/MGMT 115. Industrial Organization

ECON/MGMT 115. Industrial Organization ECON/MGMT 115 Industrial Organization 1. Cournot Model, reprised 2. Bertrand Model of Oligopoly 3. Cournot & Bertrand First Hour Reviewing the Cournot Duopoloy Equilibria Cournot vs. competitive markets

More information

Université du Maine Théorie des Jeux Yves Zenou Correction de l examen du 16 décembre 2013 (1 heure 30)

Université du Maine Théorie des Jeux Yves Zenou Correction de l examen du 16 décembre 2013 (1 heure 30) Université du Maine Théorie des Jeux Yves Zenou Correction de l examen du 16 décembre 2013 (1 heure 30) Problem (1) (8 points) Consider the following lobbying game between two firms. Each firm may lobby

More information

SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games

SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games Jörgen Weibull February 2017 1 Introduction Sofar,thecoursehasbeenfocusedonfinite games: Normal-form games with a finite number of players, where each player has a finite

More information

1 Solutions to Homework 3

1 Solutions to Homework 3 1 Solutions to Homework 3 1.1 163.1 (Nash equilibria of extensive games) 1. 164. (Subgames) Karl R E B H B H B H B H B H B H There are 6 proper subgames, beginning at every node where or chooses an action.

More information

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson all 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) 1. Critique of subgame perfection. 1 Consider the following three-player sequential game. In the first

More information

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L. Econ 400, Final Exam Name: There are three questions taken from the material covered so far in the course. ll questions are equally weighted. If you have a question, please raise your hand and I will come

More information

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game.

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game. Finitely repeated simultaneous move game. Consider a normal form game (simultaneous move game) Γ N which is played repeatedly for a finite (T )number of times. The normal form game which is played repeatedly

More information

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard December 5, 2012 Question 1 (Comparative Performance Evaluation) Consider the same normal linear model as in Question 1 of Homework 1. This time the principal employs

More information