MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE"

Transcription

1 MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Answers to Problem Set [] In part (i), proceed as follows. Suppose that we are doing 2 s best response to. Let p be probability that player plays U. Now if player 2 chooses L, her payoff is while if she chooses R, her payoff is pb + ( p)f pd = ( p)h. When p = 0, this boils down to a comparison of f with h, while if p =, this boils down to a comparison of b with d. (a) If f h and b d have the same sign, then player 2 will always want to choose L (assuming f > h and b > d) or will always want to choose R (assuming f < h and b < d), regardless of the value of p. So the best response is flat at the same value of q ( or 0). (b) If f > h and b < d, then player 2 will prefer L below some cutoff value of p and R above, where the cutoff is given by pb + ( p)f = pd = ( p)h. So the best response looks like this: it is q = for p < p, q = 0 for p > p, and q is any value between 0 and when p = p. The other cases are basically identical to (a) and (b). Notice that I have neglected possible equalities (such as f = h) but you do these in a very similar way. (ii) You will need a c and e g to have the same sign, and f h and b d to have the same sign. This ensures that each player has a strictly dominant strategy. (iii) Suppose, on the contrary, that (U, L) is a pure strategy Nash equilibrium. Then a e and b d. Case. b = d. Then it must be that g > c, otherwise (U, R) would be another Nash equilibrium. But then f > h, otherwise (D, R) would be Nash. But this means that to avoid (D, L) being Nash, a > e. So in this case, a > e and b = d. Now let q be the probability of the Column player playing L. For all q (0, ) but close enough to, qa + ( q)c > qe + ( q)g, so playing U for Row is a strictly best response. And if so, Column is indifferent between L and R (since b = d), so all pairs (p, q) with p = and q sufficiently close to are also Nash, a contradiction to uniqueness. Case 2. b > d. But then, because there are no strictly dominant strategies, h f. But then, to avoid (D, R) being Nash, it must be that c > g. But there are no dominant strategies, so that a = e (remember that a e to start with, so this is the only alternative). Now apply

2 2 the last couple of lines in Case starting from a = e (instead of b = d) to get a similar contradiction. [2] The best way to do these is to simply plot the best responses for each player on the same graph and then check out the intersections. I do this for the first example, the Battle of the Sexes. In the figure below, p is the probability of the Row player playing U and q is the probability of the Column player playing L. Note that there are three equilibria, two in pure and one in mixed, in which p = q = /3. p /3 0 /3 q You can (and should) do the rest yourself. [3] This is a classical model in political science. First take n = 2. Define the unique position x such that half the population have ideal points to the left of x and the other half have ideal points to the right of it. Because there is a continuum of citizens and ideal points have a density function, there is no ambiguity about this definition. Now consider all possible combinations of pure strategies, call them (x, x 2 ). Without loss of generality we can suppose that x x 2. Case. x < x 2. Now there are two subpossibilities. First, each of the candidates is getting an equal number of votes; there is an electoral tie. But then neither player can be playing a best response to each other. For instance, if x is increased slightly by ɛ (so that x + ɛ is still less than x 2 ), then candidate will not lose a single original voter, will gain some (why?) and so will win the elections for sure rather than with probability /2. Second, one of the candidates, say, is a clear winner. But the other candidate can assure herself a chance by simply selecting the same position x. Thus it is not possible for two candidates to have distinct positions in Nash equilibrium. Case 2. x = x 2. Again two subpossibilities. One is that this common value is not equal to x, the median defined above. But then any of the players can deviate slightly in the direction of x and get more than half the votes (why?), guaranteeing a victory. In contrast, with x = x 2 each player s chances of victory are only

3 The only remaining possibility is that x = x 2 = x, where both parties converge to the median voter. This is a Nash equilibrium, and it;s the only one as we have seen. If n 3 there is no Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. It is very easy to see this using the methods above. Essentially, one looks through different cases and gets a profitable deviation each time. You may be wondering how the equivalent of median voter convergence gets ruled out. Well, imagine that x i = x for every i, so each candidate s chances are /n. Now have any candidate deviate by choosing a position slightly to the rigt of x. Notice that she will now get everyone to the right of her, which is almost half the population. In contrast, the voters to her left are split up among the remaining candidates (some even stay with her), so that none of her rivals can get more than a quarter. So she wins for sure. [Go back again to case 2 above and see why this argument does not work when n = 2.] [4] (a) Look at the first-order conditions for best responses. The important point here is that you should not blindly write down first-order equality conditions describing a Nash equilibrium. Suppose you do that here: you will get the absurd result that n λ i f ( e i ) =, i= which, of course, cannot hold simultaneously for all the different values of λ i! Of course, once you see this you will understand right away that in any equilibrium e, e i is positive only if λ i is the largest among all the λ s. So in any pure strategy Nash equilibrium, the shareholders who have a share lower than the maximum share call this share M put in zero effort, and the maximum shareholders put in any combination of efforts so that total effort E solves the equation Mf (E) =. (b) Notice that none of the above attains the efficient outcome unless there is one person who gets the entire share! In that case, M = and the last equation in part (a) guarantees that the outcome is efficient. (c) Notice that high inequality is conducive to efficiency in this example. But efficiency just means Pareto optimality: there is no other combination of efforts that can make every person better off. [At this stage, you should convince yourself that every Nash equilibrium under every situation in which at least two persons get a positive share is inefficient in thise sense.] Pareto-optimality isn t everything in life, however, because the outcome is highly inequitable. The result also depends on the assumption that output is a function of the sum of efforts. If output depends in other ways on effort, then efficiency and inequality are not closely related anymore. If you are interested in more on this, look at [5] let e m be the amount of love and care put in by Mum, and e d the amount put in by Dad. Mum wants to maximize m(e m + e d ), while Dad wants to maximize d(e m + e d ). 3

4 4 By the same argument as in case (a) of the previous question, both parents cannot simultaneously set their first-order conditions equal to zero (because they have different maximizers). So one parent must put in zero love and care and the other the whole amount. Now show that if Mum has the larger maximizer she must put in all the effort. [3] [a] Consider the maximization problem: n max [u(c i ) v(e i )] subject to i= i= n n c i f( e i ). Of course you can use Lagrangeans to do this, but a simpler way is to first note that all c i s must be the same. For if not, transfer some from a larger c i to a smaller c j : by the strict concavity of u the maximand must go up. The argument that all the e i s must be the same is just the same: again, proceed by contradiction and transfer some from larger e i to smaller e j. By the strict concavity of v the maximand goes up. Note in both cases that the constraint is unaffected. So we have the problem: ( ) f(ne) max u v(e) n which (for an interior solution) leads to the necessary and sufficient first-order condition i= u (c )f (ne ) = v (e ). [b] The (symmetric) equilibrium values ĉ and ê will satisfy the FOC (/n)u (ĉ)f (nê) = v (ê), It is easy to see that this leads to underproduction (and underconsumption) relative to the first best. For if (on the contrary) nê ne, then ĉ c also. But then by the curvature of the relevant functions, both sets of FOCs cannot simultaneously hold. [c] Each person chooses r to maximize ([ ] ) e u β(/n) + ( β) e + E f(e + E ) v(e) where E denotes the sum of other efforts. Let (c, e) denote the best response. Write down the FOC which are necessary and sufficient for a best response: ([ ] ) u e (c) β(/n) + ( β) e + e f (e + E ) + f(e + E ( β)e ) (e + E ) 2 = v (e) Now impose the symmetric equilibrium condition that (c, r) = ( c, te) and E = (n )ẽ. Using this in the FOC above, we get [ ] u ( c) n f ( β)(n )f(nẽ) (nẽ) + n 2 = v (ẽ). ẽ

5 Examine this for different values of β. In particular, at β = we get the old equilibrium which is no surprise. The interesting case is when β is at zero (all output divided according to work points). Then you should be able to check that u ( c)f (nẽ) < v (ẽ)! [Hint: To do this, use the strict concavity of f, in particular the inequality that f(x) > xf (x) for all x > 0.] But the above inequality means that you have overproduction relative to the first best. To prove this, simply run the underproduction proof in reverse and use the same sort of logic. You should also be able to calculate the β that gives you exactly the first best solution. Notice that it depends only on the production function and not on the utility function. [d] Think about it! [7] (a) 5 b a 2 c d (6,0,6) (8,6,8) e f 3 g h g h (7,0,7) (0,0,0) (0,0,0) (7,0,7) (b) If player 2 plays C with probability then we are done; must initially play B. So all it remains to do is check when player 2 will want to play D with positive probability. This will happen if player 2 anticipates that in the subsequent coordination game between players and 3, one of the two pure strategy equilibria (it does not matter which one) is played. In that case 2 will strictly prefer to play D. But in these pure cordination outcomes player gets 7, so once again he will prefer to play B right at the beginning. [If player 2 anticipates the only remaining equilibrium in the coordination game, which yields an expected payoff to her of 5, she will want to play C, and this case has already been covered.] (c) Suppose that player 2 anticipates that in the subsequent coordnation game one of the two pure strategy equilibria will be played, but that player anticipates the mixed strategy equilibrium. In that case player 2 will, indeed, play D (anticipating a payoff of 0), but along this path player only anticipates an expected payoff of 3.5 (why?). So under these beliefs, player will play A.

6 6 This possibility is ruled out by the definition of a subgame perfect equilibrium because it is assumed that players have common beliefs about the strategy profile that will be played in the game. [8] Version (i): auditor s strategy space is { Audit, Not Audit }, individual s space is all maps from from the above space to { Evade, Not Evade }. Version (ii): auditor s strategy space is [0, ], where p [0, ] represents the probability of audit, individual s space is all maps from from the above space to { Evade, Not Evade }. Version (iii): auditor s strategy space { Audit, Not Audit }, individual s space is { Evade, Not Evade }. Solving these games is very easy. The important point is to note the different interpretations of a probability of audit: in (ii), it is a pure strategy, in (iii) it is a mixed strategy. [9] Basically, we worked this out in class. We showed that in a single-entrant problem the entrant would enter and the incumbent would not fight. Now you should be able to solve the n-entrant problem by using the same logic of backward induction as in the centipede game. This should show that no matter how many entrants you have (as long as they are finite), the entrant will enter and the incumbent will accommodate. [0] [OR Exercise 0.3.] Notice that if Army has strictly more battalions than Army 2, then this will never change over the course of the game no matter what they do. In this case the unique equilibrium of the game is for Army to attack when it can (in these cases K 2) and for 2 never to attack. In this equilibrium Army s payoff is K + x, where x > is the payoff from occupation. By deviating it can get only K. For Army 2 it suffices to consider a one-shot deviation. If it is in an attacking position, then for a profitable attack it must be that L 2 (otherwise it cannot occupy the island). If it attacks, then it loses a battalion. If L 2 then it loses the island next round for good (applying the strategies thereafter), so this deviation is not profitable. So the only case to consider is where they have the same number of battalions; K = L = M. If M =, the attacker does not attack (it wins but cannot occupy). So if M = 2, an attack with permanent occupation thereafter will occur. This means that if M = 3 an attack will not occur. And so on. It follows that if M is odd an attack will not occur, while if M is even and positive, it will occur. [] To discuss this question, consider the matching pennies game L R U,, D,, It should be obvious that no player can gain by committing to move first. The other person will obviously exploit the knowledge of the previous move. Matching pennies is an example of a game in which there is first-mover disadvantage. In contrast, consider any two-player game such that each player has a unique best response to the other player s strategy at each of its pure-strategy Nash equilibria, and assume that at least one such Nash equilibrium exists. Then notice that if a player is given the right to go first, she cannot be worse off. The reason is that she can always, at least, choose the Nash

7 equilibrium that is best for her and play her part of that strategy profile. She can be assured that her opponent will choose his part of the profile (this is where a unique best response at each Nash equilibrium helps), and so our first-mover can always guarantee herself the payoff from the best possible Nash equilibrium. So she is no worse off when she moves first. But sometimes she can do strictly better. Consider the Cournot duopoly with linear demand curve p = A bq and constant marginal cost c. Let s call the two individual outputs x and y. Calculate y as a best response to x: for each x, y is chosen to FOC (assuming y > 0): or max(a bx by c)y, (A bx by c) by = 0, y = A bx c, 2b at least for all the x s such that A bx c 0 (if not, y = 0). When the player that chooses x moves first, the big difference is that she does not play a best response to y! In fact there is no single number y that describes the strategy of the other player, who moves second. If you draw the game tree you see that the other player s strategy is a specification of y conditional on x. However, we know by subgame perfection that in equilibrium, this conditional strategy must specify best responses for each pre-committed value of x. Thus player maximizes knowing that subsequently, max(a bx by c)y, y = A bx c. 2b The solution to this first-mover problem gives the payoff to moving first. Notice that a feasible solution to this problem is to choose the Cournot-Nash value of x in the simultaneous-move game; then y would also be the Cournot-Nash value (unique), and the first mover can pick up the Cournot payoff at least. But she can do better. I leave the details to you. Solve the maximization problem above, and show that yields a value of x that is different from the simultaneous-move Cournot-Nash value. [2] Call the last period 0. Count backwards at A s offer points and label these points t = {0,, 2,...}. Let A s payoff at point t be a t. Now in the period just previous to t, B proposes and can obviously get αa t by offering A the amount αa t. Therefore what a can get at stage t +, which is just prior to this proposal by B, must be given by a t+ = β( αa t ) = ( β) + αβa t. This is a simple difference equation starting from a 0 and if there are T offer points, the solution a T, which is A s first offer (in real time) is given by a T = ( β)[ + αβ + (αβ) (αβ) T ] + (αβ) T a 0 7

8 8 Because a 0 is surely bounded, its exact value is irrelevant as long as αβ is less than one. The initial offer converges to a β αβ as T, which is exactly the infinite horizon Rubinstein bargaining solution studied in Lectures 5 and 6. By the same token, B s initial offer must converge to b α αβ. When α = β =, this convergence result breaks down. It can be verified that whenever A is the last person to make an offer, her first period payoff a T equals, otherwise it equals 0 (likewise for B). Such a sequence has no limit as T.

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Problem Set 1 These questions will go over basic game-theoretic concepts and some applications. homework is due during class on week 4. This [1] In this problem (see Fudenberg-Tirole

More information

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE Answers to Problem Set 2 [1] (a) This is standard (we have even done it in class). The one-shot Cournot outputs can be computed to be A/3, while the payoff to each firm can

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, MsC Economics List of Problems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

Notes for Section: Week 4

Notes for Section: Week 4 Economics 160 Professor Steven Tadelis Stanford University Spring Quarter, 2004 Notes for Section: Week 4 Notes prepared by Paul Riskind (pnr@stanford.edu). spot errors or have questions about these notes.

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to GAME THEORY PROBLEM SET 1 WINTER 2018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to andrey.zhukov@aalto.fi. Materials from Osborne and Rubinstein

More information

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers Econ 5001 Spring 2018 Prof. James Peck The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers Note: There were 4 versions of the test: A, B, C, and D, based on player 1 s

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 9, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO May 22, 2015 Announcements HW #3 is due next week. Ch. 6.1: Ultimatum Game This is a simple game that can model a very simplified

More information

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3 Introduction to Political Economy 14.770 Problem Set 3 Due date: Question 1: Consider an alternative model of lobbying (compared to the Grossman and Helpman model with enforceable contracts), where lobbies

More information

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015. FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.) Hints for Problem Set 2 1. Consider a zero-sum game, where

More information

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium Chapter 11 Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium In the previous chapter we examined simultaneous move games in which each player had a dominant strategy; the Prisoner s Dilemma game was one example.

More information

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours YORK UNIVERSITY Faculty of Graduate Studies Final Examination December 14, 2010 Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics S. Bucovetsky time=2.5 hours Do any 6 of the following 10 questions. All count

More information

In Class Exercises. Problem 1

In Class Exercises. Problem 1 In Class Exercises Problem 1 A group of n students go to a restaurant. Each person will simultaneously choose his own meal but the total bill will be shared amongst all the students. If a student chooses

More information

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game.

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game. Finitely repeated simultaneous move game. Consider a normal form game (simultaneous move game) Γ N which is played repeatedly for a finite (T )number of times. The normal form game which is played repeatedly

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 07. (40 points) Consider a Cournot duopoly. The market price is given by q q, where q and q are the quantities of output produced

More information

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions Econ 711 Homework 1 s January 4, 014 1. 1 Symmetric, not complete, not transitive. Not a game tree. Asymmetric, not complete, transitive. Game tree. 1 Asymmetric, not complete, transitive. Not a game tree.

More information

Strategy -1- Strategy

Strategy -1- Strategy Strategy -- Strategy A Duopoly, Cournot equilibrium 2 B Mixed strategies: Rock, Scissors, Paper, Nash equilibrium 5 C Games with private information 8 D Additional exercises 24 25 pages Strategy -2- A

More information

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati. Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati. Module No. # 06 Illustrations of Extensive Games and Nash Equilibrium

More information

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercise. (U, R).. (U, L) and (D, R). 3. (D, R). 4. (U, L) and (D, R). 5. First, eliminate R as it is strictly dominated by M for player. Second, eliminate M as it is strictly

More information

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4) Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4) Outline: Modeling by means of games Normal form games Dominant strategies; dominated strategies,

More information

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I Homework 1, due in recitation on 10/18/2018. 1. Consider the following strategic game: player 1/player 2 L R U 1,1 0,0 D 0,0 3,2 Any NE can be

More information

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9 EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 24 November 2017 Bargaining Games: Recall Two players, i {A, B} are trying to share a surplus. The size of the surplus is normalized

More information

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Do not forget to write Problems 1 in the first Blue Book and Problems 2, 3 and 4 in the second Blue Book. 1 Econ 101A Final

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Leonardo Felli 7 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Contract Theory has become only recently a subfield of Economics. As the name suggest the main object of the analysis is a contract. Therefore

More information

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002 Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002 P1. Consider the following game. There are two piles of matches and two players. The game starts with Player 1 and thereafter the players

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 More on strategic games and extensive games with perfect information Block 2 Jun 11, 2017 Auctions results Histogram of

More information

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two MATH 321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two Course Instructor: Prof. Y.K. Kwok 1. (a) Suppose that an iterated dominance equilibrium s is not a Nash equilibrium, then there exists s i of some player

More information

HW Consider the following game:

HW Consider the following game: HW 1 1. Consider the following game: 2. HW 2 Suppose a parent and child play the following game, first analyzed by Becker (1974). First child takes the action, A 0, that produces income for the child,

More information

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final) The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final) Watson, Chapter 15, Exercise 1(part a). Looking at the final subgame, player 1 must

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Reputations arise in situations where there is an element of repetition, and also where coordination between players is possible. One definition of leadership is that

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO March 22, 2015 Homework #1 Homework #1 will be due at the end of class today. Please check the website later today for the solutions

More information

Noncooperative Oligopoly

Noncooperative Oligopoly Noncooperative Oligopoly Oligopoly: interaction among small number of firms Conflict of interest: Each firm maximizes its own profits, but... Firm j s actions affect firm i s profits Example: price war

More information

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem Nash equilibrium: The concept of Nash equilibrium can be extended in a natural manner to the mixed strategies

More information

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

Game Theory: Additional Exercises Game Theory: Additional Exercises Problem 1. Consider the following scenario. Players 1 and 2 compete in an auction for a valuable object, for example a painting. Each player writes a bid in a sealed envelope,

More information

Problem Set 2 Answers

Problem Set 2 Answers Problem Set 2 Answers BPH8- February, 27. Note that the unique Nash Equilibrium of the simultaneous Bertrand duopoly model with a continuous price space has each rm playing a wealy dominated strategy.

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 23, 2015 Administrative Stuff Homework 2 is due next week. Due to the change in material covered, I have decided to change the grading system

More information

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1 M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term.. Private Provision of Public Good. Consider the following public good game:

More information

Game Theory Fall 2006

Game Theory Fall 2006 Game Theory Fall 2006 Answers to Problem Set 3 [1a] Omitted. [1b] Let a k be a sequence of paths that converge in the product topology to a; that is, a k (t) a(t) for each date t, as k. Let M be the maximum

More information

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information Backward Induction in dynamic games of imperfect information We start at the end of the trees first find the Nash equilibrium (NE) of the last subgame

More information

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

Answer Key: Problem Set 4 Answer Key: Problem Set 4 Econ 409 018 Fall A reminder: An equilibrium is characterized by a set of strategies. As emphasized in the class, a strategy is a complete contingency plan (for every hypothetical

More information

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1 . Economic Applications of Game Theory Fall 00 TA: Youngjin Hwang Problem 3 Solutions. (a) There are three subgames: [A] the subgame starting from Player s decision node after Player s choice of P; [B]

More information

University of Hong Kong ECON6036 Stephen Chiu. Extensive Games with Perfect Information II. Outline

University of Hong Kong ECON6036 Stephen Chiu. Extensive Games with Perfect Information II. Outline University of Hong Kong ECON6036 Stephen Chiu Extensive Games with Perfect Information II 1 Outline Interpretation of strategy Backward induction One stage deviation principle Rubinstein alternative bargaining

More information

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. 14.126 GAME THEORY MIHAI MANEA Department of Economics, MIT, 1. Existence and Continuity of Nash Equilibria Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. Theorem 1. Suppose

More information

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average) Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, 2016 1. In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average) cost. To investigate the consequences of markup pricing,

More information

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves. Econ 221 Fall, 2018 Li, Hao UBC CHAPTER 3. GAMES WITH SEQUENTIAL MOVES Game trees. Sequential-move games with finite number of decision notes. Sequential-move games with Nature s moves. 1 Strategies in

More information

Economics 171: Final Exam

Economics 171: Final Exam Question 1: Basic Concepts (20 points) Economics 171: Final Exam 1. Is it true that every strategy is either strictly dominated or is a dominant strategy? Explain. (5) No, some strategies are neither dominated

More information

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017 G5212: Game Theory Mark Dean Spring 2017 Bargaining We will now apply the concept of SPNE to bargaining A bit of background Bargaining is hugely interesting but complicated to model It turns out that the

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 14, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria Mixed Strategies

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 5 [1] Consider an infinitely repeated game with a finite number of actions for each player and a common discount factor δ. Prove that if δ is close enough to zero then

More information

MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 395

MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 395 MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 95 SPRING, 006 PROFESSOR A. JOSEPH GUSE () There are positions available with wages w and w. Greta and Mary each simultaneously apply to one of them. If they apply

More information

Games of Incomplete Information ( 資訊不全賽局 ) Games of Incomplete Information

Games of Incomplete Information ( 資訊不全賽局 ) Games of Incomplete Information 1 Games of Incomplete Information ( 資訊不全賽局 ) Wang 2012/12/13 (Lecture 9, Micro Theory I) Simultaneous Move Games An Example One or more players know preferences only probabilistically (cf. Harsanyi, 1976-77)

More information

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games Haifeng Huang University of California, Merced Repeated games Repeated games: given a simultaneous-move game G, a repeated game of G is an extensive

More information

1 Solutions to Homework 3

1 Solutions to Homework 3 1 Solutions to Homework 3 1.1 163.1 (Nash equilibria of extensive games) 1. 164. (Subgames) Karl R E B H B H B H B H B H B H There are 6 proper subgames, beginning at every node where or chooses an action.

More information

CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory)

CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory) 0 5 CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory) 1.0 Preferences Assigned: October 28, 2009 Suppose that you equally like a banana and a lottery that gives you an apple 30% of the time and a carrot 70%

More information

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition Kai Hao Yang /2/207 In this lecture, we will apply the concepts in game theory to study oligopoly. In short, unlike

More information

Econ 302 Assignment 3 Solution. a 2bQ c = 0, which is the monopolist s optimal quantity; the associated price is. P (Q) = a b

Econ 302 Assignment 3 Solution. a 2bQ c = 0, which is the monopolist s optimal quantity; the associated price is. P (Q) = a b Econ 302 Assignment 3 Solution. (a) The monopolist solves: The first order condition is max Π(Q) = Q(a bq) cq. Q a Q c = 0, or equivalently, Q = a c, which is the monopolist s optimal quantity; the associated

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO March 27, 2015 Homework #1 Homework #1 will be due at the end of class today. Please check the website later today for the solutions

More information

Other Regarding Preferences

Other Regarding Preferences Other Regarding Preferences Mark Dean Lecture Notes for Spring 015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University 1 Lecture 1 We are now going to introduce two models of other regarding preferences, and think

More information

CHAPTER 14: REPEATED PRISONER S DILEMMA

CHAPTER 14: REPEATED PRISONER S DILEMMA CHAPTER 4: REPEATED PRISONER S DILEMMA In this chapter, we consider infinitely repeated play of the Prisoner s Dilemma game. We denote the possible actions for P i by C i for cooperating with the other

More information

Game Theory Notes: Examples of Games with Dominant Strategy Equilibrium or Nash Equilibrium

Game Theory Notes: Examples of Games with Dominant Strategy Equilibrium or Nash Equilibrium Game Theory Notes: Examples of Games with Dominant Strategy Equilibrium or Nash Equilibrium Below are two different games. The first game has a dominant strategy equilibrium. The second game has two Nash

More information

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information May 6, 2015 Example 2, 2 A 3, 3 C Player 1 Player 1 Up B Player 2 D 0, 0 1 0, 0 Down C Player 1 D 3, 3 Extensive-Form Games With Imperfect Information Finite No simultaneous moves: each node belongs to

More information

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012 Name Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012 1) Consider the following strategic form game in which Player 1 chooses the row and Player 2 chooses the column. Both players know that this is

More information

Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence

Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence A The infinite horizon model This section defines the equilibrium of the infinity horizon model described in Section III of the paper and characterizes

More information

Oligopoly Games and Voting Games. Cournot s Model of Quantity Competition:

Oligopoly Games and Voting Games. Cournot s Model of Quantity Competition: Oligopoly Games and Voting Games Cournot s Model of Quantity Competition: Supposetherearetwofirms, producing an identical good. (In his 1838 book, Cournot thought of firms filling bottles with mineral

More information

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0 Problem Set 5 1. There are two players facing each other in the following random prisoners dilemma: S C S, -1, x c C x r, 1 0,0 With probability p, x c = y, and with probability 1 p, x c = 0. With probability

More information

Game Theory: Normal Form Games

Game Theory: Normal Form Games Game Theory: Normal Form Games Michael Levet June 23, 2016 1 Introduction Game Theory is a mathematical field that studies how rational agents make decisions in both competitive and cooperative situations.

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Part 2. Dynamic games of complete information Chapter 1. Dynamic games of complete and perfect information Ciclo Profissional 2 o Semestre / 2011 Graduação em Ciências Econômicas

More information

Notes for Section: Week 7

Notes for Section: Week 7 Economics 160 Professor Steven Tadelis Stanford University Spring Quarter, 004 Notes for Section: Week 7 Notes prepared by Paul Riskind (pnr@stanford.edu). spot errors or have questions about these notes.

More information

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercise - Quantity competition 1 Take firm 1 s perspective Total revenue is R(q 1 = (4 q 1 q q 1 and, hence, marginal revenue is MR 1 (q 1 = 4 q 1 q Marginal cost is MC

More information

Econ 101A Final Exam We May 9, 2012.

Econ 101A Final Exam We May 9, 2012. Econ 101A Final Exam We May 9, 2012. You have 3 hours to answer the questions in the final exam. We will collect the exams at 2.30 sharp. Show your work, and good luck! Problem 1. Utility Maximization.

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 017 1. Sheila moves first and chooses either H or L. Bruce receives a signal, h or l, about Sheila s behavior. The distribution

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015 CUR 41: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 015 Instructions: Please write your name in English. This exam is closed-book. Total time: 10 minutes. There are 4 questions,

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Repeated Games. September 3, Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality. Finitely Repeated Games. Infinitely Repeated Games

Repeated Games. September 3, Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality. Finitely Repeated Games. Infinitely Repeated Games Repeated Games Frédéric KOESSLER September 3, 2007 1/ Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality Finitely Repeated Games Infinitely Repeated Games Automaton Representation of Strategies The One-Shot

More information

Advanced Microeconomic Theory EC104

Advanced Microeconomic Theory EC104 Advanced Microeconomic Theory EC104 Problem Set 1 1. Each of n farmers can costlessly produce as much wheat as she chooses. Suppose that the kth farmer produces W k, so that the total amount of what produced

More information

Econometrica Supplementary Material

Econometrica Supplementary Material Econometrica Supplementary Material PUBLIC VS. PRIVATE OFFERS: THE TWO-TYPE CASE TO SUPPLEMENT PUBLIC VS. PRIVATE OFFERS IN THE MARKET FOR LEMONS (Econometrica, Vol. 77, No. 1, January 2009, 29 69) BY

More information

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Graduate School of Management and Economics

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Graduate School of Management and Economics In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics (for MBA students) 44111 (1393-94 1 st term) - Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Game Theory Game:

More information

SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games

SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games Jörgen Weibull February 2017 1 Introduction Sofar,thecoursehasbeenfocusedonfinite games: Normal-form games with a finite number of players, where each player has a finite

More information

Strategies and Nash Equilibrium. A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory

Strategies and Nash Equilibrium. A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory Strategies and Nash Equilibrium A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory (Mostly from Fudenberg & Tirole) Players choose actions, receive rewards based on their own actions and those of the other players. Example,

More information

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Chapter 33: Public Goods Chapter 33: Public Goods 33.1: Introduction Some people regard the message of this chapter that there are problems with the private provision of public goods as surprising or depressing. But the message

More information

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 ANSWER KEY

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 ANSWER KEY ECONS 44 STRATEGY AND GAE THEORY IDTER EXA # ANSWER KEY Exercise #1. Hawk-Dove game. Consider the following payoff matrix representing the Hawk-Dove game. Intuitively, Players 1 and compete for a resource,

More information

Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts. Game in strategic form has following elements. Player set N. (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i.

Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts. Game in strategic form has following elements. Player set N. (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i. Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts Game in strategic form has following elements Player set N (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i. Payoff function f i for player i f i : S R, where S is product of S i s.

More information

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version)

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version) July 4, 2017 1. Person A lexicographically prefers good x to good y, i.e., when comparing two bundles of x and y, she strictly prefers

More information

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Kang Rong School of Economics, Shanghai University of Finance and Economic (SHUFE) August, 202 Abstract I analyze an alternating-offer model that integrates

More information

Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ

Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ Finding Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games Page 1 Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ Introduction 1 The canonical game 1 Best-response correspondences 2 A s payoff as a function

More information

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu June 16th, 2016 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics)

More information

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2013 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

GAME THEORY: DYNAMIC. MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell. Frank Cowell: Dynamic Game Theory

GAME THEORY: DYNAMIC. MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell. Frank Cowell: Dynamic Game Theory Prerequisites Almost essential Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium GAME THEORY: DYNAMIC MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell April 2018 1 Overview Game Theory: Dynamic Mapping the temporal

More information

Repeated Games. EC202 Lectures IX & X. Francesco Nava. January London School of Economics. Nava (LSE) EC202 Lectures IX & X Jan / 16

Repeated Games. EC202 Lectures IX & X. Francesco Nava. January London School of Economics. Nava (LSE) EC202 Lectures IX & X Jan / 16 Repeated Games EC202 Lectures IX & X Francesco Nava London School of Economics January 2011 Nava (LSE) EC202 Lectures IX & X Jan 2011 1 / 16 Summary Repeated Games: Definitions: Feasible Payoffs Minmax

More information

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming 10. Game Theory Strategic Reasoning and Acting Alexander Kleiner and Bernhard Nebel Strategic Game A strategic game G consists of a finite set N (the set of players)

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Chapter 5 Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Until now we implicitly adopted a view that a Nash equilibrium is a desirable outcome of a strategic game. In this chapter we consider two alternative

More information

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

1 Two Period Exchange Economy University of British Columbia Department of Economics, Macroeconomics (Econ 502) Prof. Amartya Lahiri Handout # 2 1 Two Period Exchange Economy We shall start our exploration of dynamic economies with

More information

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture X: Introduction to Game Theory

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture X: Introduction to Game Theory Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture X: Introduction to Game Theory Kai Hao Yang 11/14/2017 1 Introduction and Basic Definition of Game So far we have been studying environments where the economic

More information

In reality; some cases of prisoner s dilemma end in cooperation. Game Theory Dr. F. Fatemi Page 219

In reality; some cases of prisoner s dilemma end in cooperation. Game Theory Dr. F. Fatemi Page 219 Repeated Games Basic lesson of prisoner s dilemma: In one-shot interaction, individual s have incentive to behave opportunistically Leads to socially inefficient outcomes In reality; some cases of prisoner

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012 Chapter 6: Mixed Strategies and Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibrium

More information

Answers to Problem Set 4

Answers to Problem Set 4 Answers to Problem Set 4 Economics 703 Spring 016 1. a) The monopolist facing no threat of entry will pick the first cost function. To see this, calculate profits with each one. With the first cost function,

More information

Game Theory: Global Games. Christoph Schottmüller

Game Theory: Global Games. Christoph Schottmüller Game Theory: Global Games Christoph Schottmüller 1 / 20 Outline 1 Global Games: Stag Hunt 2 An investment example 3 Revision questions and exercises 2 / 20 Stag Hunt Example H2 S2 H1 3,3 3,0 S1 0,3 4,4

More information