Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities"

Transcription

1 Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities Miho Hong Jaeok Park August 2, 2018 Abstract In this paper, we incorporate externalities into Shapley-Scarf housing markets. Agents preferences are defined over allocations rather than houses, and we focus on preferences that are egocentric in the sense that agents primarily care about their own allotments. When preferences are egocentric, we can apply the top trading cycles (TTC) algorithm using the associated preferences over houses. We establish that the allocation generated by the TTC algorithm is a stable allocation in the core, and we present a further preference restriction under which it is the unique such allocation. We also investigate the properties of the TTC algorithm as a mechanism. Our results extend the existing results on the TTC algorithm to the case of egocentric preferences, and they suggest that the TTC algorithm is useful and has desirable properties even in the presence of externalities. Keywords: Core, Externalities, Housing markets, Indivisibility, Stability, Top trading cycles. JEL Classification: C71, C78, D62. 1 Introduction In this paper, we study a market with indivisibilities and externalities. In their pioneering work, Shapley and Scarf (1974) introduce an exchange economy with a finite number of We are grateful to Takashi Akahoshi, Benjamin Casner, Yeon-Koo Che, Eun Jeong Heo, Daisuke Hirata, Jinyong Jeong, Seungwon (Eugene) Jeong, Jinwoo Kim, Bettina Klaus, Fuhito Kojima, Peng Liu, Eiichi Miyagawa, William Phan, Tayfun Sönmez, Takashi Ui, and seminar and conference participants at Kyoto University, Hitotsubashi University, Kobe University, the 14th Meeting of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare, the 2018 Asian Meeting of the Econometric Society, and the 29th International Conference on Game Theory at Stony Brook for valuable comments and suggestions. School of Economics, Yonsei University ( miho.m.hong@gmail.com) Corresponding author. School of Economics, Yonsei University, 50 Yonsei-ro, Seodaemun-gu, Seoul 03722, Republic of Korea ( jaeok.park@yonsei.ac.kr) 1

2 agents in which each agent owns an indivisible object (say, a house), has use for exactly one object, and looks for trading with other agents. Such an economy is referred to as a housing market in the literature. It is one of the simplest kinds of exchange economies one can imagine, and together with a house allocation problem (Hylland and Zeckhauser, 1979) it has served as a basic model for indivisible goods allocation problems and one-sided matching problems (see, for example, Moulin, 1995; Abdulkadiroğlu and Sönmez, 2013). Externalities are abundant in the real world, and a market with indivisible goods is not an exception. For example, in residential areas, a resident of a house cares about the demographics of his neighbors, and in universities, a faculty member s preferences regarding offices may depend on his relationships with colleagues using nearby offices. Despite the ubiquity of externalities, most existing works on housing markets have not taken externalities into consideration, assuming that each agent cares only about his own allotment but not others. The goal of this paper is to provide an analysis of housing markets with externalities. Shapley and Scarf (1974) show that the core (defined by strong domination) of a housing market is nonempty. They also introduce an algorithm called the top trading cycles (TTC) algorithm that produces an allocation in the core. Roth and Postlewaite (1977) complement Shapley and Scarf s (1974) results by proving that the core (defined by weak domination) of a housing market is a singleton when agents have strict preferences over houses and that the unique allocation in the core can be obtained by the TTC algorithm. As the core is the main solution concept for housing markets and the TTC algorithm provides a method to find an allocation in the core, we aim to investigate whether the tight connection between the core and the TTC algorithm continues to hold in the presence of externalities. The presence of externalities creates difficulties in applying the TTC algorithm as well as defining the core. At each step of the TTC algorithm, each remaining agent points to the owner of the house he prefers most among the remaining houses. However, when there are externalities, an agent s preferences over houses may depend on how the rest of the houses are allocated to the other agents, and thus his favorite house may not be well-defined. In order to avoid this complication, we focus on a class of preferences where an agent is primarily interested in his own allotment. That is, each agent has a strict preference order over houses, and whenever any two allocations assign distinct houses to him, his ranking between the two allocations is determined by that between the houses he receives at those allocations. 1 An agent is subject to externalities in the sense that he may have a strict ranking between two allocations that assign the same house to him. We call this kind of 1 Dutta and Massó (1997) propose similar preference restrictions in two-sided many-to-one matching markets. They consider firm-lexicographic (resp. worker-lexicographic ) preferences where a worker s preferences over firms (resp. colleagues) dictate his overall preferences over firm-colleague pairs. In the context of two-sided one-to-one matching markets with contracts, Li (1993) uses weak externalities to refer to a situation where an agent cares about his own partner and contract prior to others. Sasaki and Toda (1996) call such preferences order preserving. 2

3 preferences egocentric preferences. Though restrictive, it is a reasonable class of preferences over allocations. It expresses the idea that one s own allotment is of higher significance than others allotments in one s utility. In other words, it reflects a situation in which the size of externalities is small relative to that of utility from one s own allotment. When an agent has egocentric preferences, he has well-defined preferences over houses. Thus, any housing market with egocentric preferences is associated with a housing market without externalities, and we can apply the TTC algorithm to the associated housing market. The core is the set of allocations that are immune to coalitional deviations, and thus it depends on what kind of outcomes a coalition can attain by deviating from a proposed allocation. The presence of externalities creates two issues. First, when there are externalities, it matters to a coalition how the residual agents react to its deviation. Thus, it needs to form a belief about the reaction of the residual agents, and different kinds of expectation lead to various concepts of the core. Second, in the presence of externalities, a coalition may benefit from the reallocation of the outside agents houses even when its members keep the same houses as in the proposed allocation, and thus some agents may form a coalition just to influence others houses. However, it is not so natural that the outside agents adjust their behavior even when a coalition makes no change in its behavior. So we deal with the second issue by requiring in our definition of domination that a deviating coalition should change its behavior from the proposed allocation. Given our concept of domination, we consider two extreme concepts of the core. At one extreme, deviating agents have optimistic prediction that the outside agents will behave in a way that benefits the deviators. At the other extreme, deviating agents have pessimistic expectation that the outside agents aim to deter the deviation. We call the core based on optimistic and pessimistic expectation the ω-core (Kóczy, 2007) and the α-core (Aumann, 1961), respectively. The ω-core is the smallest and the α-core is the largest among cores based on various kinds of expectation. So we resolve the first issue by providing results in the strongest form with an extreme core concept. In particular, we present an existence result using the ω-core and a uniqueness result using the α-core, so that the results continue to hold with any other core notion. In other words, our results hold independently of the core notion we adopt. We also introduce two intermediate notions of the core, called the γ-core and the δ-core (Hart and Kurz, 1983), and study their logical relationship. The γ-core is based on the belief that the remaining agents end up with their own endowments when a coalition deviates, whereas the δ-core is based on the belief that they keep trading their houses as in the proposed allocation whenever possible. 2 Another solution concept that plays a significant role in the presence of externalities is stable allocations. Suppose that agents agree on an allocation and execute trade to 2 Existing studies on two-sided matching markets with externalities have made similar assumptions: when some agents deviate, other unaffected agents keep their matches. See, for example, Mumcu and Saglam (2010) for one-to-one matching and Bando (2012, 2014) for many-to-one matching. 3

4 achieve the allocation. Without externalities (and strict preferences over houses), no further improvement by a coalition is possible if the allocation is in the core (defined by weak domination). However, with externalities, a group of agents may get better off by reallocating their allotments among themselves even if the allocation is in the ω-core. This is because reallocation by a coalition can make an outside agent worse off and thus the new allocation does not necessarily dominate the original endowment allocation. We call an allocation that is immune to further coalitional deviations a stable allocation, following the terminology of Roth and Postlewaite (1977). We can expect that an allocation that is not stable would not persist, and thus we focus on stable allocations. In sum, we take stable allocations in the core as our solution concept. An allocation being in the core means that no coalition has a profitable deviation from the allocation before it is implemented, while an allocation being stable indicates that no coalition has an incentive to deviate from the allocation after it is implemented. Thus, our solution concept checks that an allocation is not blocked before and after trade is executed according to the allocation. In our main results, we study the relationship between the TTC algorithm and stable allocations in the core. We first show that the allocation generated by the TTC algorithm is a stable allocation in the ω-core (Theorem 1). Since the ω-core is the smallest core, a solution is guaranteed to exist regardless of the core concept, and it can be obtained by applying the TTC algorithm. We next show that, when externality creators have aligned interests, a stable allocation in the α-core is unique and coincides with the allocation obtained by the TTC algorithm (Theorem 2). Since the α-core is the largest core and there exists a stable allocation in any smaller core, the uniqueness result still holds with any other core concept. This result generalizes the existing result of Roth and Postlewaite (1977) that an allocation in the core of a housing market without externalities is unique and can be obtained by the TTC algorithm. There are other desirable properties of the TTC algorithm established in the existing literature. For example, Abdulkadiroğlu and Sönmez (1998) show that one can generate all Pareto efficient allocations from the TTC algorithm by varying agents endowments, Roth (1982) and Moulin (1995) prove that the TTC algorithm as a mechanism is (coalitionally) strategy-proof, and Ma (1994) establishes that a mechanism is individually rational, Pareto efficient, and strategy-proof if and only if it is the TTC mechanism. In Propositions 1 3, we show that these existing results can be generalized to the case of egocentric preferences when we replace Pareto efficiency with stability. This suggests that stability plays a more important role than Pareto efficiency in the presence of externalities, while without externalities these two concepts coincide. Our results also indicate that it is desirable to select the allocation generated by the TTC algorithm when there are multiple stable allocations in the core. So our analysis implies that, when externalities are not so large, the TTC algorithm continues to provide the best solution for housing markets. In 4

5 other words, the desirable properties of the TTC algorithm are robust to the introduction of small externalities. 3 There is a growing body of literature on matching markets with externalities, especially in two-sided settings (see Bando et al., 2016, for a recent survey). Sasaki and Toda (1996) provide an early analysis on two-sided one-to-one matching problems with externalities. They consider a scenario where a deviating pair holds a pessimistic belief about the reaction of non-deviating agents, and they show that a stable matching exists for all preference profiles if and only if agents estimate that all possible matchings can arise after a deviation. Mumcu and Saglam (2010) also consider two-sided one-to-one matching problems with externalities but use a different stability notion analogous to the δ-core, as explained in footnote 2. They provide a sufficient condition on the preference profile for the existence of stable matchings. Bando (2012, 2014) studies two-sided many-to-one matching problems with externalities among firms, and he presents preference restrictions for the existence of quasi-stable matchings as well as a modified deferred acceptance algorithm that generates the worker-optimal quasi-stable matching. Dutta and Massó (1997) analyze two-sided many-to-one matching problems with preferences over colleagues. In this setting, externalities exist only among workers hired by the same firm, and thus, unlike in our model and the aforementioned models, the core concept does not depend on the reaction of residual agents. Dutta and Massó (1997) show among other results that, when preferences are firm-lexicographic, a matching in the core exists and can be obtained by finding a stable matching under the associated preference profile without externalities. Our work is closely related to theirs in that not only we adopt a similar preference restriction but also we establish the existence of a solution by using the allocation in the core of the associated housing market without externalities. There are not many studies on one-sided matching problems with externalities. Mumcu and Saglam (2007) study housing markets with externalities and show that there can be no or more than one allocation in the core. Baccara et al. (2012) examine the problem of assigning offices to faculty members, which can be modeled as a house allocation problem, and quantify the effects of network externalities using field data. Sönmez (1999) and Ehlers (2018) consider a class of indivisible goods allocation problems, which includes housing markets as a special case, while allowing externalities. Their main results and comparison with ours are discussed in Section 4. Recently, Graziano et al. (2018) study housing markets with externalities and present two preference restrictions under which the set of stable allocations is a von Neumann Morgenstern stable set. Their first preference restriction corresponds to our egocentricity assumption but is more restrictive in that they assume strict preferences over allocations. So we establish 3 In a similar vein, Fisher and Hafalir (2016) consider two-sided one-to-one matching markets with small aggregate externalities and provide a sufficient condition for the existence of stable matchings. 5

6 that stable allocations exist (Theorem 1) and form a stable set (Remark 1) even when an agent can be indifferent between two allocations where he receives the same house. The rest of this paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we present the model of housing markets with egocentric preferences, and introduce some desirable properties of allocations. In Section 3, we describe the TTC algorithm and study the properties of allocations it produces. In Section 4, we examine the properties of the TTC algorithm as a mechanism. In Section 5, we discuss some intermediate core concepts and the case of non-egocentric preferences. In Section 6, we conclude. 2 The Model 2.1 Housing Markets with Egocentric Preferences We consider an exchange economy with a finite number of agents in which each agent owns a house initially, has use for one and only one house, and seeks to trade houses with other agents. Let N and H be finite sets of agents and houses, respectively, with N = H 3. An allocation describes the house assigned to each agent and is represented by a one-to-one function from N onto H. Let A be the set of all allocations. For any allocation a A, a(i) denotes the house received by agent i, and we call it the allotment of agent i at allocation a. We allow consumption externalities in that an agent cares not only about his own allotment but also about others. So each agent s preferences are defined over the set of allocations instead of houses. For each agent i N, R i denotes his preference relation, which is a complete and transitive binary relation on A. For any a, b A, ar i b means that agent i likes allocation a at least as much as allocation b. Given R i, we denote its asymmetric and symmetric parts by P i and I i, respectively. That is, for any a, b A, we write ap i b if ar i b and not br i a, and we write ai i b if ar i b and br i a. A profile of agents preference relations is denoted by R = (R i ) i N. Agents ownership is described by an initial endowment allocation e A so that e(i) is the house initially owned by agent i. A housing market (with externalities) is a 4-tuple N, H, R, e. We assume that each agent is not indifferent between any two allocations where he receives different houses. In other words, ai i b implies a(i) = b(i). We also assume that each agent cares about his own allotment prior to others. More specifically, ap i b and a(i) b(i) implies a P i b for any a and b such that a (i) = a(i) and b (i) = b(i). We call a preference relation satisfying these two assumptions egocentric. Note that, given an egocentric preference relation R i, we can derive a preference relation R i on H by defining h R i h if (i) h = h or (ii) h h and ap i b for all a, b A such that a(i) = h and b(i) = h. By our assumptions, Ri is a complete, transitive, and antisymmetric binary relation on H, expressing agent i s strict preferences over houses as his allotment. We refer to R i as 6

7 the preference relation over own-allotments associated with R i. We write the asymmetric part of R i as P i, which is defined analogously to P i. Given a housing market N, H, R, e with egocentric preferences, we can consider a related housing market N, H, R, e without externalities, where R = ( R i ) i N. In the literature on matching without externalities, it is common to assume strict preferences over one s possible allotments for analytic convenience, and our assumptions generalize it by allowing externalities. In the following, when we mention the case of no externalities, we refer to the case of strict preferences over houses unless otherwise stated. 2.2 Properties of Allocations We discuss several desirable properties that an allocation can possess, first in a housing market and then in a house allocation problem Core The core is a central solution concept for cooperative games, providing a set of allocations that are immune to coalitional deviations. When there are externalities, the preferences of coalition members depend on the allocation outside of the coalition. Hence, when a coalition plans a deviation, it needs to predict how the residual agents react to the deviation, and it implements the deviation only if its members get better off given its expectation. There are different kinds of expectation that a coalition can form about the residual agents behavior, and here we present two extreme kinds while discussing intermediate ones later in Section 5.1. In the most optimistic prediction, a coalition believes that the outside agents will do a favor for its members, and thus it will deviate if it is possible to make its members better off with the help of the outsiders. In contrast, in the most pessimistic prediction, a coalition expects that the residual agents will take action against its members interests, and so it will deviate if the deviation can benefit its members even in the worst possible scenario. Of course, these two kinds of expectation are too extreme and seem unrealistic, but we study them because the core notions based on them provide a lower and an upper bound for any core notion based on a more reasonable and realistic kind of expectation. 4 A nonempty subset of N is called a coalition, while N as a coalition is called the grand coalition. For any a A and any S N, let a(s) = {a(i) : i S}. For a given allocation a, we say that a coalition S is a trading cycle in a (with endowment e) if a(s) = e(s) and a(s ) e(s ) for any nonempty S S with S S. That is, a trading cycle in a is a minimal subset of agents who trade houses among themselves to obtain their allotments at a. 4 For example, the recursive cores proposed by Kóczy (2007), where the residual agents choose a core allocation, lie between the two extreme cores we consider. 7

8 The elements of a trading cycle in a can be indexed as {i 1,..., i m } such that a(i l ) = e(i l+1 ) for all l = 1,..., m 1 and a(i m ) = e(i 1 ), and we sometimes represent the trading cycle by the sequence (i 1,..., i m ). An allocation a uniquely partitions the set of agents into trading cycles in a. An allocation b A dominates an allocation a A via coalition T (or, coalition T blocks a via b) in the market N, H, R, e if (i) b(t ) = e(t ), (ii) b(i) a(i) for some i T, (iii) br i a for all i T, and (iv) bp i a for some i T. The ω-core of the market N, H, R, e is the set of allocations that are not dominated by any allocation in N, H, R, e. For any coalition T, let A e T be the set of all allocations in the submarket consisting of the agents in T. That is, A e T denotes the set of all bijections from T to e(t ). Similarly, let Ae T be the set of all allocations in the submarket consisting of the agents outside of T. When T is the grand coalition, we take A e T as the empty set. For any coalition T, any pair (a T, a T ) A e T Ae T yields an allocation where trade occurs among agents in T and among those outside of T. A coalition T α-blocks an allocation a in the market N, H, R, e if there exists b T A e T such that (b T, b T ) dominates a via T in N, H, R, e for all b T A e T. The α-core of the market N, H, R, e is the set of allocations that are not α-blocked by any coalition in N, H, R, e. When there are externalities, it is possible that an agent benefits from other agents reallocation of their allotments. Hence, some agents may form a coalition in order to affect others allotments while keeping their own allotments. By imposing the requirement b(i) a(i) for some i T in the definition of domination, we preclude this possibility. Given a proposed allocation, if a coalition plans to maintain its members allotments, there is no reason for the outside agents to react and adjust their allotments. Thus, we require that a coalition should make a different arrangement within it in order to initiate a deviation and induce the residual agents reaction. 5 The notion of the ω-core reflects the most optimistic view of deviating agents that trade outside of the coalition can be chosen as they desire. In contrast, the notion of the α-core is based on the most pessimistic belief that the residual agents objective is to deter the deviation. Hence, the ω-core is smaller than the α-core, and any other core notion (given our definition of domination) yields a core that lies between the two. When there are no externalities, it is immaterial what kind of expectation a coalition holds about the residual agents behavior, and thus the two extreme core notions reduce to the usual notion of the core (defined by weak domination) Stability and Pareto Efficiency A house allocation problem is a triple N, H, R, which is the same as a housing market except that agents own houses collectively rather than individually. An allocation a A 5 We further explain the necessity of this requirement in Remark 5 in Section

9 is stable in the problem N, H, R if a belongs to the ω-core of the market N, H, R, a (cf. Roth and Postlewaite, 1977). That is, no coalition can block a stable allocation once it is implemented. Suppose that a is not stable. Then there exists an allocation b and a coalition T such that b dominates a via T in N, H, R, a. Let T = {i T : b(i) a(i)}. Then T T, and br i a for all i T. With egocentric preferences, we have bp i a for all i T, and this holds true even when the agents outside of T reallocate their allotments from b. Note that T consists of trading cycles in b with endowment a, satisfying a(t ) = b(t ). Hence, the concept of stability can be defined equivalently by using the α-core (and thus any other core) instead of the ω-core, and it can be characterized as follows: An allocation a is stable if and only if there exists no allocation b such that b a and b(i) P i a(i) for all i N with b(i) a(i). Thus, stability is a concept that can be checked with preferences over own-allotments. Remark 1. Our notion of stability is slightly different from that of Roth and Postlewaite (1977) in that we use a core concept defined by weak domination while Roth and Postlewaite (1977) adopt strong domination in which every coalition member gains strictly. Kawasaki (2015) shows that the set of stable allocations in the sense of Roth and Postlewaite (1977) is the unique von Neumann Morgenstern (vnm) stable set with respect to some domination relation. Although we use weak domination to define our core concepts, our assumption of egocentric preferences allows us to use strong domination for agents whose allotments differ at the two compared allocations in the characterization of stability, and we can obtain a similar result to that of Kawasaki (2015). For any a, b A, let us define b a if b a and b(i) P i a(i) for all i N with b(i) a(i). Then the set of stable allocations is the unique vnm stable set with respect to the domination relation. 6 An allocation a A is Pareto efficient in the problem N, H, R if there exists no allocation b A such that br i a for all i N and bp i a for some i N. Note that, unlike stable allocations, we need preferences over allocations in order to find Pareto efficient allocations and allocations in any core, as there can be an agent who receives the same allotment at the two compared allocations. Stable allocations as well as allocations in any core are Pareto efficient because the grand coalition cannot block these allocations. When there are no externalities, a Pareto efficient allocation is stable, 7 and thus the concepts of stability and Pareto efficiency coincide. In contrast, stability is stronger than Pareto efficiency when there are externalities, as shown in the following example. 6 The set of stable allocations satisfies internal stability by definition. We can check that the relation is transitive. Hence, if an allocation a is not stable, we can eventually obtain a stable allocation b such that b a, which proves external stability. Furthermore, we can show that there is no other vnm stable set than the set of stable allocations, following the argument in the proof of Theorem 1 of Kawasaki (2015). 7 As noted, if a is not stable, there exists another allocation b such that bp ia for all i N with b(i) a(i). Without externalities, bi ia for all i N with b(i) = a(i). Thus, a is not Pareto efficient. 9

10 Example 1. Consider a housing market with N = {i 1, i 2, i 3 }, H = {h 1, h 2, h 3 }, and e = (h 1, h 2, h 3 ). 8 The agents have egocentric preferences, and their associated preferences over own-allotments are given by P i1 : h 2, h 3, h 1, Pi2 : h 3, h 1, h 2, Pi3 : h 1, h 3, h 2. Agent i 1 s preferences satisfy (h 2, h 1, h 3 )P i1 (h 2, h 3, h 1 ). Let b = (h 2, h 1, h 3 ). Since any reallocation of b makes agent i 1 worse off, b is Pareto efficient. However, b is not stable because agents i 2 and i 3 can get better off by exchanging their allotments from b. Example 1 suggests that there can be too many Pareto efficient allocations when there are externalities: if an agent has a unique most preferred allocation, it is Pareto efficient even when some other agents can become better off by reallocating their allotments from the allocation. Our analysis in the next two sections reveals that stability is a more relevant concept than Pareto efficiency in the presence of externalities. 3 Top Trading Cycles in a Housing Market with Egocentric Preferences 3.1 Top Trading Cycles Algorithm Shapley and Scarf (1974) introduce the top trading cycles (TTC) algorithm, developed by David Gale, as a method to find an allocation in the core of a housing market without externalities. Given a housing market N, H, R, e with egocentric preferences, we can apply the TTC algorithm to the related market N, H, R, e without externalities, where the algorithm proceeds as follows (see, for example, Roth, 1982 and Abdulkadiroğlu and Sönmez, 1998). Step 1. Each agent points to the owner of the house he prefers most. Since there is a finite number of agents, there exists at least one cycle of agents pointing to one another. Each agent in a cycle is assigned the endowment of the agent he points to and removed from the market. If there is at least one remaining agent, proceed to the next step. Otherwise, stop. In general, at: Step k. Each remaining agent points to the owner of the house he prefers most among the remaining houses. Each agent in a cycle is assigned the endowment of the agent he points to and removed from the market. If there is at least one remaining agent, proceed to the next step. Otherwise, stop. 8 When agents are indexed as i 1, i 2, and so on, we often describe an allocation as a list of houses where the first element in the list is assigned to i 1, the second to i 2, and so on. 10

11 Since there is a finite number of agents, the algorithm terminates within a finite number of steps. With strict preferences over houses, each agent at any step has a unique most preferred house. It is possible that multiple cycles form at a step, and in this case agents in all the cycles are removed simultaneously. Let K be the total number of steps in the algorithm, and let S k be the set of agents removed at step k, for k = 1,..., K. The algorithm proceeds in a unique way, producing an allocation as well as a partition {S 1,..., S K } of N. We call the allocation obtained by the TTC algorithm the TTC allocation of the market N, H, R, e. Note that any cycle formed at any step in the TTC algorithm is a trading cycle in the TTC allocation, and thus we call it a top trading cycle. We can regard S k as the union of top trading cycles formed at step k Properties of TTC Allocations When there are no externalities, the TTC algorithm produces the unique allocation in the core. Our first main result presents the properties that the TTC allocation possesses when there are externalities. Theorem 1. Consider a housing market N, H, R, e with egocentric preferences. The TTC allocation of N, H, R, e is stable in N, H, R and is in the ω-core of N, H, R, e. Proof. Let a A be the TTC allocation of N, H, R, e, and let {S 1,..., S K } be the partition of N obtained from the TTC algorithm. First, we show that a is stable in N, H, R. Suppose to the contrary that there exists an allocation b such that b a and b(i) P i a(i) for all i T := {i N : b(i) a(i)}. Let k be the smallest k such that S k T. Choose any i S k T. Then b(i ) P i a(i ). Since a(i ) is agent i s most preferred house at step k, i := b(i ) belongs to S k for some k < k. 10 Since i S k, there is some j S k such that a(j) = i. Since S k T =, we have b(j) = a(j). Then we have b(i ) = i = b(j) and i j, contradicting the one-to-one property of the allocation b. Next, we show that a is in the ω-core of N, H, R, e. Suppose to the contrary that there exists an allocation b and coalition T such that b dominates a via T in N, H, R, e. Let T = {i T : b(i) a(i)}. Then T is nonempty, and let k be the smallest k such that S k T. Choose any i S k T. Since b(i ) a(i ) and br i a, we have b(i ) P i a(i ). Since a(i ) is agent i s most preferred house at step k in the TTC algorithm, i := b(i ) belongs to S k for some k < k. Since b(t ) = e(t ) and i T, we have i T and thus 9 More precisely, a top trading cycle for a housing market can be defined as a trading cycle in which each agent obtains his favorite house. Then S k is the union of top trading cycles for the housing market with the remaining agents at step k. 10 With an abuse of notation, for any allocation a A, we sometimes use a(i) to refer to the owner of a(i), i.e., e 1 (a(i)), when there is no ambiguity about the endowment allocation e. 11

12 b(i ) = a(i ). Starting from i S k T, we can trace the owners of assigned houses along the top trading cycle in S k, where each agent in the cycle belongs to S k T. Hence, there is some j S k T such that a(j) = i. Then b(j) = a(j), and we have b(i ) = i = b(j) and i j, contradicting the one-to-one property of the allocation b. Theorem 1 shows that the TTC allocation is stable and is in the ω-core. We illustrate the result of Theorem 1 with Example 1. The TTC allocation of the housing market in Example 1 is a = (h 2, h 3, h 1 ), which is obtained in one step. It can be checked that both a and b = (h 2, h 1, h 3 ) are in the ω-core. Also, a is stable while b is not. So we can interpret that the TTC algorithm selects a stable allocation among allocations in the ω-core. In other words, there is a stable allocation in the ω-core, while there can be an unstable allocation in it. Since the ω-core is the smallest core given our definition of domination, Theorem 1 remains valid when we adopt any other core concept. When there are no externalities and agents may be indifferent between distinct houses, the core defined by strong domination is nonempty and may contain unstable allocations, but it contains at least one stable allocation, which can be obtained by the TTC algorithm (see Shapley and Scarf, 1974; Roth and Postlewaite, 1977). When externalities are introduced, we obtain similar results even with strict preferences over own-allotments and a core notion defined by weak domination. There can be multiple stable allocations in the ω-core, as shown by the following example. Example 2. Consider a housing market with N = {i 1, i 2, i 3 }, H = {h 1, h 2, h 3 }, and e = (h 1, h 2, h 3 ). The agents have egocentric preferences, and their associated preferences over own-allotments are given by P i1 : h 2, h 3, h 1, Pi2 : h 1, h 3, h 2, Pi3 : h 1, h 2, h 3. Agent i 1 s preferences satisfy (h 2, h 3, h 1 )P i1 (h 2, h 1, h 3 ). The TTC allocation is a = (h 2, h 1, h 3 ), and thus a is stable in N, H, R and is in the ω-core of N, H, R, e by Theorem 1. Let b = (h 2, h 3, h 1 ). It can be checked that b is also stable and is in the ω-core. In Examples 1 and 2, agent i 1 gets better off when agents i 2 and i 3 exchange their allotments from the TTC allocation a to achieve allocation b. In Example 1, both agents i 2 and i 3 get worse off by moving from a to b, and thus b can precluded by imposing stability. In Example 2, however, there are conflicting interests between agents i 2 and i 3 ; agent i 3 benefits from moving from a to b while agent i 2 loses. In this situation, we can preclude neither of a and b because there will be at least one agent who objects to a change, and it creates the possibility of multiple stable allocations in the ω-core. In order to exclude situations like Example 2, we use the following restriction on preference profiles. We say that externality creators have aligned interests under a preference 12

13 profile R if the following condition is met: for any a, b A, if there exists j N such that a(j) = b(j) and ap j b, then either ap i b for all i N with a(i) b(i) or bp i a for all i N with a(i) b(i). The condition says that, if there are agents who can create an externality to another agent by reallocating their allotments, these agents should have common preferences regarding whether to implement the reallocation or not. In other words, if some agents have conflicting interests in reallocating their allotments, then every other agent who receives the same allotment should be indifferent to such a reallocation (that is, no externalities are created by the reallocation). To get a sense of the condition, consider the preference relations over own-allotments in Example 1. Agents i 1 and i 2 have common interests in reallocating h 2 and h 3 between themselves: both prefer (a(i 1 ), a(i 2 )) = (h 2, h 3 ) to (h 3, h 2 ). In this case, agent i 3 can have a strict preference between (h 2, h 3, h 1 ) and (h 3, h 2, h 1 ). In contrast, agents i 1 and i 2 have conflicting interests in reallocating h 1 and h 3 because both prefer h 3 to h 1. Then agent i 3 should be indifferent between (h 1, h 3, h 2 ) and (h 3, h 1, h 2 ). In this way, we can check whether externality creators have aligned interests under a given preference profile. 11 The aligned interests condition limits the extent to which a group of agents exerts externalities to the other agents. 12 For instance, it precludes the preference profile in Example 2: by reallocating their allotments from a = (h 2, h 1, h 3 ), agents i 2 and i 3 can make agent i 1 better off, but they have conflicting interests regarding the change. Our second main result presents a uniqueness result. Theorem 2. Consider a housing market N, H, R, e with egocentric preferences. If externality creators have aligned interests under R, then the TTC allocation of N, H, R, e is the unique allocation that is stable in N, H, R and is in the α-core of N, H, R, e. Proof. Suppose that externality creators have aligned interests under R. Let a A be the TTC allocation of N, H, R, e, and let {S 1,..., S K } be the partition of N obtained from the TTC algorithm. Suppose to the contrary that there is an allocation b, different from a, 11 Let a 1 = (h 1, h 2, h 3), a 2 = (h 1, h 3, h 2), a 3 = (h 2, h 1, h 3), a 4 = (h 2, h 3, h 1), a 5 = (h 3, h 1, h 2), and a 6 = (h 3, h 2, h 1). Consider the following egocentric preferences over allocations: a 3P i1 a 4P i1 a 5I i1 a 6P i1 a 1I i1 a 2, a 4P i2 a 2P i2 a 3P i2 a 5P i2 a 6P i2 a 1, and a 6P i3 a 4P i3 a 1P i3 a 3P i3 a 2I i3 a 5. It can be checked that externality creators have aligned interests under this preference profile, while the associated preference relations over ownallotments are those in Example Roughly speaking, under the aligned interests condition, it is easier to have externalities when agents have diverse preferences over own-allotments. For example, agents i 1 and i 3 have opposite preferences over own-allotments in Example 1, and this allows agent i 2 to have strict preferences over allocations. In the extreme case where every agent has identical preferences over own-allotments, the aligned interests condition permits no externalities. It can also be shown that the condition precludes the case where every agent has strict preferences over allocations. 13

14 that is stable in N, H, R and is in the α-core of N, H, R, e. Let T = {i N : b(i) a(i)}. Since b a, T is nonempty. Let k be the smallest k such that S k T. Choose any i S k T. Since b(i) = a(i) for all i S 1 S k 1, we have a(i ) R i b(i ). Since b(i ) a(i ), we have a(i ) P i b(i ). Suppose that b(i) S k for all i S k. Then S k T blocks b via a in N, H, R, a, which contradicts the stability of b. Hence, there exists i S k such that b(i) / S k. Let a be an arbitrary allocation such that a (i) = a(i) for all i S k. Let T = {i N : b(i) a (i)}. Since a (i) = a(i) for all i S k and S k T, we have S k T. By egocentricity, we know that a P i b for all i S k T. Since there exists i S k such that b(i) / S k, there exists i / S k such that b(i) S k. Since S k is a union of trading cycles in a with endowment e, we have a (i) / S k for all i / S k and thus (S k ) c T. Suppose that a P i b for all i (S k ) c T. Then a P i b for all i T, contradicting the stability of b. Hence, there exists i (S k ) c T such that bp i a. Then, by the aligned interests condition, we have a I i b for all i / T. This implies that S k α-blocks b in N, H, R, e, which contradicts that b is in the α-core. Theorem 2 shows that, under the aligned interests condition, there exists a unique stable allocation in the α-core. Since the α-core is the largest core and there exists a stable allocation in any core, Theorem 2 continues to hold when we use any other core concept. Theorem 2 generalizes the existing result without externalities that the TTC allocation is the unique allocation in the core. Without externalities, the aligned interests condition is satisfied trivially, the α-core coincides with the core, and any allocation in the core is stable. The role of the aligned interests condition in obtaining the uniqueness result can be interpreted as follows. Note that TTC allocations and stable allocations depend only on preferences R over own-allotments while the notion of domination uses preferences R over allocations. So in general, the equivalence between the TTC allocation and a stable allocation in the α-core cannot be expected. But under the aligned interests condition, it suffices to know R to determine whether a stable allocation is dominated or not. Suppose that an allocation a is stable in N, H, R and that an allocation b dominates a via coalition T in N, H, R, e. Let S = {i N : b(i) a(i)}. Note that S T, and thus there exists i S such that bp i a. If bp i a for all i S, then a is not stable, which is a contradiction. Hence, there exists i S such that ap i b. Then by the aligned interests condition, bi i a for all i / S, and only the preference profile R over own-allotments plays a role. The aligned interests condition does not imply that even the ω-core is a singleton. As mentioned following Theorem 1, the two allocations a = (h 2, h 3, h 1 ) and b = (h 2, h 1, h 3 ) are in the ω-core of the housing market in Example 1, while a preference profile over allocations can be constructed to satisfy the aligned interests condition as noted in footnote 11. So imposing stability is indispensable for obtaining a uniqueness result. 14

15 Remark 2. We can obtain the uniqueness result in Theorem 2 using a weaker sufficient condition. We say that the housing market N, H, R, e exhibits aligned interests within trading cycles if the following condition is met: for any a, b A, if S is a trading cycle in a with endowment e such that ap i b for all i S with a(i) b(i) and bp i a for some i / S with a(i) b(i), then ar i b for all i S with a(i) = b(i). This condition is weaker than the previous aligned interests condition in that an agent can be affected by an externality even when the externality creators have conflicting interests, but the direction of the externality should be aligned with the preferences of the externality creators in the same trading cycle. The housing market in Example 2 does not satisfy this condition: For a = (h 2, h 1, h 3 ) and b = (h 2, h 3, h 1 ), we have bp i1 a, ap i2 b, and bp i3 a, while agents i 1 and i 2 constitute a trading cycle in a. The proof of Theorem 2 goes through under the alternative condition, when we take S k as a trading cycle, instead of a union of trading cycles, that has an overlap with T. The proof also works when we further weaken the alternative condition by requiring S to be a trading cycle in the TTC allocation and a to coincide with the TTC allocation on S. In our next result, we characterize the set of TTC allocations obtained by varying the endowment allocation e for a given house allocation problem N, H, R. It is known that, without externalities, the set of TTC allocations is equal to the set of Pareto efficient allocations (see Lemma 1 of Abdulkadiroğlu and Sönmez, 1998). However, we can expect that this result does not generalize to the case of egocentric preferences for the following two reasons. First, TTC allocations depend only on preferences R over own-allotments, whereas Pareto efficiency requires the knowledge of preferences R over allocations. Second, any TTC allocation is stable as shown in Theorem 1, while the set of stable allocations can be strictly smaller than that of Pareto efficient allocations as shown in Example 1. The following result shows that we can generate any stable allocation as a TTC allocation for some endowment allocation. Proposition 1. Consider a house allocation problem N, H, R with egocentric preferences. An allocation a A is stable in N, H, R if and only if it is the TTC allocation of N, H, R, e for some endowment allocation e A. Proof. See the Appendix. From Proposition 1, we can see that TTC allocations are more closely related to stable allocations than to Pareto efficient allocations. As mentioned following Example 1, 15

16 the concept of Pareto efficiency is too weak when there are externalities. In the proof of Proposition 1, in order to show that any stable allocation a is a TTC allocation for some endowment allocation, we set the endowment allocation as a itself. Abdulkadiroğlu and Sönmez (1998) take exactly the same approach to prove that any Pareto efficient allocation is in the core for some endowment allocation when there are no externalities. Remark 3. When there are externalities, it is not obvious how to define competitive equilibrium, as an agent s most preferred house in a budget set may depend on others choices. However, with egocentric preferences, one s favorite house is well-defined for any budget set, and so we can apply the usual concept of competitive equilibrium. Then competitive equilibria of a housing market N, H, R, e with egocentric preferences coincide with those of the related housing market N, H, R, e without externalities. Thus, a competitive allocation of a housing market N, H, R, e with egocentric preferences is unique and given by the TTC allocation (see Theorem 2 of Roth and Postlewaite, 1977). 4 TTC Mechanism and Strategy-Proofness In this section, we fix N, H, and e, and consider a scenario where each agent i reports his preferences R i and an allocation is chosen based on agents reports. Again, we assume that each agent s preferences belong to the class of egocentric preferences, and thus he is required to report an egocentric preference relation. Let R be the set of all egocentric preference relations on A. A mechanism is a rule that selects an allocation for each egocentric preference profile. That is, a mechanism can be represented by a mapping φ : R N A. We can consider a mechanism that selects the TTC allocation for each preference profile. We call it the TTC mechanism and denote it by φ T. Note that the TTC mechanism utilizes only preferences over own-allotments, and this feature can be regarded as an informational advantage of the TTC mechanism in that it suffices for agents to report their preferences over own-allotments rather than those over allocations. We can also consider a mechanism that selects an allocation in the ω-core (resp. the α-core) for each preference profile and call it an ω-core mechanism (resp. an α-core mechanism). Without externalities, a core mechanism is unique, coinciding with the TTC mechanism. However, with egocentric preferences, there can be multiple allocations in the ω-core, and thus there can be an ω-core mechanism and an α-core mechanism different from the TTC mechanism. For any coalition T N, let R T = (R i ) i T R T and R T = (R i ) i/ T R N\T denote the preference profiles of agents in T and those not in T, respectively. When T consists of a single agent i, we write R i instead of R {i}. A mechanism φ is strategy-proof if for any R R N, for any i N, and for any R i R, φ(r)r iφ(r i, R i). That is, when a mechanism is strategy-proof, no agent can gain by misreporting his preferences. A mechanism φ is 16

17 coalitionally strategy-proof if for any R R N and for any nonempty T N, there exists no R T RT such that φ(r T, R T )R i φ(r) for all i T and φ(r T, R T )P i φ(r) for some i T. In other words, when a mechanism is coalitionally strategy-proof, no coalition of agents can make at least one member better off and none worse off by jointly misreporting their preferences. Obviously, if a mechanism is coalitionally strategy-proof, it is strategyproof. It has been shown that, when there are no externalities, the TTC mechanism is strategyproof (Roth, 1982) and coalitionally strategy-proof (Moulin, 1995, Lemma 3.3). 13 In the following proposition, we extend these existing results to the case where the domain of preferences consists of egocentric preferences. Proposition 2. The TTC mechanism φ T is coalitionally strategy-proof. Proof. See the Appendix. Roth (1982) proves that no agent can obtain a more preferred house by misreporting his preferences in the TTC mechanism. Similarly, Moulin (1995, Lemma 3.3) shows that, when a group of agents misreports their preferences in the TTC mechanism, no member can obtain a more preferred house without making another member receive a less preferred house. Thus, there is no profitable manipulation by an individual agent or a group of agents in which a misreporting agent receives a better house. Without externalities, this is sufficient for (coalitional) strategy-proofness. However, when there are externalities, there is another kind of potentially profitable manipulation in which misreports by an agent or a group of agents influence others allotments while misreporting agents receive the same allotments. In the proof of Proposition 2, we show that this second kind of manipulation cannot be profitable. When a group of agents misreports their preferences in the TTC mechanism in a way that they maintain the same allotments, the allotments of the remaining agents are not affected either. 14 We say that an allocation a A is individually rational in the housing market N, H, R, e if a(i) R i e(i) for all i N. Note that individual rationality can be checked only with preferences over own-allotments and that any allocation in the α-core is individually rational Bird (1984) proves that the TTC mechanism is coalitionally strategy-proof in a weaker sense that there is no joint misreport that makes every member better off, but in a more general setting where indifferences between distinct houses are allowed. Roth (1982) also considers a setting that allows indifferences. 14 A mechanism is called nonbossy if no agent can influence others allotments without changing his own allotment (Satterthwaite and Sonnenschein, 1981). Miyagawa (2002) argues that the TTC mechanism is nonbossy. It is easy to see that, if a mechanism is nonbossy, no group of agents can influence the outsiders allotments without changing the members allotments. 15 The preference ranking of houses below one s endowment house does not play a role when we apply the TTC algorithm and when we check whether an allocation in the α-core is stable. Hence, Theorems 1 and 2 as well as the results in this section remain valid as long as each agent s preference ranking of allocations satisfies the egocentricity assumption weakly above his endowment house. 17

Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities

Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities Miho Hong and Jaeok Park January 29, 2018 Yonsei University 1 Introduction Introduction of Housing Markets Housing Markets

More information

Hierarchical Exchange Rules and the Core in. Indivisible Objects Allocation

Hierarchical Exchange Rules and the Core in. Indivisible Objects Allocation Hierarchical Exchange Rules and the Core in Indivisible Objects Allocation Qianfeng Tang and Yongchao Zhang January 8, 2016 Abstract We study the allocation of indivisible objects under the general endowment

More information

Virtual Demand and Stable Mechanisms

Virtual Demand and Stable Mechanisms Virtual Demand and Stable Mechanisms Jan Christoph Schlegel Faculty of Business and Economics, University of Lausanne, Switzerland jschlege@unil.ch Abstract We study conditions for the existence of stable

More information

Pareto-Optimal Assignments by Hierarchical Exchange

Pareto-Optimal Assignments by Hierarchical Exchange Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods Bonn 2011/11 Pareto-Optimal Assignments by Hierarchical Exchange Sophie Bade MAX PLANCK SOCIETY Preprints of the Max Planck Institute

More information

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015 Best-Reply Sets Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis This version: May 2015 Introduction The best-reply correspondence of a game the mapping from beliefs over one s opponents actions to

More information

Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano

Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano Department of Economics Brown University Providence, RI 02912, U.S.A. Working Paper No. 2002-14 May 2002 www.econ.brown.edu/faculty/serrano/pdfs/wp2002-14.pdf

More information

Yao s Minimax Principle

Yao s Minimax Principle Complexity of algorithms The complexity of an algorithm is usually measured with respect to the size of the input, where size may for example refer to the length of a binary word describing the input,

More information

A Core Concept for Partition Function Games *

A Core Concept for Partition Function Games * A Core Concept for Partition Function Games * Parkash Chander December, 2014 Abstract In this paper, we introduce a new core concept for partition function games, to be called the strong-core, which reduces

More information

Mechanisms for House Allocation with Existing Tenants under Dichotomous Preferences

Mechanisms for House Allocation with Existing Tenants under Dichotomous Preferences Mechanisms for House Allocation with Existing Tenants under Dichotomous Preferences Haris Aziz Data61 and UNSW, Sydney, Australia Phone: +61-294905909 Abstract We consider house allocation with existing

More information

Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game

Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game Parkash Chander * and Myrna Wooders May 1, 2011 Abstract We propose a new concept of core for games in extensive form and label it the γ-core of an extensive

More information

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions.

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B eb Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B.1 Proofs of results about block correlated markets. This subsection provides proofs for Propositions A1, A2, A3 and A4, and the proof of Lemma A1. Proof of Proposition

More information

Understanding Stable Matchings: A Non-Cooperative Approach

Understanding Stable Matchings: A Non-Cooperative Approach Understanding Stable Matchings: A Non-Cooperative Approach KANDORI, Michihiro, KOJIMA, Fuhito, and YASUDA, Yosuke January 8, 2013 Abstract We present a series of non-cooperative games with monotone best

More information

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core Camelia Bejan and Juan Camilo Gómez September 2011 Abstract The paper shows that the aspiration core of any TU-game coincides with

More information

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants April 2008 Abstract In this paper, we determine the optimal exercise strategy for corporate warrants if investors suffer from

More information

The Core of a Strategic Game *

The Core of a Strategic Game * The Core of a Strategic Game * Parkash Chander February, 2016 Revised: September, 2016 Abstract In this paper we introduce and study the γ-core of a general strategic game and its partition function form.

More information

Lecture Notes on The Core

Lecture Notes on The Core Lecture Notes on The Core Economics 501B University of Arizona Fall 2014 The Walrasian Model s Assumptions The following assumptions are implicit rather than explicit in the Walrasian model we ve developed:

More information

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms On Existence of Equilibria in Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms Northwestern University April 23, 2014 Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms In allocation mechanisms, agents choose messages. The messages determine

More information

Equivalence Nucleolus for Partition Function Games

Equivalence Nucleolus for Partition Function Games Equivalence Nucleolus for Partition Function Games Rajeev R Tripathi and R K Amit Department of Management Studies Indian Institute of Technology Madras, Chennai 600036 Abstract In coalitional game theory,

More information

Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case

Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case Kalyan Chatterjee Kaustav Das November 18, 2017 Abstract Chatterjee and Das (Chatterjee,K.,

More information

BOUNDS FOR BEST RESPONSE FUNCTIONS IN BINARY GAMES 1

BOUNDS FOR BEST RESPONSE FUNCTIONS IN BINARY GAMES 1 BOUNDS FOR BEST RESPONSE FUNCTIONS IN BINARY GAMES 1 BRENDAN KLINE AND ELIE TAMER NORTHWESTERN UNIVERSITY Abstract. This paper studies the identification of best response functions in binary games without

More information

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium Online Appendix to Partnerships versus Corporations: Moral Hazard, Sorting and Ownership Structure Ayca Kaya and Galina Vereshchagina Appendix A formally defines an equilibrium in our model, Appendix B

More information

Lecture B-1: Economic Allocation Mechanisms: An Introduction Warning: These lecture notes are preliminary and contain mistakes!

Lecture B-1: Economic Allocation Mechanisms: An Introduction Warning: These lecture notes are preliminary and contain mistakes! Ariel Rubinstein. 20/10/2014 These lecture notes are distributed for the exclusive use of students in, Tel Aviv and New York Universities. Lecture B-1: Economic Allocation Mechanisms: An Introduction Warning:

More information

arxiv: v3 [cs.gt] 30 May 2018

arxiv: v3 [cs.gt] 30 May 2018 An Impossibility Result for Housing Markets with Fractional Endowments arxiv:1509.03915v3 [cs.gt] 30 May 2018 Abstract Haris Aziz UNSW Sydney and Data61 (CSIRO), Australia The housing market setting constitutes

More information

Competition for goods in buyer-seller networks

Competition for goods in buyer-seller networks Rev. Econ. Design 5, 301 331 (2000) c Springer-Verlag 2000 Competition for goods in buyer-seller networks Rachel E. Kranton 1, Deborah F. Minehart 2 1 Department of Economics, University of Maryland, College

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

Notes, Comments, and Letters to the Editor. Cores and Competitive Equilibria with Indivisibilities and Lotteries

Notes, Comments, and Letters to the Editor. Cores and Competitive Equilibria with Indivisibilities and Lotteries journal of economic theory 68, 531543 (1996) article no. 0029 Notes, Comments, and Letters to the Editor Cores and Competitive Equilibria with Indivisibilities and Lotteries Rod Garratt and Cheng-Zhong

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY The Core Note: This is a only a

More information

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS 4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS Marek Rutkowski School of Mathematics and Statistics University of Sydney Semester 2, 2016 M. Rutkowski (USydney) Slides 4: Single-Period Market Models 1 / 87 General Single-Period

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium Draft chapter from An introduction to game theory by Martin J. Osborne. Version: 2002/7/23. Martin.Osborne@utoronto.ca http://www.economics.utoronto.ca/osborne Copyright 1995 2002 by Martin J. Osborne.

More information

Stable Many-to-Many Matchings with Contracts

Stable Many-to-Many Matchings with Contracts Stable Many-to-Many Matchings with Contracts Bettina-Elisabeth Klaus Markus Walzl Working Paper 09-046 Copyright 2008 by Bettina-Elisabeth Klaus and Markus Walzl Working papers are in draft form. This

More information

Outside Options in Neutral Allocation of Discrete Resources

Outside Options in Neutral Allocation of Discrete Resources Outside Options in Neutral Allocation of Discrete Resources Marek Pycia M. Utku Ünver This Draft: December 2016, First Draft: May 2007 Abstract Serial dictatorships have emerged as natural direct mechanisms

More information

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. 14.126 GAME THEORY MIHAI MANEA Department of Economics, MIT, 1. Existence and Continuity of Nash Equilibria Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. Theorem 1. Suppose

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. Bidding With Securities: Comment. Yeon-Koo Che Jinwoo Kim

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. Bidding With Securities: Comment. Yeon-Koo Che Jinwoo Kim Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Bidding With Securities: Comment Yeon-Koo Che Jinwoo Kim Discussion Paper No.: 0809-10 Department of Economics Columbia University New

More information

CATEGORICAL SKEW LATTICES

CATEGORICAL SKEW LATTICES CATEGORICAL SKEW LATTICES MICHAEL KINYON AND JONATHAN LEECH Abstract. Categorical skew lattices are a variety of skew lattices on which the natural partial order is especially well behaved. While most

More information

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion Davit Khantadze September 30, 017 Abstract We are interested in optimal signals for the sender when the decision maker (receiver) has to make two separate decisions.

More information

Econ 618: Topic 11 Introduction to Coalitional Games

Econ 618: Topic 11 Introduction to Coalitional Games Econ 618: Topic 11 Introduction to Coalitional Games Sunanda Roy 1 Coalitional games with transferable payoffs, the Core Consider a game with a finite set of players. A coalition is a nonempty subset of

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren October, 2013 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Antino Kim Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington Bloomington, IN 47405, U.S.A.

Antino Kim Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington Bloomington, IN 47405, U.S.A. THE INVISIBLE HAND OF PIRACY: AN ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF THE INFORMATION-GOODS SUPPLY CHAIN Antino Kim Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington Bloomington, IN 47405, U.S.A. {antino@iu.edu}

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH http://www.kier.kyoto-u.ac.jp/index.html Discussion Paper No. 657 The Buy Price in Auctions with Discrete Type Distributions Yusuke Inami

More information

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Computer Science Technical Reports Graduate Center 2009 TR-2009011: Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions Sergei Artemov Follow this and additional works

More information

Game Theory: Normal Form Games

Game Theory: Normal Form Games Game Theory: Normal Form Games Michael Levet June 23, 2016 1 Introduction Game Theory is a mathematical field that studies how rational agents make decisions in both competitive and cooperative situations.

More information

Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data

Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data a thesis submitted to the department of industrial engineering and the institute of engineering and sciences of bilkent university

More information

Working Paper Series. This paper can be downloaded without charge from:

Working Paper Series. This paper can be downloaded without charge from: Working Paper Series This paper can be downloaded without charge from: http://www.richmondfed.org/publications/ COALITION-PROOF ALLOCATIONS IN ADVERSE SELECTION ECONOMIES Jeffrey M. Lacker and John A.

More information

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies Chapter 10 Elimination by Mixed Strategies The notions of dominance apply in particular to mixed extensions of finite strategic games. But we can also consider dominance of a pure strategy by a mixed strategy.

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

Envy-free and efficient minimal rights: recursive. no-envy

Envy-free and efficient minimal rights: recursive. no-envy Envy-free and efficient minimal rights: recursive no-envy Diego Domínguez Instituto Tecnológico Autónomo de México Antonio Nicolò University of Padova This version, July 14, 2008 This paper was presented

More information

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 20 November 13 2008 So far, we ve considered matching markets in settings where there is no money you can t necessarily pay someone to marry

More information

Best response cycles in perfect information games

Best response cycles in perfect information games P. Jean-Jacques Herings, Arkadi Predtetchinski Best response cycles in perfect information games RM/15/017 Best response cycles in perfect information games P. Jean Jacques Herings and Arkadi Predtetchinski

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 9, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria

More information

Parkash Chander and Myrna Wooders

Parkash Chander and Myrna Wooders SUBGAME PERFECT COOPERATION IN AN EXTENSIVE GAME by Parkash Chander and Myrna Wooders Working Paper No. 10-W08 June 2010 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS VANDERBILT UNIVERSITY NASHVILLE, TN 37235 www.vanderbilt.edu/econ

More information

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Research Department Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring Harold L. Cole and Narayana Kocherlakota Working Paper 604 September 2000 Cole: U.C.L.A. and Federal Reserve

More information

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership Attila Tasnádi Department of Mathematics, Budapest University of Economic Sciences and Public Administration, H-1093 Budapest, Fővám tér 8, Hungary

More information

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Chapter 5 Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Until now we implicitly adopted a view that a Nash equilibrium is a desirable outcome of a strategic game. In this chapter we consider two alternative

More information

3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure

3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure Mathematical Models in Economics and Finance Topic 3 Fundamental theorem of asset pricing 3.1 Law of one price and Arrow securities 3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure 3.3 Valuation

More information

Internet Trading Mechanisms and Rational Expectations

Internet Trading Mechanisms and Rational Expectations Internet Trading Mechanisms and Rational Expectations Michael Peters and Sergei Severinov University of Toronto and Duke University First Version -Feb 03 April 1, 2003 Abstract This paper studies an internet

More information

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments Kentaro Tomoeda October 31, 215 Abstract This article analyzes the implementability of efficient investments for two commonly used mechanisms in single-item

More information

Optimal group strategyproof cost sharing

Optimal group strategyproof cost sharing Optimal group strategyproof cost sharing Ruben Juarez Department of Economics, University of Hawaii 2424 Maile Way, Saunders Hall 542, Honolulu, HI 96822 (email: rubenj@hawaii.edu) May 7, 2018 Abstract

More information

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 24, November 28 Outline 1 Sequential Trade and Arrow Securities 2 Radner Equilibrium 3 Equivalence

More information

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Shingo Ishiguro Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University 1-7 Machikaneyama, Toyonaka, Osaka 560-0043, Japan August 2002

More information

COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS

COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS DAN HATHAWAY AND SCOTT SCHNEIDER Abstract. We discuss combinatorial conditions for the existence of various types of reductions between equivalence

More information

The efficiency of fair division

The efficiency of fair division The efficiency of fair division Ioannis Caragiannis, Christos Kaklamanis, Panagiotis Kanellopoulos, and Maria Kyropoulou Research Academic Computer Technology Institute and Department of Computer Engineering

More information

A Decentralized Learning Equilibrium

A Decentralized Learning Equilibrium Paper to be presented at the DRUID Society Conference 2014, CBS, Copenhagen, June 16-18 A Decentralized Learning Equilibrium Andreas Blume University of Arizona Economics ablume@email.arizona.edu April

More information

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions? March 3, 215 Steven A. Matthews, A Technical Primer on Auction Theory I: Independent Private Values, Northwestern University CMSEMS Discussion Paper No. 196, May, 1995. This paper is posted on the course

More information

Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games

Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games Michael Ummels ummels@logic.rwth-aachen.de FSTTCS 2006 Michael Ummels Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction 1 / 15 Infinite

More information

Lecture 5: Iterative Combinatorial Auctions

Lecture 5: Iterative Combinatorial Auctions COMS 6998-3: Algorithmic Game Theory October 6, 2008 Lecture 5: Iterative Combinatorial Auctions Lecturer: Sébastien Lahaie Scribe: Sébastien Lahaie In this lecture we examine a procedure that generalizes

More information

Equilibrium payoffs in finite games

Equilibrium payoffs in finite games Equilibrium payoffs in finite games Ehud Lehrer, Eilon Solan, Yannick Viossat To cite this version: Ehud Lehrer, Eilon Solan, Yannick Viossat. Equilibrium payoffs in finite games. Journal of Mathematical

More information

Finite Population Dynamics and Mixed Equilibria *

Finite Population Dynamics and Mixed Equilibria * Finite Population Dynamics and Mixed Equilibria * Carlos Alós-Ferrer Department of Economics, University of Vienna Hohenstaufengasse, 9. A-1010 Vienna (Austria). E-mail: Carlos.Alos-Ferrer@Univie.ac.at

More information

Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items

Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items Nir Shabbat - 05305311 December 5, 2012 Introduction The paper I read is called Approximate Revenue Maximization with Multiple Items by Sergiu Hart

More information

Envy-Free Configurations in the Market Economy

Envy-Free Configurations in the Market Economy Envy-Free Configurations in the Market Economy Koichi Tadenuma Faculty of Economics, Hitotsubashi University Kunitachi, Tokyo 186-8601, Japan Email: tadenuma@econ.hit-u.ac.jp Yongsheng Xu Department of

More information

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010 May 19, 2010 1 Introduction Scope of Agent preferences Utility Functions 2 Game Representations Example: Game-1 Extended Form Strategic Form Equivalences 3 Reductions Best Response Domination 4 Solution

More information

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let April 29, 2015 "A Characterization of Efficient, Bayesian Incentive Compatible Mechanisms," by S. R. Williams. Economic Theory 14, 155-180 (1999). AcommonresultinBayesianmechanismdesignshowsthatexpostefficiency

More information

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models 1.1 Law of one price and Arrow securities 1.2 No-arbitrage theory and

More information

A Market Clearing Solution for Social Lending

A Market Clearing Solution for Social Lending A Market Clearing Solution for Social Lending Ning Chen Arpita Ghosh Division of Mathematical Sciences, Nanyang Technological University, Singapore. ningc@ntu.edu.sg Yahoo! Research, Santa Clara, CA, USA.

More information

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk Kenneth Mirkin and Marek Pycia June 2015. Preliminary Draft. Abstract We study directed search in a frictional two-sided matching market in which each seller

More information

TABLEAU-BASED DECISION PROCEDURES FOR HYBRID LOGIC

TABLEAU-BASED DECISION PROCEDURES FOR HYBRID LOGIC TABLEAU-BASED DECISION PROCEDURES FOR HYBRID LOGIC THOMAS BOLANDER AND TORBEN BRAÜNER Abstract. Hybrid logics are a principled generalization of both modal logics and description logics. It is well-known

More information

Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons

Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons Andrew McLennan September 4, 2014 I. Introduction Economics 6030/8030 Microeconomics B Second Semester 2014 Lecture 6 Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons A. One of the most famous and influential

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Leonardo Felli 7 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Contract Theory has become only recently a subfield of Economics. As the name suggest the main object of the analysis is a contract. Therefore

More information

Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction. By: Stephen P. Holland

Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction. By: Stephen P. Holland Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction By: Stephen P. Holland Holland, Stephen P. (2003) Extraction Capacity and the Optimal Order of Extraction, Journal of Environmental Economics and

More information

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Kang Rong School of Economics, Shanghai University of Finance and Economic (SHUFE) August, 202 Abstract I analyze an alternating-offer model that integrates

More information

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Juyan Zhang and Yi Zhang February 20, 2011 Abstract We investigate hold-up in the case of both simultaneous and sequential investment. We show that if

More information

Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity

Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity Jan Werner December 2013, revised August 2014. Abstract: This paper is about (non) participation in efficient risk sharing in an economy where agents have

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros

Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros Midterm #1, February 3, 2017 Name (use a pen): Student ID (use a pen): Signature (use a pen): Rules: Duration of the exam: 50 minutes. By

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Leonardo Felli 9 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3 Consider now a different cause for the failure of the Coase Theorem: the presence of transaction costs. Of course for this to be an interesting

More information

Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market. Jeffrey Gao

Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market. Jeffrey Gao Efficiency and Herd Behavior in a Signalling Market Jeffrey Gao ABSTRACT This paper extends a model of herd behavior developed by Bikhchandani and Sharma (000) to establish conditions for varying levels

More information

Economics and Computation

Economics and Computation Economics and Computation ECON 425/56 and CPSC 455/555 Professor Dirk Bergemann and Professor Joan Feigenbaum Lecture I In case of any questions and/or remarks on these lecture notes, please contact Oliver

More information

BAYESIAN GAMES: GAMES OF INCOMPLETE INFORMATION

BAYESIAN GAMES: GAMES OF INCOMPLETE INFORMATION BAYESIAN GAMES: GAMES OF INCOMPLETE INFORMATION MERYL SEAH Abstract. This paper is on Bayesian Games, which are games with incomplete information. We will start with a brief introduction into game theory,

More information

On the existence of coalition-proof Bertrand equilibrium

On the existence of coalition-proof Bertrand equilibrium Econ Theory Bull (2013) 1:21 31 DOI 10.1007/s40505-013-0011-7 RESEARCH ARTICLE On the existence of coalition-proof Bertrand equilibrium R. R. Routledge Received: 13 March 2013 / Accepted: 21 March 2013

More information

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we 6 Mixed Strategies In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we postponed discussing the option that a player may choose to randomize between several of his pure strategies.

More information

FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 1134

FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 1134 S"l - ^ FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 1134 A Note On Nondictationai Conditions and the Relations Between Choice Mechanisms and Social Welfare Functions Zvi Ritz Ccliege of Commerce and Business Administration

More information

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation Journal of Economics and Finance Volume 24 Number 1 Spring 2000 Pages 56-63 Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation Veronika Grimm and Ulrich Schmidt* Abstract This paper considers the classical independent

More information

Applying Risk Theory to Game Theory Tristan Barnett. Abstract

Applying Risk Theory to Game Theory Tristan Barnett. Abstract Applying Risk Theory to Game Theory Tristan Barnett Abstract The Minimax Theorem is the most recognized theorem for determining strategies in a two person zerosum game. Other common strategies exist such

More information

Optimal Delay in Committees

Optimal Delay in Committees Optimal Delay in Committees ETTORE DAMIANO University of Toronto LI, HAO University of British Columbia WING SUEN University of Hong Kong July 4, 2012 Abstract. We consider a committee problem in which

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 14, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria Mixed Strategies

More information

While the story has been different in each case, fundamentally, we ve maintained:

While the story has been different in each case, fundamentally, we ve maintained: Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 22 November 20 2008 What the Hatfield and Milgrom paper really served to emphasize: everything we ve done so far in matching has really, fundamentally,

More information

MATH 121 GAME THEORY REVIEW

MATH 121 GAME THEORY REVIEW MATH 121 GAME THEORY REVIEW ERIN PEARSE Contents 1. Definitions 2 1.1. Non-cooperative Games 2 1.2. Cooperative 2-person Games 4 1.3. Cooperative n-person Games (in coalitional form) 6 2. Theorems and

More information

Optimal Allocation of Policy Limits and Deductibles

Optimal Allocation of Policy Limits and Deductibles Optimal Allocation of Policy Limits and Deductibles Ka Chun Cheung Email: kccheung@math.ucalgary.ca Tel: +1-403-2108697 Fax: +1-403-2825150 Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Calgary,

More information

THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET

THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET MICHAEL PINSKER Abstract. We calculate the number of unary clones (submonoids of the full transformation monoid) containing the

More information

ABattleofInformedTradersandtheMarket Game Foundations for Rational Expectations Equilibrium

ABattleofInformedTradersandtheMarket Game Foundations for Rational Expectations Equilibrium ABattleofInformedTradersandtheMarket Game Foundations for Rational Expectations Equilibrium James Peck The Ohio State University During the 19th century, Jacob Little, who was nicknamed the "Great Bear

More information