Endogenous Minimum Participation in International Environmental Agreements: An Experimental Analysis

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Endogenous Minimum Participation in International Environmental Agreements: An Experimental Analysis"

Transcription

1 January 2014 Endogenous Minimum Participation in International Environmental Agreements: An Experimental Analysis David M. McEvoy (corresponding author) Department of Economics Appalachian State University 3108 Raley Hall, 416 Howard Street Boone, NC Phone: Todd L. Cherry Department of Economics Appalachian State University 3095 Raley Hall, 416 Howard Street Boone, NC Phone: John K. Stranlund Department of Resource Economics University of Massachusetts at Amherst 222 Stockbridge Hall Amherst, MA Phone: Abstract: Most international treaties require a minimum number of countries to ratify the treaty before it enters into force. Despite the wide-spread use of this mechanism, little is known about its effectiveness at facilitating cooperation. In this paper we analyze a coalition formation game that includes an endogenously determined minimum participation constraint and then test the theoretical predictions using a series of economic experiments. We demonstrate theoretically that players will vote to implement an efficient coalition size as the membership requirement and this coalition will form. This is true regardless of whether the efficient coalition is the grand coalition or some smaller coalition. Our experimental tests of the theory demonstrate that the minimum participation mechanism is highly effective at facilitating cooperation when efficiency requires the formation of the grand coalition. However, when efficiency requires only a subset of the players to join and provide the public good, profitable coalitions are deliberately blocked in a significant number of trials. While this result is not consistent with a model of players who are only concerned with material payoffs, it is consistent with a model that includes players with inequality preferences. 1

2 1. Introduction Almost all international environmental agreements (IEAs) require a minimum number of countries to ratify the agreement before it enters into force. If the minimum membership condition is met, as well as other accompanying conditions, the treaty becomes active and ratifying countries are bound to their commitments. If the condition is not met, the treaty never enters into force and affected countries are not bound by its provisions. Minimum membership requirements are standard in treaties that address global environmental issues, and Barrett (2003, pp ) provides a thorough examination of membership requirements in international environmental agreements. For example, the Kyoto Protocol to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change required ratification by at least 55 parties prior to its entry into force in February Similarly, the Montreal Protocol on Substances that Deplete the Ozone Layer required at least 11 countries to ratify it before it entered into force in Examples of minimum membership requirements extend to treaties that address international risk and security, such as the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons, which required the ratification of the five nuclear nations (at that time) plus 40 additional nations. The Chemical Weapons Convention required ratification by at least 65 nations before it entered into force in While many treaties require ratification by a subset of affected parties to enter into force, some require all parties to join. For example, the Convention for the Protection of the Marine Environment of the North-East Atlantic required accession of all contracting parties, and the Treaty of Lisbon required ratification by all European Union member states. Because of their wide-spread use in international agreements, there is a small gametheoretic literature on the role of minimum membership requirements. Black et al. (1992) find that an exogenously imposed minimum membership requirement can increase participation with an international environmental agreement. A similar finding is discussed in Carraro and Siniscalco (1992). Clearly, however, national sovereignty requires that all provisions of international treaties, including membership requirements, be determined endogenously by affected parties. Carraro et al. (2009) provide an analysis of endogenous minimum participation requirements in IEAs, and find that the mechanism increases the size of cooperative coalitions 1 Both the Kyoto and Montreal protocols included an extra provision to ensure participants represented a minimum level of global emissions. Members to the Kyoto Protocol had to represent at least 55 percent of the total 1990 greenhouse gas emissions. Similarly, the Montreal Protocol required representation of at least two-thirds of the total 1986 consumption of ozone-depleting substances. 2

3 relative to the non-cooperative baseline. Particularly relevant for our study, Carraro et al. also find that endogenous minimum participation requirements can lead to efficient outcomes. 2 However, empirical data on the effectiveness of minimum participation constraints in IEAs is absent because of the lack of counterfactuals and controls necessary for careful analysis. Consequently, we use laboratory experiments to evaluate the effectiveness of endogenously determined minimum requirements in motivating coalition formation to provide public goods. Of course, laboratory experiments, like the game-theoretic models they stem from, dramatically simplify the international negotiation process. However, the experimental approach allows us to examine the performance of particular institutions in a controlled environment. Since international environmental agreements are designed to address collective action problems between resource users, the same fundamental tensions that exist between countries can be simulated in a laboratory environment, and the results of experiments can shed light on how institutional rules, in this case minimum participation rules, affect coalition formation. 3 We begin by developing a theoretical model of endogenous agreement formation to provide a public good, including the endogenous determination of a minimum membership requirement. Our model is a simplified version of the one in Carraro et al., yielding clearer predictions so that it is amenable to tests with experimental data. The game we analyze consists of two stages. The first stage is unique in the experimental coalition formation literature in that individuals vote on a minimum membership requirement. In the second stage, each individual decides whether they will join a coalition to provide the public good and a coalition forms if the membership requirement is met. We demonstrate that expected-payoff-maximizing individuals will choose to adopt the minimum membership requirement that is equal to the efficient coalition size, and that this coalition will form. This theoretical result is robust to whether the efficient agreement is the grand coalition or a smaller coalition. We designed our laboratory experiments to test these predictions. Results show that when efficiency requires all players to join an agreement, subjects adopted the efficient minimum membership requirement about 75 percent of the time. Conditional on subjects 2 A recent working paper by Weikard et al. (2009) extends the theoretical analysis by Carraro et al. (2009) to include heterogeneous agents under different sharing rules. Harstad (2006) models coalitions of heterogeneous agents that contribute to a public good and derives optimal participation rules as well as solving for political equilibria (i.e., Condorcet winners). 3 The use of laboratory experiments in the evaluation of public policies is well established (Plott 1987; Shogren and Hurley 1999; Cason and Plott 1996; Stranlund et al. 2011), and experiments are particularly well suited to evaluate the effectiveness of different voluntary institutions. 3

4 adopting the efficient minimum membership requirement, efficient agreements formed over 90 percent of the time. Consequently, in these cases we observe significantly higher efficiency than other coalition formation experiments that do not include endogenous minimum membership requirements (e.g., Kosfeld et al. 2009; Dannenberg et al. 2010; McEvoy et al. 2011). The results were not as positive when efficiency required only 50 percent participation. While subjects still adopted the efficient minimum membership requirement about 75 percent of the time, the efficient coalition formed just over half of the time. Interestingly, the efficient coalition was blocked in about one-third of the cases in which it was adopted as the membership condition. While this is inconsistent with a theoretical model of individuals with standard preferences, we demonstrate that this behavior is consistent with a theory that allows for preferences concerning inequality in the manner of Fehr and Schmidt (1999). 4 The lesson for international environmental policy making is clear: endogenous minimum participation requirements are effective at achieving high levels of cooperation, but they may be significantly less effective when the participation requirements allow for freeriders. Although no experimental research has investigated the effectiveness of minimum membership requirements directly, a significant literature has done so indirectly with analyses of minimum contributing sets in public good games (e.g., Rapoport 1985; Erev and Rapoport 1990; Cadsby and Maynes 1999; Cooper and Stockman 2002; McEvoy 2010). In these games, all individual contributions to the public good are returned if there are too few contributors. In contrast with our game, minimum contributing sets are not determined by the players themselves. A related literature on endogenous institution formation in public goods games has received much attention recently. Most of this literature explores the formation of institutions that govern all players (e.g., Walker et al. 2000; Gurerk et al. 2006; Tyran and Feld 2006; Kroll et al. 2007; Sutter et al. 2010). Typically, however, international treaties are formed to restrict the behavior of only participating nations. A handful of recent studies that are motivated by international treaty formation examine coalition formation in public goods games (e.g., Kosfeld et al. 2009; Dannenberg et al. 2010; McEvoy et al. 2011; Barrett and Dannenberg 2012), but none consider endogenous minimum membership requirements. 5 4 Others have conjectured that preferences over inequality might play important roles in international cooperation because all treaties must tackle issues of equity (Ringius et al. 2002; Lange and Vogt 2003). 5 The sequence of decisions in some of the coalition formation experiments differs significantly from the sequence of decisions in international treaty formation. For example, in the experiments of Kosfeld et al. (2009), players first 4

5 The remainder of the paper proceeds as follows. In the next section we develop our theoretical model and derive its predictions. In section 3 we describe the experimental design we use to test these predictions. We present the results of the experiments in section 4 and conclude in section Theory Consider a game in which n players decide whether to contribute a single unit to a public good. Our model is a variant of the seminal model by Barrett (1994). Let the number of individuals who contribute to the public good (and the total supply of the public good) be s. Let b > 0 denote the shared benefit players receive from contributions to the public good up to s n and let c > 0 denote the individual cost of contributing. The basic payoff function of a player that contributes to the public good is π i = A + bs c, for s s, [1] where A is a positive constant. Assume that c > b so that no player would contribute to the public good in a standard, non-cooperative Nash equilibrium. However, suppose that collective welfare is maximized when s individuals contribute their units to the public good. In the typical coalition formation game, collective welfare is maximized when everyone contributes; that is, when s = n. However, we also allow for the possibility that it is efficient that the public good be provided by a coalition that is smaller than the grand coalition. We assume a simple case of this in which individual contributions yield a return of b up to an aggregate level and additional contributions yield a return of zero. For example, abatement activities that move emissions levels below the absorptive capacity of the natural environment will not yield additional environmental benefits. Examples of this also include any project for which contributions in excess of what is required to provide the good do not yield public benefits. In either case, if s is efficient, then n( A + bs ) cs > na, which requires nb > c. Given the motivation for collective action to provide the public good, suppose that the players are able to form a cooperative coalition in a two-stage game. In the first stage (the voting decide whether to join a coalition, and then the members vote on whether to contribute to the public good. Hence, in their analysis members of a coalition decide what the coalition should accomplish after they make their participation decision. In contrast, the players in our study understand ex ante what they are required to do in a coalition before they make their decision to join or not. This corresponds more closely to the actual process of treaty formation, where countries typically decide the commitments of the coalition members and what triggers entry into force before they decide whether to ratify (join). 5

6 stage), all players vote on the minimum number of members required for a coalition to form. Players cannot vote for a membership requirement equal to zero and they cannot opt out of this vote. We call the outcome of this vote the minimum membership requirement. In our experiments we implement a plurality voting rule so that the number that receives the most votes becomes the membership requirement. 6 In stage two of the coalition formation game (the coalition stage), the players decide independently and sequentially whether or not to join the coalition. 7 The order in which the players make their join/not join decisions is unknown in the voting stage of the game, and each potential order is equally likely. This order is revealed to the players in the coalition stage. Decisions to join or not join are observed by all other players in the second stage. 8 If enough players join so that the membership requirement is met, the coalition forms and its members provide their units of the public good. Throughout we call such a coalition an effective coalition. Those that do not join an effective coalition do not provide their units of the public good (because c > b), but still benefit from its provision. If the minimum membership requirement is not met, an effective coalition does not form and no player contributes to the public good. We look for a subgame perfect equilibrium for this game, consisting of individual votes for the minimum membership requirement in the first stage of the game and decisions to join or not join a coalition in the second stage. An equilibrium is found by backward induction, so we start by describing the coalition stage. At this point in the game a minimum membership requirement has been chosen. Denote the membership requirement as s p. Using [1], those who decide to join a coalition with s members earn: A + bs c for s s if s sp; m π ( s) = A+ bs c for s> s if s sp; A if s< sp. [2] 6 A plurality voting rule is often implemented in local and national elections to determine a single winner when there are more than two candidates. See Myerson and Weber (1993) for an analysis of voting equilibria under plurality voting rules. 7 Although our game is motivated by the model of Carraro et al. (2009), it is not a special case of their model. This is primarily due to the facts that they require unanimity in the vote for the membership requirement and players make their decision to join an agreement simultaneously. 8 In fact, having the players decide to join or not in sequence and with perfect information about these decisions is a reasonable description of the actual process of treaty accessions. Differences in the lengths of national debates about the decision to ratify a treaty and differing positions of a treaty on national legislative agendas imply that ratification decisions must be sequential. Moreover, the decision to ratify a treaty or not tends to be very public. 6

7 Throughout the superscript m indicates the player is a member of a coalition. Nonmembers, identified by the superscript nm, earn: π nm A + bs for s s if s sp; ( s) = A + bs for s > s if s sp; A if s< sp. [3] From [2] and [3] it is clear that when an effective coalition forms, nonmembers earn strictly higher profits than members, because they enjoy the benefits of public good contributions without incurring the cost of contributing. However, if the minimum membership requirement is not met, both members and nonmembers earn their noncooperative payoff A. Players will join an effective coalition only if it is profitable for them to do so in the sense that they earn at least as much in the coalition as they would if no coalition formed. Thus, a m coalition is profitable for its members if and only if π ( s s s ) = A + bs c A. Assume m throughout that a coalition with s members is strictly profitable so that π ( s s s ) > A, or m rather, bs c > 0. Note from [2] that π ( s s s p ) is increasing in s up to s and then is constant. Combined with b< c, these relations imply that there exist coalition sizes that are strictly greater than one and weakly less than s that are profitable. The smallest of these profitable coalitions is: m { π p } { } smin = min s ( s s s ) = A = min s s c/ b, [4] where smin (1, s]. For an effective coalition to form in the second stage of the game both the membership requirement and the profitability requirement must be satisfied. The players make their decisions to join or not join sequentially. Define a critical player as one whose choice to not join a coalition prevents the coalition from forming. That is, a player is critical if and only if n s players have already opted out of the coalition. Suppose at first p p p that the membership requirement is sp s min. A critical player in this situation will always choose to join a coalition of s p members. To see why, note first that if a critical player refuses to join a coalition then no coalition will form and the player will earn A. However, the player earns a higher payoff if he is part of a profitable coalition. So, if a critical player joins a coalition then he either earns this higher payoff if all the other critical players also join, or he earns the 7

8 payoff A if one of the other critical players refuses to join and a coalition does not form. Therefore, when sp s a critical player will always join a coalition because he cannot be min worse off by doing so and he may be strictly better off. Since all critical players will join a coalition, a noncritical player would never join, because it is always more profitable to stay out of a profitable coalition. Therefore, given sp s min, the outcome of the second stage coalition game is that an effective coalition of s p individuals will form. Moreover, since nonmembers earn strictly higher payoffs than members, the first n s players in the sequence will decide to not p join the coalition and the last s p players will decide to join. In the second stage of the game, all members of the coalition make their contributions to the public good, while the remaining players contribute nothing. Now suppose that the membership requirement is s p < s. In this case, a critical player will choose to not join because he would be joining an unprofitable coalition. Since no critical player will join a coalition if sp < s, the outcome of the second stage coalition game in this min case is that an effective coalition will not form and all players contribute nothing to the public good. To sum up, the equilibrium of the second stage coalition formation game is a coalition size and provision of the public good s such that p min s = s if sp smin and s = 0 if sp < smin. In the first case the first n s players to decide whether or not to join the coalition choose not to, while the last s players join the coalition. 9 Now let us examine the determination of the minimum membership requirement s p in the voting (first) stage of the game. Following Carraro et al. (2009), we assume that players vote 9 Others have examined sequential decision making in threshold public good games. Erev and Rapoport (1990) and Cooper and Stockman (2002) derive similar equilibria to ours in threshold public good games in which players are assigned the order in which they must decide whether to contribute to a public good. In their studies a threshold is specified exogenously, which is referred to as the minimum contributing set. We noted the similarity between minimum contributing sets and minimum membership requirements for international treaties in the introduction. McEvoy (2010) explores the endogenous order of sequential decisions in public good games and finds that the timing of participation decisions is sensitive to the threshold in these games. In particular, he finds that subjects are more likely to rush to opt out of voluntary coalitions when the free-riding payoff is larger. 8

9 sincerely in the sense that they vote for the membership requirement that gives them the highest expected payoff from the perspective of the first stage of the game. 10 From our description of the coalition stage of the game, if the membership requirement is not less than the minimum profitable coalition, a player s payoff is determined by his position in the order in which the players make their decisions whether to join a coalition. Recall that this sequence is unknown in the first stage of the game. Hence, a player that expects an effective coalition of s players to form in the second stage evaluates the probability that he will be a member of this coalition as s/ n and the probability that he will not be a member as ( n s)/ n. His expected payoff from the perspective of the first stage of the game is then: m ( ) π ( ) nm vs () = s/ n () s + ( n s)/ nπ () s. [5] Remove the s p constraint from [2] and [3], substitute the results into [5], and differentiate with respect to s to obtain: b c/ n> 0, for s s; v () s = c/ n < 0, for s > s. Equation [6] indicates that the expected payoff of every player is maximized at the efficient coalition size. Given that all players vote sincerely in the first stage of the game, each of them votes to implement the efficient coalition as the minimum membership requirement. That is, sp = s. profitable, Moving ahead to the coalition formation stage, since the efficient coalition size is s = s s. Therefore, the coalition s = s will form. Obviously, if s = n, then all p min players will join the coalition. If s < n, then the first n s players to make their join/not join decision will choose to not join, while the last s players join the coalition. 11 The main prediction of the theory is that the endogenous determination of a minimum membership requirement allows players to form an efficient coalition to provide a public good. In the next section we present our experimental design used to test this prediction under two scenarios; one in which efficiency requires full participation (i.e., the grand coalition) and one in which [6] 10 Palfrey (1984) and Osborne and Slivinski (1996) also analyze games given sincere voting. 11 Carraro et al. (2009) provide sufficient conditions for their game to result in the formation of the grand coalition. Our game satisfies those sufficient conditions. Carraro et al. do not examine the case in which the efficient coalition is smaller than the grand coalition. 9

10 efficiency requires only partial participation. 3. Experiments Following the theoretical model, our experiments have two stages, a voting stage and a coalition formation stage. The context of the experiment is fairly generic; subjects decide whether to join a coalition (called an agreement) with its members making a discrete choice to contribute to the public good (called a public account). We implement two experimental treatments that differ according to the returns to individual contributions to the public good. In one treatment the marginal return to contributions is constant so that the efficient coalition is the grand coalition. In the other treatment, the marginal return to public good contributions is constant up to an aggregate level and then zero so that the efficient coalition is smaller than the grand coalition. We chose parameter values of n = 6, A = 10, and c = 10 for each treatment. In one treatment the marginal return to all individual contributions was set at b = 4.5. Since nb c > 0 for all contributions, the efficient coalition in this case is six individuals ( s = 6 ). In the other treatment, b = 4.5 for contributions up to three units and then zero after three units. The efficient coalition size in this case is three individuals ( s = 3 ). Plugging our parameter values into equation [4] reveals a minimum profitable coalition size of three members. Therefore, in both treatments, coalitions of three or more are profitable for the members. All sessions were run at the experimental economics laboratory at [insert university] using software specifically designed for this experiment. Subjects were recruited from the undergraduate and graduate student populations. Two sessions were implemented for each of the treatments. In each session, three groups of six subjects were in the lab. These groups of six were reshuffled each period throughout the experiment, which lasted 20 periods. 12 For each treatment we have 720 individual-level observations, which include their votes for the membership requirement in the first stage and their decisions to join a coalition in the second stage. We also have 120 group-level observations on coalition formation, public good provision and overall group efficiency. The sessions lasted for roughly 1 hour, subjects were paid their cumulative earnings and earned $16.50 on average (20 experimental dollars = $1). 12 To mitigate reputation effects, we follow the literature with subject anonymity and a stranger design. Though imperfect, the stranger design ensured no group was repeated, which was known by subjects. Anonymity conditions did not allow subjects to track other subjects or their decisions. With similar anonymity conditions, Fehr and Gächter (2000) find behavior is equivalent across imperfect and perfect stranger designs. 10

11 In the first stage of the experiments, subjects simultaneously voted on the minimum membership requirement for a coalition to form in the second stage. The membership requirement that received the most votes was implemented in the second stage of the game. Ties were settled by a random draw. In the coalition formation stage, each subject decided whether or not to join the coalition. Following the theoretical model, these decisions were made sequentially under perfect information. Each of the six subjects in a group was randomly assigned an order in which to make decisions, and this order changed each period. 13 For example, if a subject was assigned an order number of three, then she had to wait for the first two players to submit their choices before she could make her decision. Once a subject made their choice they could not change it. During this stage, all subjects were informed about whether the subjects before them joined the agreement or did not join the agreement. They were also constantly reminded of the membership requirement for the agreement to form. Therefore, each player knew with certainty whether their participation decision was critical for the coalition to form. If enough players joined the coalition to satisfy the minimum membership requirement, then the coalition formed and those that joined contributed to the public good. Those who did not join did not contribute. If too few subjects joined the coalition to satisfy the membership requirement, then no coalition formed and no one contributed to the public good. 4. Results Our experimental data suggest the following broad conclusions. The majority of subjects in both treatments voted for efficient minimum membership requirements. These votes led to the adoption of the efficient membership requirements in roughly three out of every four trials for both treatments. When efficiency required full participation (the s = 6 treatment), coalitions formed in 85 percent of all trials. The efficient coalition almost always formed (91.3 percent) when the efficient membership requirement was adopted. Overall, efficiency was very high in this treatment, about 87.4 percent as measured by the ratio of realized group earnings to maximum group earnings. Hence, group results in the s = 6 treatment closely matched our theoretical predictions that groups will use the membership requirement to form efficient 13 Subjects were not aware of their decision order when voting on the minimum membership requirement in the first stage. 11

12 coalitions. However, performance was significantly worse in the treatment for which a 3-player coalition was efficient (the s = 3 treatment). In this treatment coalitions formed in only 61 percent of all trials and the efficient coalition formed in only about half the trials. Consequently, average efficiency was significantly lower in these treatments (about 80 percent) than in the s = 6 treatments. Interestingly, the efficient coalition was blocked about a third of the time when the efficient membership requirement was adopted. This behavior is not consistent with a theory of coalition formation that includes only individuals with standard payoff-maximizing preferences. However, we will demonstrate that this behavior is consistent with a theory that allows for preferences over inequality. We begin our detailed analysis of the results by examining the data on voting for the membership requirement in the first stage of the experiments. Table 1 provides votes and referenda outcomes by membership requirement and treatment. The first row in each cell contains the number of votes and percentage of total votes (out of 720 for each treatment) for that minimum membership requirement. The second row in each cell contains the number of times and percentage of trails in the treatment (out of 120) that membership requirement was implemented. Under the s = 6 treatments, the 6-player membership requirement received 55.6 percent (400 of 720) of total votes, which is considerably more than the 19.3 percent received by the second most preferred option of a 5-player membership requirement. The remaining four options received even fewer votes. This voting behavior resulted in the selection of the efficient membership requirement in 76.7 percent (92 of 120) of referenda. [Table 1] The percentage of votes for efficient membership requirements is very similar across the two treatments. In the s = 3 treatment, the 3-player membership requirement received 56.8 percent of the votes. Membership requirements of size two received the second most with 21.2 percent of votes. Mirroring the results from the s = 6 treatment, voting led to the adoption of the efficient membership requirement in 76.7 percent (92 of 120) of referenda. Figure 1 illustrates the percentage of votes for efficient membership requirements over periods for both treatments. To summarize, the majority of subjects in both treatments voted for efficient membership requirements, and these were adopted in roughly three out of every four trials. 12

13 [Figure 1] Figure 1 suggests that the time series of the percentages of votes for the efficient coalition are very similar between the two treatments. We confirm this with results from a Probit model conditioning individual voting decisions on treatment, period fixed effects and subject-specific random effects. These results are reported in the first column of Table 2. Note that the treatment effect ( s = 3 ) is insignificant. In addition, the Probit model in the second column of Table 2 confirms that the likelihood of groups adopting the efficient membership requirement is statistically equivalent in the two treatments. [Table 2] Recall that our theoretical model yields the prediction that expected-payoff-maximizing players would vote for minimum membership requirements equal to efficient coalition sizes. Our experimental results from the voting stage are broadly consistent with this prediction in that the majority of subjects voted to adopt the efficient membership requirements. However, in contrast with our theoretical model we do observe significant, though minority, voting for smaller-thanefficient membership requirements. Our theoretical model is not helpful in explaining why 45 percent of votes were cast for inefficient agreement sizes. It is interesting to note that in each treatment the second most frequent vote was for one member less than the efficient agreement size. These votes are consistent with players attempting to increase their chances to free ride on profitable agreements. For example, a lone free rider on a coalition of five players in the full participation treatment would be the highest possible earner. Of course there are other possible explanations for this behavior. If players are not confident that other group members will join the agreement when it is rational to do so (if for example, they have a trembling hand when making their participation decision), then a lower participation threshold may appear less risky. 14 While the results from the voting stage are equivalent in the two treatments, the results from the coalition formation stage differ significantly. Table 3 contains results concerning coalition formation by minimum membership requirement and treatment. For each membership 14 We thank an anonymous referee for suggesting this possible explanation. See McGinty (2011) for an example of trembling hand equilibria in a coalition formation game. 13

14 requirement/treatment combination we provide the number of times a coalition formed under the membership requirement, this number as a percentage of total trials, and coalition formations as a percentage of times the membership requirement was adopted. The final column in Table 3 contains the number and percentage of trials a coalition of any size formed (i.e., all effective coalitions). [Table 3] Under the s = 6 treatment, coalitions of any size formed in 102 of 120 trials (85 percent). In 84 of 120 trials the efficient coalition formed (70 percent). Moreover, when players adopted the efficient membership requirement of six players, coalitions almost always formed (84 of 92, 91.3 percent). Thus, coalitions formed quite frequently in the s = 6 treatments and most coalitions were efficient. Other coalition sizes formed much less frequently. This suggests that the main reason why coalitions did not form in a subset of trials is because groups sometimes failed to implement the 6-player membership requirement. In both treatments, if a coalition failed to form then no player contributed to the public good and each earned 10 experimental dollars. In contrast, coalitions formed significantly less frequently under the s = 3 treatment. Overall, coalitions formed in 60.8 percent of trials in this treatment, which is significantly lower than the 85 percent coalition formation rate under the s = 6 treatment. This is confirmed by the results of the third model in Table 2, which is a Probit model of total coalition formation. Note that the dummy for the s = 3 treatment is negative and significant. Furthermore, the efficient coalition formed in 51.7 percent of trials (62 of 120), compared with 70 percent of trials in the s = 6 treatment. The most striking difference between the two treatments is the percentage of coalitions that formed conditional on the adoption of an efficient membership requirement. In both treatments, the referenda resulted in efficient membership requirements in 92 of 120 trials. With the s = 6 treatment, coalitions formed in 84 of those 92 trials (91.3 percent). However, under the s = 3 treatment, coalitions formed in 62 of those 92 trials (67.4 percent). The fourth Probit model in Table 2 confirms that the likelihood of a coalition forming when the efficient membership requirement was adopted is significantly lower in the s = 3 treatment. Let us explore this phenomenon more closely, since it implies that some individuals willfully blocked efficient coalitions in the sense that they were critical for the formation of the 14

15 coalition but refused to join so the coalition failed to form. The 3-player membership requirement was implemented in 92 out of 120 trials (76.7 percent from Table 1) under the s = 3 treatment. The efficient coalition failed to form in 30 of these trials. These blocks are inconsistent with a model that contains only individuals with standard expected-payoffmaximizing preferences. Such individuals would never block a profitable coalition, and efficient coalitions are always profitable. However, these blocks are consistent with the presence of subjects who are averse to disadvantageous inequality. When s = 3, the efficient outcome requires that the three non-members earn strictly higher payoffs than the three members. If players dislike payoff inequality, it is possible that coalitions that are profitable in terms of material payoffs are no longer profitable in terms of utility. In fact, minimum profitable coalition sizes for inequality-averse players will be weakly greater than those for players with standard preferences. Therefore, inequality-averse players may block efficient coalitions that are not individually profitable given their inequality preferences. That inequality averse individuals require higher minimum profitable coalition sizes is demonstrated theoretically in Kosfeld et al. (2009) for a game that is similar to ours. We demonstrate this result for our model in the appendix. We complete our data analysis with results on average public good provision and average efficiency in Table 4. Efficiency for each group in each period is calculated as the ratio of aggregate payoffs to maximum attainable payoffs. As expected, public good provision and efficiency were lower in the s = 3 treatment than in the s = 6 treatment. The significance of the difference in efficiency levels is confirmed in the linear regression results contained in the final column of Table 2. [Table 4] To judge the performance of the endogenous determination of minimum membership requirements, we can compare the efficiency level of our s = 6 treatment (87.4 percent) to recent experimental coalition formation studies that do not include this feature. The efficiency level in this treatment is quite high relative to these other studies. 15 For example, Kosfeld et al. 15 We cannot use the literature to judge the performance of our s = 3 treatment, because all other coalition formation experiments require the formation of the grand coalition for efficient provision of a public good. 15

16 (2009) conducted two coalition formation treatments which differed in the minimum number of members required for coalitions to be profitable (either 3 or 2 out of 4). As noted earlier, subjects in their experiments first decided whether to join a coalition, and then in a second stage the coalition members voted whether to contribute all of their endowment to the public good or not. Efficiency levels in their experiments were 51 percent and 70 percent for minimum profitable coalition sizes of 3 and 2, respectively. Among a number of treatments in McEvoy et al. (2011) were two coalition formation treatments that differed in terms of the individual costs of providing the good, producing different sizes of minimally profitable coalitions. These were then set as minimum membership requirements. One treatment required 3 of 10 subjects to join before a coalition formed while the other had a membership requirement of 6 of 10 subjects. The authors did not allow contributions from nonmembers and did not allow contributions if a coalition did not form; hence their efficiency measures are fairly conservative. Efficiency levels were 59.6 percent for the 3-player membership requirement and 56.2 percent for the 6-player membership requirement. Subjects performed much worse in the experiments of Dannenberg et al. (2010). They conducted three coalition formation treatments with 10-player groups. The authors report an efficiency level of 24 percent for one treatment in which coalition members contribution decisions were determined automatically by maximizing joint welfare. In another treatment coalition members only contributed half of what was required to maximize joint welfare and efficiency fell to 12 percent. The efficiency level was 29 percent in a third treatment in which coalition members endogenously determined the required minimum contribution. Although there are significant differences in the protocols between the experiments in Dannenberg et al. (2010) and our own (including group sizes), the comparison suggests that endogenous thresholds serve as effective coordination devices in coalition formation games. 5. Conclusion Many international environmental agreements include a minimum membership requirement for entry into force. Despite the wide-spread use of these requirements, little is known about their effectiveness. We have analyzed a coalition formation game that includes the endogenous determination of a minimum membership requirement and then tested the theoretical predictions of the game using a series of laboratory experiments. The main prediction of our theoretical 16

17 model is that agents will vote to adopt efficient coalition sizes as membership requirements and that these coalitions will form. Our experimental results are largely consistent with the theoretical predictions when efficiency requires the grand coalition to form. In this treatment, coalitions formed 85 percent of the time and over 90 percent of these were the efficient grand coalition. These results demonstrate the value of the endogenously determined membership requirements. In fact, the level of efficiency for this treatment is significantly higher than in other coalition formation experiments that do not include the endogenous determination of membership requirements. However, in our treatment for which the efficient coalition required only a subset of the group, coalitions formed only 60 percent of the time and efficient coalitions were deliberately blocked about a third of the time. If these blocks had not occurred, performance in this treatment would have matched the performance of the treatment that required the grand coalition to form for efficient provision of the public good. Although individuals with standard preferences would never block efficient coalitions from forming, these actions are consistent with inequality-averse individuals. Equity concerns may help explain the choice of membership requirements in many existing voluntary institutions; in particular, the fact that many international agreements require very high levels of participation (Barrett 2003). In light of our results it is possible that equity concerns can limit the formation of international agreements when membership requirements would allow free riders. One might expect that inefficiently high membership requirements would emerge to limit freeriding, although we do not observe this in our experiments. The role of equity preferences in the formation of voluntary agreements is not well understood, so further research in this area would be beneficial. Another caveat is that our analysis assumes homogeneity in the costs and benefits of providing a public good. Future research should relax this simplifying assumption and explore the role of endogenous minimum participation requirements among heterogeneous players. Our objective was to empirically test a feature of international governance endogenous minimum participation - that is included in almost all environmental treaties. Although our laboratory experiments necessarily abstract from the many intricacies involved with international management of shared resources, the results shed light on the effectiveness of the institution in a controlled environment. The take away message for stakeholders in international diplomacy is 17

18 that endogenous minimum participation requirements can be effective at fostering cooperation, but may be significantly less effective when targeted participation allows for free riding. References Barrett, Scott Self-enforcing International Environmental Agreements. Oxford Economic Papers 46(5): Barrett, Scott Environment and Statecraft: The Strategy of Environmental Treaty Making. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press. Barrett, Scott and Astrid Dannenberg Climate Negotiations under Scientific Uncertainty. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 109(43): Black, Jane, Maurice D. Levi and David de Meza Creating a Good Atmosphere: Minimum Participation for Tackling the Greenhouse Effect. Economica 60(239): Cadsby, Charles B., and Elizabeth Maynes Voluntary Provision of Threshold Public Goods with Continuous Contributions: Experimental Evidence. Journal of Public Economics, 71(1): Carraro, Carlo and Domenico Siniscalco The International Dimension of Environmental Policy. European Economic Review 36(2-3): Carraro, Carlo, Carmen Marchiori, and Sonia Oreffice Endogenous Minimum Participation in International Environmental Treaties. Environmental and Resource Economics, 42(3): Cason, Timothy N. and Charles R. Plott "EPA's New Emissions Trading Mechanism: A Laboratory Evaluation." Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 30 (2): Cooper, David J. and Carol K. Stockman Learning to Punish: Experimental Evidence from a Sequential Step-Level Public Goods Game. Experimental Economics 5(1): Dannenberg, Astrid, Andreas Lange and Bodo Sturm On the Formation of Coalitions to Provide Public Goods Experimental Evidence from the Lab. NBER Working Paper No Erev, Ido, and Amnon Rapoport Provision of Step-Level Public Goods: The Sequential Contribution Mechanism. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 34(3): Fehr, Ernst, and Klaus M. Schmidt A Theory of Fairness, Competition, and Cooperation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(3):

19 Fehr, Ernst, and Simon Gachter Cooperation and Punishment in Public Goods Experiments. American Economic Review, 90(4): Gurerk, Ozgur, Bernd Irlenbusch, and Bettina Rockenbach The Competitive Advantage of Sanctioning Institutions. Science, 312(5770): Harstad, Bard Flexible Integration? Mandatory and Minimum Participation Rules. The Scandinavian Journal of Economics 108(4): Kosfeld, Michael, Akira Okada, and Arno Riedl Institution Formation in Public Goods Games. American Economic Review, 99(4): Kroll, Stephan, Todd L. Cherry, and Jason F. Shogren Voting, Punishment, and Public Goods. Economic Inquiry, 45(3): Lange, Andreas and Carsten Vogt Cooperation in International Environmental Negotiations Due to a Preference for Equity. Journal of Public Economics 87(9-10): McEvoy, David Not It: Opting Out of Voluntary Coalitions that Provide a Public Good. Public Choice 142(1): McEvoy, David, James Murphy, John Spraggon, and John Stranlund The Problem of Maintaining Compliance with Stable Coalitions: Experimental Evidence. Oxford Economic Papers 63(3), McGinty, Matthew A Risk-Dominant Allocation: Maximizing Coalition Stability. Journal of Public Economic Theory 13(2): Myerson, Roger B. and Robert J. Weber A Theory of Voting Equilibria. American Political Science Review 87(1): Osborne, Martin. and Al Slivinski A Model of Political Competition with Citizen- Candidates. Quarterly Journal of Economics 111(1): Palfrey, Thomas Spatial Equilibrium with Entry. Review of Economic Studies 51(1): Plott, Charles Dimensions of Parallelism: Some Policy Applications of Experimental Methods. Laboratory Experimentation in Economics: Six Points of View Alvin Roth (Ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge U.K. Rapoport, Amnon Provision of Public Goods and the MCS Experimental Paradigm. American Political Science Review 79(1):

20 Ringius, Lasse, Asbjorn Torvanger and Arild Underdal Burden Sharing and Fairness Principles in International Climate Policy. International Environmental Agreements: Politics, Law and Economics 2(1): Shogren, Jason F. and Terrance M. Hurley "Experiments in Environmental Economics." Handbook of Environmental and Resource Economics. Jeroen C.J.M. van den Bergh (eds.). Cheltenham, U.K. and Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar Stranlund, John K., James J. Murphy and John M. Spraggon An Experimental Analysis of Compliance in Dynamic Emissions Markets. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 62(3), Sutter, Matthias, Stefan Haigner and Martin G. Kocher Choosing the Carrot or the Stick? Endogenous Institutional Choice in Social Dilemma Situations. Review of Economic Studies, 77(4): Tyran, Jean-Robert, and Lars P. Feld Achieving Compliance when Legal Sanctions are Non-deterrent. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 108(1): Walker, J.M., Roy Gardner, Andrew Herr and Elinor Ostrom Collective Choice in the Commons: Experimental Results on Proposed Allocation Rules and Votes. The Economic Journal, 110(460): Weikard, Hans-Peter, Leo Wangler and Andreas Freytag Minimum Participation Rules with Heterogeneous Countries. Jena Economic Research Papers , ISSN

21 Appendix Here we incorporate inequality aversion into our model to demonstrate that minimum profitable coalitions are weakly larger for inequality averse individuals than for individuals with standard preferences. We follow Fehr and Schmidt (1999) in modeling preferences over inequality. Suppose at first that s = n and s = 0. Given the financial payoffs [2] and [3] with these p restrictions, define the utility of a member of an effective coalition with s members as: βi ( ) ( ), [7] m m αi m m ui () s = πi () s max π j πi (),0 s max πi () s π j,0 n 1 n 1 j i where α i > 0 captures the player s loss from disadvantageous inequality and β i > 0 captures her nm j loss from advantageous inequality. Since π () s π () s = c and π () s π () s = 0from [2] and [3], [7] can be written as: m αicn ( s) ui () s = A + bs c. [8] n 1 Similarly, the utility of a nonmember of an effective coalition with s members is: m i j i βi ( ) ( ), [9] nm nm αi nm nm ui () s = πi () s max π j πi (),0 s max πi () s π j,0 n 1 n 1 which can be written as j i nm βisc ui () s = A + bs. [10] n 1 It is straightforward to show that the free-riding incentive is preserved in this model if ( n 1)( β 1) < α ; that is, as long as the aversion to advantageous inequality is not too strong i i relative to the aversion to disadvantageous inequality. Incorporating the efficient coalition size s n to determine individual payoffs yields: u m i αi ( n sc ) A + bs c for s s; n 1 () s = αi ( n sc ) A + bs c for s > s; n 1 j i m j m i [11] 21

22 u nm i βisc A + bs for s s; n 1 () s = βisc A + bs for s > s. n 1 Using [11], an individual s minimum profitable coalition size can be characterized as: [12] where c( n 1) + αicn sˆ i =. bn ( 1) + α c i [13] To demonstrate, we first derive s ˆi as the solution to: αi( n sc ) A + bs c = A. [14] n 1 m Since u () s in [11] is increasing in s, if sˆi However, if sˆi i > s, then must be the solution to s then s ˆi is i s minimum profitable coalition size. αi( n sc ) A + bs c = A. [15] n 1 Plug s ˆi into [14] and into [15], set the resulting equations equal to each other and collect terms to obtain, which implies that if sˆi > s. Recall from [4] that the minimum profitable coalition size for an individual with standard preferences is smin = min{ s s c/ b}. From [13],, sˆi is increasing in α, and sˆ = c/ b for α = 0. Together, these imply for an individual with disadvantageous inequality aversion i (i.e., α i > 0). Therefore, such an individual has a weakly higher minimum profitable coalition size than an individual with standard preferences. By substituting in our experimental parameters into equation [13] we can demonstrate how large must be to increase the minimum profitable coalition size beyond the efficient size. i i In the treatment with an efficient coalition of three members, if exceeds 0.584, then the minimum profitable coalition for an individual will exceed three members. As a frame of reference, at least 40 percent of players in Fehr and Schmidt s analysis were estimated to have α >

23 Figure 1: Percentage of votes for efficient coalitions by treatment Table 1: Individual votes and referenda outcomes by minimum membership requirement and treatment Minimum membership requirement Totals s = 6 35 (4.9%) 27 (3.8%) 53 (7.4%) 66 (9.2%) 139(19.3) 400 (55.6%) (1.7%) 3 (2.5%) 6 (5.0%) 7 (5.8%) 10 (8.3%) 92 (76.7%) 120 s = 3 91 (12.6%) 153 (21.2%) 409 (56.8%) 32 (4.4%) 9 (1.3%) 26 (3.6%) (5.8%) 19 (15.8%) 92 (76.7%) 1 (0.8%) 0 (0.0%) 1 (0.8%) 120 Top of each cell: Number of votes for each minimum membership requirement (percent of total votes by treatment). Note there are 720 individual votes per treatment. Bottom of each cell: Number of times each minimum membership requirement was implemented (percent of total trials by treatment). Note there are 120 group-level observations per treatment. 23

24 Vote on efficient MMR s = p = Model p = period effects (chi-square) p = subject effects (chi-square) p = Table 2: Regression results comparing the two treatments Efficient referenda outcomes p = Total coalition formation p = Efficient coalition formation p = Efficiency p = p = p = p = p = p = p = p = p = n Notes: The first four columns report average marginal effects (and p-values) for the s = 3 treatment (relative to the s = 6 treatment) from Probit regressions. The first model controls for period fixed effects and subject random effects. The other three Probit regressions are at the group-level and control for period fixed effects. The last model is a linear regression with a dependent variable defined as total group earnings/max group earnings and controls for period fixed effects. Table 3: Coalition formation by minimum membership requirement and treatment Minimum membership requirement Total s = % 0.8% 4.2% 3.3% 5.8% 70.0% 85.0% 50.0% 33.3% 83.3% 57.1% 70.0% 91.3% s = % 7.5% 51.7% 0.0% 0.0% 0.8% 60.8% % 67.4% 0.0% 0.0% 100.0% Top of each cell: Number of times coalitions formed. Middle of each cell: Percentage coalition formation by number of trials per treatment. Bottom of each cell: Percentage coalition formation by adopted membership requirement. 24

25 Table 4. Public good provision and efficiency Average Public Treatment Good Provision s = (0.26) s = (0.31) Efficiency 87.4% (2.21) 79.6% (2.07) Standard errors are in parentheses. Each treatment consists of 120 group-level observations. 25

26 Experiment Instructions (Treatment s = 6 ) Thank you for agreeing to participate in this experiment. Please follow along carefully while I read these instructions. Your earnings will be paid to you in cash at the end of the experiment. The exact amount of money you will earn will depend on your decisions, and the decisions made by the other participants, during this experiment. GENERAL DETAILS Throughout this session, your earnings will be reported in Experimental Dollars. 20 Experimental Dollars equals 1 US dollar. GROUPS During each period of this experiment you will be in a group with 5 OTHER subjects (groups of size 6). Each period of the experiment the groups will be reshuffled so you will not be with the same 5 people. ENDOWMENTS Every period you will be given an initial endowment of 10 Experimental Dollars (called, your endowment). Everyone in your group gets the same endowment. THE AGREEMENT In each period you will have the opportunity to form an agreement with the other 5 members of your group. The agreement has two stages. 1. In the first stage you get to vote on the minimum number of members required for the agreement to form. Your vote will be from 1 to 6. The number that receives the most votes wins. If there are ties, the winning number is selected at random among the tied numbers. 2. In the second stage you get to decide whether or not to join the agreement. If enough members join agreement in this stage to satisfy the required minimum number of members decided from the first stage, the agreement forms. 26

27 YOUR EARNINGS If an agreement forms, those that joined the agreement automatically contribute their endowment to a public account and those that did not join keep their endowment. Contributions made to the public account benefit everybody in the group. Specifically, everyone will earn $0.45 * the total contributions to the public account. If you keep your endowment, you will earn $1 * 10 plus the earnings from the public account. If an agreement does not form, everyone keeps their endowment, no contributions to the public account are made and everyone earns $10. To summarize, depending on your decisions and the decisions made by the other group members your earnings each period will be one of the following: A. If an agreement DOES NOT form, then you will earn: $1 * your endowment of 10 = $10 B. If an agreement DOES form and you DID NOT JOIN the agreement, then you will earn: $1 * your endowment of 10 + $0.45 * the total amount of contributions in the public account C. If an agreement DOES form and you DID JOIN the agreement, then you will earn: $0.45 * the total amount of contributions in the public account During this experiment these calculations will be made for you and displayed in a table. We will now go over the two stages of the game in detail and provide examples. [go to next page] 27

28 STAGE 1 Below is an example of what you will see on your computer screen during Stage 1. The box highlighted in yellow is the active box on the screen. Within the yellow box you will vote on the minimum number of members required for an agreement to form. You will make your decision by clicking on a number in the list box. Once you click on a number in the listbox, then you must click the green button to submit your vote. The number that receives the most votes wins. In the event of a tie, the winning vote will be randomly chosen from the set of tied numbers. The greenish-blue box at the bottom of the screen shot above (and reproduced below) can be used to see how your earnings possibilities in Stage 2 change with the minimum number of members required for an agreement to form. You can select a minimum number of members from the list within the blue box at any time and see how your earnings possibilities change in the Example earnings table to the right. Your choices made in this box are not recorded and are just used to make informed decisions. You must cast your vote in the highlighted yellow box above. 28

29 For example, if the result of the vote in Stage 1 is 2 as is the case in the example image below, the payoff possibilities are captured in the table to the right. In this situation, if fewer than 2 members join the agreement in Stage 2 then the agreement does not form and every player earns $10 regardless of their decision. However, if 2 or more players join the agreement in Stage 2 then the agreement forms and those that join contribute their endowments of 10. For example, if 4 players join then those four players will earn $0.45 * 40=$18 and the 2 players that do not join will earn $1 * 10 + $0.45 * 40 = $28. These earnings, rounded to the nearest integer, are displayed in the Example earnings table. Once everyone has submitted their vote the stage ends, a box highlighted in yellow will appear displaying the result from the vote. Once you have had a chance to look over the outcome of the vote, you may click the green Proceed button in the upper left area of the screen. Once everyone has clicked Proceed, Stage 2 will begin. [go to next page] 29

30 STAGE 2 The screen shot below is an example of what you will see during Stage 2. The box highlighted in light yellow in the upper-left portion of the screen is where you will make your decision. This box also contains all of the information regarding the choices of the other 5 group members. In this stage you can either join the agreement (click Join Agreement ) or not join the agreement (click Do Not Join Agreement ). In this stage, the six members of your group will be assigned, randomly, an order number in which to make decisions. If you are assigned 1, then you will be the first to make a decision. If you are assigned 2, you will be the second to make a decision. And so on. All decisions that are made will be instantly visible to the other group members. Note also in the box in the upper-left portion of the screen you can find the running total of the number of players that decided to join the agreement and the number of players that decided to not join the agreement. In the example below, two other group members have already decided, one chose to join the agreement and one chose to not join the agreement. Note the bright yellow box reminding you it is now your turn to make a decision. 30

31 Also you will be provided with updates regarding the requirements for the agreement to form. Recall from Stage 1, the group voted that at least 3 people must join the agreement. In the screen shot, since only one person has joined thus far, 2 more people need to join for the agreement to form. Finally, the box below the yellow box labeled Earnings Table lists all of your earnings possibilities for the period. Note that the Earnings Table is the same as the Example earnings table from Stage 1. When its not your turn to make a decision, your screen will look like this. Note the dark orange box reminding you that it is not yet your decision. 31

32 END OF PERIOD After all groups have finished making their decisions in Stage 2, the period will be over. At that point a Period Results box will appear at the bottom of your monitor displaying the outcomes and your earnings (in experimental dollars) for the period and information regarding the decisions made by you and all the members in your group. Once you have had a chance to look at the Period Results you can click the green Ready to Start button at the top-right of the screen to begin the next period. Once all groups are ready, the next period will begin immediately. END OF EXPERIMENT You will be notified on your computer monitor once the experiment has ended and a summary screen with your total earnings will be displayed. At that point please stay seated and quiet and wait for your earnings to be paid to you. SUMMARY Each period you will be in a group with 5 other people. The members of your group will change every period. In Stage 1 during each period of play you get to vote on the minimum number of members required for the agreement to form. In Stage 2 during each period of play you get to decide whether or not to join the agreement. If enough group members join the agreement to satisfy the number voted on in Stage 1 an agreement forms. Otherwise, an agreement does not form. Your earnings will be determined by one of the following formulas and clearly displayed in the Earnings Table: A. If an agreement DOES NOT form, then you will earn: 1 * your endowment of $10 = $10 B. If an agreement DOES form and you DID NOT JOIN the agreement, then you will earn: $1 * your endowment of 10 + $0.45 * the total amount of contributions in the public account C. If an agreement DOES form and you DID JOIN the agreement, then you will earn: $0.45 * the total amount of contributions in the public account 20 Experimental Dollars = 1 U.S. Dollar. Fractions of a dollar will be rounded up to the nearest quarter. 32

33 Experiment Instructions (Treatment s = 3 ) Thank you for agreeing to participate in this experiment. Please follow along carefully while I read these instructions. Your earnings will be paid to you in cash at the end of the experiment. The exact amount of money you will earn will depend on your decisions, and the decisions made by the other participants, during this experiment. GENERAL DETAILS Throughout this session, your earnings will be reported in Experimental Dollars. 20 Experimental Dollars equals 1 US dollar. GROUPS During each period of this experiment you will be in a group with 5 OTHER subjects (groups of size 6). Each period of the experiment the groups will be reshuffled so you will not be with the same 5 people. ENDOWMENTS Every period you will be given an initial endowment of 10 Experimental Dollars (called, your endowment). Everyone in your group gets the same endowment. THE AGREEMENT In each period you will have the opportunity to form an agreement with the other 5 members of your group. The agreement has two stages. 1. In the first stage you get to vote on the minimum number of members required for the agreement to form. Your vote will be from 1 to 6. The number that receives the most votes wins. If there are ties, the winning number is selected at random among the tied numbers. 2. In the second stage you get to decide whether or not to join the agreement. If enough members join agreement in this stage to satisfy the required minimum number of members decided from the first stage, the agreement forms. 33

34 YOUR EARNINGS If an agreement forms, those that joined the agreement automatically contribute their endowment to a public account and those that did not join keep their endowment. Contributions made to the public account up to a total of 30 benefit everybody in the group. Specifically, everyone will earn $0.45 * the total contributions to the public account (up to 30). Contributions to the public account in excess of 30 do not benefit group members. If you keep your endowment, you will earn $1 * 10 plus your earnings from the public account. If an agreement does not form, everyone keeps their endowment, no contributions to the public account are made and everyone earns $10. To summarize, depending on your decisions and the decisions made by the other group members your earnings will be one of the following: A. If an agreement DOES NOT form, then you will earn: $1 * your endowment of 10 = $10 B. If an agreement DOES form and you DID NOT JOIN the agreement, then you will earn: For total contributions of 30 or less: $1 * your endowment of 10 + $0.45 * the total amount of contributions in the public account For total contributions of over 30: $1 * your endowment of 10 + $0.45 * 30 C. If an agreement DOES form and you DID JOIN the agreement, then you will earn: For contributions 30 or less: $0.45 * the total amount of contributions in the public account For contributions over 30: $0.45 * 30 During this experiment these calculations will be made for you and displayed in a table. We will now go over the two stages of the game in detail and provide examples. 34

35 STAGE 1 Below is an example of what you will see on your computer screen during Stage 1. The box highlighted in yellow is the active box on the screen. Within the yellow box you will vote on the minimum number of members required for an agreement to form. You will make your decision by clicking on a number in the list box. Once you click on a number in the listbox, then you must click the green button to submit your vote. The number that receives the most votes wins. In the event of a tie, the winning vote will be randomly chosen from the set of tied numbers. The greenish-blue box at the bottom of the screen shot above (and reproduced below) can be used to see how your earnings possibilities in Stage 2 change with the minimum number of members required for an agreement to form. You can select a minimum number of members from the list within the blue box at any time and see how your earnings possibilities change in the Example earnings table to the right. Your choices made in this box are not recorded and are just used to make informed decisions. You must cast your vote in the highlighted yellow box above. 35

36 For example, if the result of the vote in Stage 1 is 2 as is the case in the example image below, the payoff possibilities are captured in the table to the right. In this situation, if fewer than 2 members join the agreement then the agreement does not form and every player earns $10 regardless of their decision. However, if 2 or more players join the agreement then the agreement forms and those that join contribute their endowments of 10. For example, if 4 players join then those four players will earn ($0.45 * 30) = $14 and the 2 players that do not join will earn ($1 * 10 + $0.45 * 30) = $24. These earnings, rounded to the nearest integer, are displayed in the Example earnings table. Once everyone has submitted their vote the stage ends, a box highlighted in yellow will appear displaying the result from the vote. Once you have had a chance to look over the outcome of the vote, you may click the green Proceed button in the upper left area of the screen. Once everyone has clicked Proceed, Stage 2 will begin. [go to next page] 36

37 STAGE 2 The screen shot below is an example of what you will see during Stage 2. The box highlighted in light yellow in the upper-left portion of the screen is where you will make your decision. This box also contains all of the information regarding the choices of the other 5 group members. In this stage you can either join the agreement (click Join Agreement ) or not join the agreement (click Do Not Join Agreement ). In this stage, the six members of your group will be assigned, randomly, an order number in which to make decisions. If you are assigned 1, then you will be the first to make a decision. If you are assigned 2, you will be the second to make a decision. And so on. All decisions that are made will be instantly visible to the other group members. Note also in the box in the upper-left portion of the screen you can find the running total of the number of players that decided to join the agreement and the number of players that decided to not join the agreement. In the example below, two other group members have already decided, one chose to join the agreement and one chose to not join the agreement. Note the bright yellow box reminding you it is now your turn to make a decision. Also you will be provided with updates regarding the requirements for the agreement to form. Recall from Stage 1, the group voted that at least 3 people must join the agreement. In the screen shot, since only one person has joined thus far, 2 more people need to join for the agreement to form. 37

38 Finally, the box below the yellow box labeled Earnings Table lists all of your earnings possibilities for the period. Note that the Earnings Table is the same as the Example earnings table from Stage 1. When its not your turn to make a decision, your screen will look like this. Note the dark orange box reminding you that it is not yet your decision. END OF PERIOD After all groups have finished making their decisions in Stage 2, the period will be over. At that point a Period Results box will appear at the bottom of your monitor displaying the outcomes and your earnings (in experimental dollars) for the period and information regarding the decisions made by you and all the members in your group. Once you have had a chance to look at the Period Results you can click the green Ready to Start button at the top-right of the screen to begin the next period. Once all groups are ready, the next period will begin immediately. 38

Enforcing Self-Enforcing International Environmental Agreements

Enforcing Self-Enforcing International Environmental Agreements Enforcing Self-Enforcing International Environmental Agreements DAVID M. McEVOY Department of Resource Economics University of Massachusetts-Amherst JOHN K. STRANLUND Department of Resource Economics University

More information

Enforcing Self-Enforcing International Environmental Agreements

Enforcing Self-Enforcing International Environmental Agreements University of Massachusetts Amherst Department of Resource Economics Working Paper No. 2006-6 http://www.umass.edu/resec/workingpapers Enforcing Self-Enforcing International Environmental Agreements David

More information

Common Pool Resource Management and the Effect of Heterogeneous Users: an Experimental Investigation

Common Pool Resource Management and the Effect of Heterogeneous Users: an Experimental Investigation Common Pool Resource Management and the Effect of Heterogeneous Users: an Experimental Investigation Lance Howe University of Alaska, Anchorage Jim Murphy (future iterations) Introduction This experiment

More information

Risk Aversion and Compliance in Markets for Pollution Control

Risk Aversion and Compliance in Markets for Pollution Control University of Massachusetts Amherst Department of Resource Economics Working Paper No. 26-2 http://www.umass.edu/resec/workingpapers Risk Aversion and Compliance in Markets for Pollution Control John K.

More information

Effective Climate Agreements under Uncertainty

Effective Climate Agreements under Uncertainty Effective Climate Agreements under Uncertainty TODD L. CHERRY Center for International Climate and Environmental Research Oslo (CICERO) P.O.Box 1129, Blindern, 0318 Oslo, Norway Department of Economics

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

Cooperation and Rent Extraction in Repeated Interaction

Cooperation and Rent Extraction in Repeated Interaction Supplementary Online Appendix to Cooperation and Rent Extraction in Repeated Interaction Tobias Cagala, Ulrich Glogowsky, Veronika Grimm, Johannes Rincke July 29, 2016 Cagala: University of Erlangen-Nuremberg

More information

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours YORK UNIVERSITY Faculty of Graduate Studies Final Examination December 14, 2010 Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics S. Bucovetsky time=2.5 hours Do any 6 of the following 10 questions. All count

More information

Ostracism and the Provision of a Public Good Experimental Evidence

Ostracism and the Provision of a Public Good Experimental Evidence Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods Bonn 2005/24 Ostracism and the Provision of a Public Good Experimental Evidence Frank P. Maier-Rigaud Peter Martinsson Gianandrea

More information

On Delays in Project Completion With Cost Reduction: An Experiment

On Delays in Project Completion With Cost Reduction: An Experiment On Delays in Project Completion With Cost Reduction: An Experiment June 25th, 2009 Abstract We examine the voluntary provision of a public project via binary contributions when contributions may be made

More information

Econ 2230: Public Economics. Lecture 18: Announcement: changing the set of equilibria

Econ 2230: Public Economics. Lecture 18: Announcement: changing the set of equilibria Econ 2230: Public Economics Lecture 18: Announcement: changing the set of equilibria Review Romano and Yildirim When public good aspect dominates sequential giving decreases giving y j du i / dy j > 0

More information

Public Goods Provision with Rent-Extracting Administrators

Public Goods Provision with Rent-Extracting Administrators Supplementary Online Appendix to Public Goods Provision with Rent-Extracting Administrators Tobias Cagala, Ulrich Glogowsky, Veronika Grimm, Johannes Rincke November 27, 2017 Cagala: Deutsche Bundesbank

More information

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Chapter 5 Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Until now we implicitly adopted a view that a Nash equilibrium is a desirable outcome of a strategic game. In this chapter we consider two alternative

More information

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015. FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.) Hints for Problem Set 2 1. Consider a zero-sum game, where

More information

Bankruptcy risk and the performance of tradable permit markets. Abstract

Bankruptcy risk and the performance of tradable permit markets. Abstract Bankruptcy risk and the performance of tradable permit markets John Stranlund University of Massachusetts-Amherst Wei Zhang University of Massachusetts-Amherst Abstract We study the impacts of bankruptcy

More information

Self-Government and Public Goods: An Experiment

Self-Government and Public Goods: An Experiment Self-Government and Public Goods: An Experiment Kenju Kamei and Louis Putterman Brown University Jean-Robert Tyran* University of Copenhagen * No blame for this draft. Centralized vs. Decentralized Sanctions

More information

Contracts, Reference Points, and Competition

Contracts, Reference Points, and Competition Contracts, Reference Points, and Competition Behavioral Effects of the Fundamental Transformation 1 Ernst Fehr University of Zurich Oliver Hart Harvard University Christian Zehnder University of Lausanne

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO May 22, 2015 Announcements HW #3 is due next week. Ch. 6.1: Ultimatum Game This is a simple game that can model a very simplified

More information

Social preferences I and II

Social preferences I and II Social preferences I and II Martin Kocher University of Munich Course in Behavioral and Experimental Economics Motivation - De gustibus non est disputandum. (Stigler and Becker, 1977) - De gustibus non

More information

Using Trade Policy to Influence Firm Location. This Version: 9 May 2006 PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE DO NOT CITE

Using Trade Policy to Influence Firm Location. This Version: 9 May 2006 PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE DO NOT CITE Using Trade Policy to Influence Firm Location This Version: 9 May 006 PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE DO NOT CITE Using Trade Policy to Influence Firm Location Nathaniel P.S. Cook Abstract This paper examines

More information

Deterring Poaching of a Common Pool Resource

Deterring Poaching of a Common Pool Resource Deterring Poaching of a Common Pool Resource Lawrence R. De Geest, John K. Stranlund, John M. Spraggon Department of Resource Economics, University of Massachusetts-Amherst, 80 Campus Center Way, Amherst

More information

Relative Performance and Stability of Collusive Behavior

Relative Performance and Stability of Collusive Behavior Relative Performance and Stability of Collusive Behavior Toshihiro Matsumura Institute of Social Science, the University of Tokyo and Noriaki Matsushima Graduate School of Business Administration, Kobe

More information

Reciprocity in Teams

Reciprocity in Teams Reciprocity in Teams Richard Fairchild School of Management, University of Bath Hanke Wickhorst Münster School of Business and Economics This Version: February 3, 011 Abstract. In this paper, we show that

More information

PUBLIC GOODS AND THE LAW OF 1/n

PUBLIC GOODS AND THE LAW OF 1/n PUBLIC GOODS AND THE LAW OF 1/n David M. Primo Department of Political Science University of Rochester James M. Snyder, Jr. Department of Political Science and Department of Economics Massachusetts Institute

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 9, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria

More information

Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions

Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions Susan K. Laury and Charles A. Holt Prepared for the Handbook of Experimental Economics Results February 2002 I. Introduction

More information

Attracting Intra-marginal Traders across Multiple Markets

Attracting Intra-marginal Traders across Multiple Markets Attracting Intra-marginal Traders across Multiple Markets Jung-woo Sohn, Sooyeon Lee, and Tracy Mullen College of Information Sciences and Technology, The Pennsylvania State University, University Park,

More information

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercise. (U, R).. (U, L) and (D, R). 3. (D, R). 4. (U, L) and (D, R). 5. First, eliminate R as it is strictly dominated by M for player. Second, eliminate M as it is strictly

More information

Thursday, March 3

Thursday, March 3 5.53 Thursday, March 3 -person -sum (or constant sum) game theory -dimensional multi-dimensional Comments on first midterm: practice test will be on line coverage: every lecture prior to game theory quiz

More information

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2013 *********************************************** COVER SHEET ***********************************************

More information

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson all 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) 1. Critique of subgame perfection. 1 Consider the following three-player sequential game. In the first

More information

Topic 3 Social preferences

Topic 3 Social preferences Topic 3 Social preferences Martin Kocher University of Munich Experimentelle Wirtschaftsforschung Motivation - De gustibus non est disputandum. (Stigler and Becker, 1977) - De gustibus non est disputandum,

More information

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1 . Economic Applications of Game Theory Fall 00 TA: Youngjin Hwang Problem 3 Solutions. (a) There are three subgames: [A] the subgame starting from Player s decision node after Player s choice of P; [B]

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO May 24, 2016 Announcements Homework #4 is due next week. Review of Last Lecture In extensive games with imperfect information,

More information

Risk Aversion and Tacit Collusion in a Bertrand Duopoly Experiment

Risk Aversion and Tacit Collusion in a Bertrand Duopoly Experiment Risk Aversion and Tacit Collusion in a Bertrand Duopoly Experiment Lisa R. Anderson College of William and Mary Department of Economics Williamsburg, VA 23187 lisa.anderson@wm.edu Beth A. Freeborn College

More information

Volume 29, Issue 1. Second-mover advantage under strategic subsidy policy in a third market model

Volume 29, Issue 1. Second-mover advantage under strategic subsidy policy in a third market model Volume 29 Issue 1 Second-mover advantage under strategic subsidy policy in a third market model Kojun Hamada Faculty of Economics Niigata University Abstract This paper examines which of the Stackelberg

More information

Endogenous Cartel Formation with Differentiated Products and Price Competition

Endogenous Cartel Formation with Differentiated Products and Price Competition Endogenous Cartel Formation with Differentiated Products and Price Competition Tyra Merker * February 2018 Abstract Cartels may cause great harm to consumers and economic efficiency. However, literature

More information

Title: The Relative-Profit-Maximization Objective of Private Firms and Endogenous Timing in a Mixed Oligopoly

Title: The Relative-Profit-Maximization Objective of Private Firms and Endogenous Timing in a Mixed Oligopoly Working Paper Series No. 09007(Econ) China Economics and Management Academy China Institute for Advanced Study Central University of Finance and Economics Title: The Relative-Profit-Maximization Objective

More information

Limitations of Dominance and Forward Induction: Experimental Evidence *

Limitations of Dominance and Forward Induction: Experimental Evidence * Limitations of Dominance and Forward Induction: Experimental Evidence * Jordi Brandts Instituto de Análisis Económico (CSIC), Barcelona, Spain Charles A. Holt University of Virginia, Charlottesville VA,

More information

International environmental agreements with asymmetric countries: climate clubs vs. global cooperation

International environmental agreements with asymmetric countries: climate clubs vs. global cooperation International environmental agreements with asymmetric countries: climate clubs vs. global cooperation Achim Hagen, Klaus Eisenack Abstract We investigate whether global cooperation for emission abatement

More information

Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260

Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260 1 Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260 Problem 1 a) What is a public good game? See, for example, Camerer (2003), Fehr and Schmidt (1999) p.836, and/or lecture notes, lecture 1 of Topic 3.

More information

Early PD experiments

Early PD experiments REPEATED GAMES 1 Early PD experiments In 1950, Merrill Flood and Melvin Dresher (at RAND) devised an experiment to test Nash s theory about defection in a two-person prisoners dilemma. Experimental Design

More information

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let April 29, 2015 "A Characterization of Efficient, Bayesian Incentive Compatible Mechanisms," by S. R. Williams. Economic Theory 14, 155-180 (1999). AcommonresultinBayesianmechanismdesignshowsthatexpostefficiency

More information

Mixed Motives of Simultaneous-move Games in a Mixed Duopoly. Abstract

Mixed Motives of Simultaneous-move Games in a Mixed Duopoly. Abstract Mixed Motives of Simultaneous-move Games in a Mixed Duopoly Kangsik Choi Graduate School of International Studies. Pusan National University Abstract This paper investigates the simultaneous-move games

More information

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Reputations arise in situations where there is an element of repetition, and also where coordination between players is possible. One definition of leadership is that

More information

Analysis of a highly migratory fish stocks fishery: a game theoretic approach

Analysis of a highly migratory fish stocks fishery: a game theoretic approach Analysis of a highly migratory fish stocks fishery: a game theoretic approach Toyokazu Naito and Stephen Polasky* Oregon State University Address: Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics Oregon

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 More on strategic games and extensive games with perfect information Block 2 Jun 11, 2017 Auctions results Histogram of

More information

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games Tim Roughgarden November 6, 013 1 Canonical POA Proofs In Lecture 1 we proved that the price of anarchy (POA)

More information

Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Financial Fragility and Coordination Failures What makes financial systems fragile? What causes crises

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Part 2. Dynamic games of complete information Chapter 1. Dynamic games of complete and perfect information Ciclo Profissional 2 o Semestre / 2011 Graduação em Ciências Econômicas

More information

Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining

Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining Model September 30, 2010 1 Overview In these supplementary

More information

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Corporate Control Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Managerial Discipline and Takeovers Managers often don t maximize the value of the firm; either because they are not capable

More information

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4) Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4) Outline: Modeling by means of games Normal form games Dominant strategies; dominated strategies,

More information

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1 REPEATED GAMES Overview Context: players (e.g., firms) interact with each other on an ongoing basis Concepts: repeated games, grim strategies Economic principle: repetition helps enforcing otherwise unenforceable

More information

Comparative Study between Linear and Graphical Methods in Solving Optimization Problems

Comparative Study between Linear and Graphical Methods in Solving Optimization Problems Comparative Study between Linear and Graphical Methods in Solving Optimization Problems Mona M Abd El-Kareem Abstract The main target of this paper is to establish a comparative study between the performance

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 07. (40 points) Consider a Cournot duopoly. The market price is given by q q, where q and q are the quantities of output produced

More information

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1 A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model of Inequity Aversion 1 Kirsten I.M. Rohde 2 January 12, 2009 1 The author would like to thank Itzhak Gilboa, Ingrid M.T. Rohde, Klaus M. Schmidt, and

More information

Equity constraints and efficiency in the tradeable permit market.

Equity constraints and efficiency in the tradeable permit market. Equity constraints and efficiency in the tradeable permit market. By Cathrine Hagem Department of Economics, University of Oslo and CICERO, Center for International Climate and Environmental Research.

More information

Factors that Affect Fiscal Externalities in an Economic Union

Factors that Affect Fiscal Externalities in an Economic Union Factors that Affect Fiscal Externalities in an Economic Union Timothy J. Goodspeed Hunter College - CUNY Department of Economics 695 Park Avenue New York, NY 10021 USA Telephone: 212-772-5434 Telefax:

More information

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015. FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.) Hints for Problem Set 3 1. Consider the following strategic

More information

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Problem Set 1 These questions will go over basic game-theoretic concepts and some applications. homework is due during class on week 4. This [1] In this problem (see Fudenberg-Tirole

More information

Voluntary Public Goods Provision, Coalition Formation, and Uncertainty 1. Nicholas E. Burger Charles D. Kolstad

Voluntary Public Goods Provision, Coalition Formation, and Uncertainty 1. Nicholas E. Burger Charles D. Kolstad Voluntary Public Goods Provision, Coalition Formation, and Uncertainty 1 Nicholas E. Burger Charles D. Kolstad University of California, Santa Barbara March, 2008 Abstract There is extensive empirical

More information

Monopoly Power with a Short Selling Constraint

Monopoly Power with a Short Selling Constraint Monopoly Power with a Short Selling Constraint Robert Baumann College of the Holy Cross Bryan Engelhardt College of the Holy Cross September 24, 2012 David L. Fuller Concordia University Abstract We show

More information

Liquidity saving mechanisms

Liquidity saving mechanisms Liquidity saving mechanisms Antoine Martin and James McAndrews Federal Reserve Bank of New York September 2006 Abstract We study the incentives of participants in a real-time gross settlement with and

More information

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Juyan Zhang and Yi Zhang February 20, 2011 Abstract We investigate hold-up in the case of both simultaneous and sequential investment. We show that if

More information

Does Encourage Inward FDI Always Be a Dominant Strategy for Domestic Government? A Theoretical Analysis of Vertically Differentiated Industry

Does Encourage Inward FDI Always Be a Dominant Strategy for Domestic Government? A Theoretical Analysis of Vertically Differentiated Industry Lin, Journal of International and Global Economic Studies, 7(2), December 2014, 17-31 17 Does Encourage Inward FDI Always Be a Dominant Strategy for Domestic Government? A Theoretical Analysis of Vertically

More information

Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy!

Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy! Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy! Jessica Abramson, Natalie Collina, and William Gasarch August 2017 1 Introduction Consider a final round of Jeopardy! with players Alice and Betty 1. We assume that

More information

Follow the Leader I has three pure strategy Nash equilibria of which only one is reasonable.

Follow the Leader I has three pure strategy Nash equilibria of which only one is reasonable. February 3, 2014 Eric Rasmusen, Erasmuse@indiana.edu. Http://www.rasmusen.org Follow the Leader I has three pure strategy Nash equilibria of which only one is reasonable. Equilibrium Strategies Outcome

More information

Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion?

Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion? Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion? Patrick Rey and Michael D. Whinston 1 Introduction In a recent paper, Marx and Shaffer (2007) study a model of vertical contracting between a manufacturer and two

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 01 Chapter 5: Pure Strategy Nash Equilibrium Note: This is a only

More information

January 26,

January 26, January 26, 2015 Exercise 9 7.c.1, 7.d.1, 7.d.2, 8.b.1, 8.b.2, 8.b.3, 8.b.4,8.b.5, 8.d.1, 8.d.2 Example 10 There are two divisions of a firm (1 and 2) that would benefit from a research project conducted

More information

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization An Application in Industrial Organization February 23, 2015 One form of collusive behavior among firms is to restrict output in order to keep the price of the product high. This is a goal of the OPEC oil

More information

Solving dynamic portfolio choice problems by recursing on optimized portfolio weights or on the value function?

Solving dynamic portfolio choice problems by recursing on optimized portfolio weights or on the value function? DOI 0.007/s064-006-9073-z ORIGINAL PAPER Solving dynamic portfolio choice problems by recursing on optimized portfolio weights or on the value function? Jules H. van Binsbergen Michael W. Brandt Received:

More information

Seeds to Succeed? Sequential Giving to Public Projects 1

Seeds to Succeed? Sequential Giving to Public Projects 1 Seeds to Succeed? Sequential Giving to Public Projects 1 Anat Bracha Tel Aviv University Michael Menietti University of Pittsburgh Lise Vesterlund University of Pittsburgh Abstract The public phase of

More information

International Environmental Agreements and Trading Blocks - Can Issue Linkage Enhance Cooperation?

International Environmental Agreements and Trading Blocks - Can Issue Linkage Enhance Cooperation? Fondazione Eni Enrico Mattei Working Papers 6-21-2018 International Environmental Agreements and Trading Blocks - Can Issue Linkage Enhance Cooperation? Effrosyni Diamantoudi Concordia University, effrosyni.diamantoudi@concordia.ca

More information

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L. Econ 400, Final Exam Name: There are three questions taken from the material covered so far in the course. ll questions are equally weighted. If you have a question, please raise your hand and I will come

More information

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Chapter 33: Public Goods Chapter 33: Public Goods 33.1: Introduction Some people regard the message of this chapter that there are problems with the private provision of public goods as surprising or depressing. But the message

More information

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium Chapter 11 Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium In the previous chapter we examined simultaneous move games in which each player had a dominant strategy; the Prisoner s Dilemma game was one example.

More information

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Online Appendix for Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Giacomo Rodano Bank of Italy Nicolas Serrano-Velarde Bocconi University December 23, 2014 Emanuele Tarantino University of Mannheim 1 1 Reorganization,

More information

Mixed strategies in PQ-duopolies

Mixed strategies in PQ-duopolies 19th International Congress on Modelling and Simulation, Perth, Australia, 12 16 December 2011 http://mssanz.org.au/modsim2011 Mixed strategies in PQ-duopolies D. Cracau a, B. Franz b a Faculty of Economics

More information

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I 1 Prisoner s Dilemma You and your partner have both been caught red handed near the scene of a burglary. Both of you have been brought to the police station,

More information

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information Backward Induction in dynamic games of imperfect information We start at the end of the trees first find the Nash equilibrium (NE) of the last subgame

More information

FIGURE A1.1. Differences for First Mover Cutoffs (Round one to two) as a Function of Beliefs on Others Cutoffs. Second Mover Round 1 Cutoff.

FIGURE A1.1. Differences for First Mover Cutoffs (Round one to two) as a Function of Beliefs on Others Cutoffs. Second Mover Round 1 Cutoff. APPENDIX A. SUPPLEMENTARY TABLES AND FIGURES A.1. Invariance to quantitative beliefs. Figure A1.1 shows the effect of the cutoffs in round one for the second and third mover on the best-response cutoffs

More information

Investing in Institutions for Cooperation

Investing in Institutions for Cooperation Investing in Institutions for Cooperation A Major Qualifying Project Report Submitted to the Faculty of Worcester Polytechnic Institute In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Bachelor

More information

Emissions trading with non signatories in a climate agreement

Emissions trading with non signatories in a climate agreement Emissions trading with non signatories in a climate agreement An analysis of coalition stability 2 1 Kai Lessmann* Ottmar Edenhofer* Robert Marschinski* Michael Finus 4 5 3 WCERE 2010, Montreal C * Potsdam

More information

Lecture 9: Basic Oligopoly Models

Lecture 9: Basic Oligopoly Models Lecture 9: Basic Oligopoly Models Managerial Economics November 16, 2012 Prof. Dr. Sebastian Rausch Centre for Energy Policy and Economics Department of Management, Technology and Economics ETH Zürich

More information

Ruling Party Institutionalization and Autocratic Success

Ruling Party Institutionalization and Autocratic Success Ruling Party Institutionalization and Autocratic Success Scott Gehlbach University of Wisconsin, Madison E-mail: gehlbach@polisci.wisc.edu Philip Keefer The World Bank E-mail: pkeefer@worldbank.org March

More information

Illustrating Adverse Selection in Health Insurance Markets with a Classroom Game. Jennifer M. Mellor College of William and Mary

Illustrating Adverse Selection in Health Insurance Markets with a Classroom Game. Jennifer M. Mellor College of William and Mary Illustrating Adverse Selection in Health Insurance Markets with a Classroom Game Jennifer M. Mellor College of William and Mary College of William and Mary Department of Economics Working Paper Number

More information

Federal Reserve Bank of New York Staff Reports

Federal Reserve Bank of New York Staff Reports Federal Reserve Bank of New York Staff Reports Liquidity-Saving Mechanisms Antoine Martin James McAndrews Staff Report no. 282 April 2007 Revised January 2008 This paper presents preliminary findings and

More information

A simple dynamic climate cooperation model: How the prospect of future negotiations can foster participation today

A simple dynamic climate cooperation model: How the prospect of future negotiations can foster participation today A simple dynamic climate cooperation model: How the prospect of future negotiations can foster participation today Eugen Kováč Robert C. Schmidt May 18, 2018 Abstract This paper studies participation in

More information

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Juyan Zhang and Yi Zhang December 20, 2010 Abstract We investigate hold-up with simultaneous and sequential investment. We show that if the encouragement

More information

EC102: Market Institutions and Efficiency. A Double Auction Experiment. Double Auction: Experiment. Matthew Levy & Francesco Nava MT 2017

EC102: Market Institutions and Efficiency. A Double Auction Experiment. Double Auction: Experiment. Matthew Levy & Francesco Nava MT 2017 EC102: Market Institutions and Efficiency Double Auction: Experiment Matthew Levy & Francesco Nava London School of Economics MT 2017 Fig 1 Fig 1 Full LSE logo in colour The full LSE logo should be used

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Crowdfunding, Cascades and Informed Investors

Crowdfunding, Cascades and Informed Investors DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES IZA DP No. 7994 Crowdfunding, Cascades and Informed Investors Simon C. Parker February 2014 Forschungsinstitut zur Zukunft der Arbeit Institute for the Study of Labor Crowdfunding,

More information

Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy!

Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy! Maximizing Winnings on Final Jeopardy! Jessica Abramson, Natalie Collina, and William Gasarch August 2017 1 Abstract Alice and Betty are going into the final round of Jeopardy. Alice knows how much money

More information

Monetary credibility problems. 1. In ation and discretionary monetary policy. 2. Reputational solution to credibility problems

Monetary credibility problems. 1. In ation and discretionary monetary policy. 2. Reputational solution to credibility problems Monetary Economics: Macro Aspects, 2/4 2013 Henrik Jensen Department of Economics University of Copenhagen Monetary credibility problems 1. In ation and discretionary monetary policy 2. Reputational solution

More information

Are Economic Sanctions Credible and Effective in Deterring Free-Riding of an International Environmental Agreement?

Are Economic Sanctions Credible and Effective in Deterring Free-Riding of an International Environmental Agreement? Are Economic Sanctions Credible and Effective in Deterring Free-Riding of an International Environmental Agreement? by Chui Ying Lui BBA (Hons) Business Economics City University of Hong Kong An Extended

More information

Can Equity Enhance Efficiency? Lessons from the Kyoto Protocol

Can Equity Enhance Efficiency? Lessons from the Kyoto Protocol Can Equity Enhance Efficiency? Lessons from the Kyoto Protocol by Francesco Bosello*, Barbara Buchner*, Carlo Carraro** and Davide Raggi* * Fondazione Eni Enrico Mattei ** University of Venice and Fondazione

More information

Interest on Reserves, Interbank Lending, and Monetary Policy: Work in Progress

Interest on Reserves, Interbank Lending, and Monetary Policy: Work in Progress Interest on Reserves, Interbank Lending, and Monetary Policy: Work in Progress Stephen D. Williamson Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis May 14, 015 1 Introduction When a central bank operates under a floor

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 017 1. Sheila moves first and chooses either H or L. Bruce receives a signal, h or l, about Sheila s behavior. The distribution

More information