BLOWING UP POWER OF A SINGULAR CARDINAL WIDER GAPS

Similar documents
SHORT EXTENDER FORCING

Silver type theorems for collapses.

Two Stationary Sets with Different Gaps of the Power Function

Extender based forcings, fresh sets and Aronszajn trees

ADDING A LOT OF COHEN REALS BY ADDING A FEW II. 1. Introduction

Strongly compact Magidor forcing.

MODIFIED EXTENDER BASED FORCING

Sy D. Friedman. August 28, 2001

On Singular Stationarity II (tight stationarity and extenders-based methods)

Short Extenders Forcings II

MITCHELL S THEOREM REVISITED. Contents

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

On almost precipitous ideals.

Global singularization and the failure of SCH

THE SHORT EXTENDERS GAP THREE FORCING USING A MORASS

DIAGONAL PRIKRY EXTENSIONS

On the Splitting Number at Regular Cardinals

DEPTH OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS SHIMON GARTI AND SAHARON SHELAH

Philipp Moritz Lücke

The first author was supported by FWF Project P23316-N13.

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 15 Jan 1991

Level by Level Inequivalence, Strong Compactness, and GCH

LARGE CARDINALS AND L-LIKE UNIVERSES

SUCCESSIVE FAILURES OF APPROACHABILITY

ARONSZAJN TREES AND THE SUCCESSORS OF A SINGULAR CARDINAL. 1. Introduction

The Semi-Weak Square Principle

Dropping cofinalities and gaps

The (λ, κ)-fn and the order theory of bases in boolean algebras

On almost precipitous ideals.

Tall, Strong, and Strongly Compact Cardinals

A precipitous club guessing ideal on ω 1

CONSECUTIVE SINGULAR CARDINALS AND THE CONTINUUM FUNCTION

A relative of the approachability ideal, diamond and non-saturation

COMBINATORICS AT ℵ ω

A HIERARCHY OF RAMSEY-LIKE CARDINALS

ON SCH AND THE APPROACHABILITY PROPERTY

ON NORMAL PRECIPITOUS IDEALS

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 9 Dec 2006

Easton s theorem and large cardinals from the optimal hypothesis

being saturated Lemma 0.2 Suppose V = L[E]. Every Woodin cardinal is Woodin with.

Continuous images of closed sets in generalized Baire spaces ESI Workshop: Forcing and Large Cardinals

PERFECT TREE FORCINGS FOR SINGULAR CARDINALS

Währinger Strasse 25, 1090 Vienna Austria

Large Cardinals with Few Measures

On Singular Stationarity I (mutual stationarity and ideal-based methods)

Cardinal arithmetic: The Silver and Galvin-Hajnal Theorems

FORCING AND THE HALPERN-LÄUCHLI THEOREM. 1. Introduction This document is a continuation of [1]. It is intended to be part of a larger paper.

A Laver-like indestructibility for hypermeasurable cardinals

Notes to The Resurrection Axioms

Generalising the weak compactness of ω

Chapter 4. Cardinal Arithmetic.

STRONGLY UNFOLDABLE CARDINALS MADE INDESTRUCTIBLE

Chain conditions, layered partial orders and weak compactness

Characterizing large cardinals in terms of layered partial orders

Generalization by Collapse

THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET

On the strengths and weaknesses of weak squares

UPWARD STABILITY TRANSFER FOR TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS

Determinacy models and good scales at singular cardinals

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 13 Feb 2014

GUESSING MODELS IMPLY THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 25 Mar 2019

LOCAL CLUB CONDENSATION AND L-LIKENESS

COLLAPSING SUCCESSORS OF SINGULARS

Interpolation of κ-compactness and PCF

Strongly Unfoldable Cardinals Made Indestructible

ON THE SINGULAR CARDINALS. A combinatorial principle of great importance in set theory is the Global principle of Jensen [6]:

Bounds on coloring numbers

The Outer Model Programme

2. The ultrapower construction

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 27 Mar 2009

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 26 Mar 2014

RVM, RVC revisited: Clubs and Lusin sets

Axiomatization of generic extensions by homogeneous partial orderings

HEIKE MILDENBERGER AND SAHARON SHELAH

SHIMON GARTI AND SAHARON SHELAH

THE TREE PROPERTY UP TO ℵ ω+1

SOME CONSEQUENCES OF REFLECTION ON THE APPROACHABILITY IDEAL

Hierarchies of (virtual) resurrection axioms

Large cardinals and their effect on the continuum function on regular cardinals

LECTURE NOTES - ADVANCED TOPICS IN MATHEMATICAL LOGIC

January 28, 2013 EASTON S THEOREM FOR RAMSEY AND STRONGLY RAMSEY CARDINALS

arxiv: v3 [math.lo] 23 Jul 2018

Non replication of options

NORMAL MEASURES ON A TALL CARDINAL. 1. Introduction We start by recalling the definitions of some large cardinal properties.

The Resurrection Axioms

3 The Model Existence Theorem

Martingales. by D. Cox December 2, 2009

CARDINALITIES OF RESIDUE FIELDS OF NOETHERIAN INTEGRAL DOMAINS

PARTITIONS OF 2 ω AND COMPLETELY ULTRAMETRIZABLE SPACES

Notes on getting presaturation from collapsing a Woodin cardinal

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

Hod up to AD R + Θ is measurable

Large cardinals and the Continuum Hypothesis

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 24 May 2009

Fat subsets of P kappa (lambda)

An effective perfect-set theorem

Undecidability and 1-types in Intervals of the Computably Enumerable Degrees

THE FIRST MEASURABLE CARDINAL CAN BE THE FIRST UNCOUNTABLE REGULAR CARDINAL AT ANY SUCCESSOR HEIGHT

A survey of special Aronszajn trees

Transcription:

BLOWING UP POWER OF A SINGULAR CARDINAL WIDER GAPS Moti Gitik School of Mathematical Sciences Raymond and Beverly Sackler Faculty of Exact Science Tel Aviv University Ramat Aviv 69978, Israel gitik@post.tau.ac.il Abstract The paper is concerned with methods for blowing power of singular cardinals using short extenders. Thus, for example, starting with κ of cofinality ω with {α < κ o(α) α +n } cofinal in κ for every n < ω we construct a cardinal preserving extension having the same bounded subsets of κ and satisfying 2 κ = κ +δ+1 for any δ < ℵ 1. 0. Introduction In Gitik-Mitchell [Git-Mit] the following was proved: Theorem. Suppose that there is no sharp for an inner model with a strong cardinal. Let κ be a strong limit cardinal of cofinality ω and 2 κ λ > κ +, where λ is not the successor of a cardinal of cofinality less than κ. Then in the core model either (a) o(κ) λ or (b) {α < κ o(α) α +n } is cofinal in κ for each n < ω. The forcing of Gitik-Magidor [Git-Mag1] provides the equiconsistency result if λ < κ +ω. Once λ > κ +ω or κ is a singular cardinal in the core model the possibility (b) of the theorem comes into consideration. In the present paper, we continue to develop methods for adding ω-sequences to cardinals κ satisfying the condition (b) of the theorem or conditions of similar flavor. The research in 1

this direction was started in [Git1], then in [Git2] the power of κ satisfying (b) was blown up to κ ++. The paper is based on forcing techniques of [Git-Mag1,2] and [Git2], but we do not assume the detailed knowledge of these articles. Rather, we present here the necessary apparatus in a simplified form. It is assumed only that the reader is familiar with the Prikry forcing and extenders. The book of A. Kanamori [Ka] is a good reference for both of them. The paper is organized as follows: in Sections 1,2 we present simplified versions of forcings for blowing power of singular cardinals introduced in [Git-Mag2] and [Git2]. The next two sections are the main technical parts of the paper. In Section 3 it is shown how to make 2 κ = κ +3 starting with κ satisfying the condition (b). In Section 4, based on the ideas developed in Section 3, the method for obtaining 2 κ κ +δ for any δ < κ is presented. Section 5 deals with generalizations based on the idea of Shelah [Sh1]. Acknowledgement We are grateful to Menachem Magidor and to Saharon Shelah for constant interest in the work and for listening to some vague ideas that materialized in this paper. The main body of the paper was presented in a graduate course at Tel Aviv University. We would like to thank the participants: Ori Gurel, Kobi Kreminitser, Carmi Merimovich and Shmulik Regev. We are grateful to Bill Mitchell, Assaf Sharon and the referee of the paper for their remarks and corrections. 1. A Simple Extender Based Forcing In this section, we present a simplified version of extender-based forcing of Gitik-Magidor [Git-Mag1,2]. Such forcing will serve only as a motivation for one defined in the next section. Thus, the reader familiar with extender-based forcings may jump directly to Section 2. Assume GCH. Let κ be a singular cardinal of cofinality ω and λ κ + be a successor cardinal. Assume that κ = n<ω κ n, where κ n n < ω is increasing and each κ n is λ + 1- strong. This means that for every n < ω there is a (κ n, λ + )-extender E n over κ n which ultrapower contains V λ+1. We fix such E n and let j n : V M Ult(V, E n ). For every α < λ we define a κ n complete ultrafilter U nα over κ n by setting X U nα iff α j n (X). Notice that a lot of U nα s will be comparable in the Rudin-Keisler order (further RK order). Recall that U RK W iff there is f : W U such that X U iff f 1 (X) W. Thus, for example, if α β, then U n,α+β RK U n,α and U n,α+β RK U n,β. We will need a strengthening of the Rudin-Kiesler order. Thus, for α, β < λ let α En β iff α β and for 2

some f κ n κ n j n (f)(β) = α. Clearly then, α En β implies U nα RK U nβ as witnessed by any f κ n κ n with j n (f)(β) = α. The partial order λ, En is κ n -directed in the RK-order. Actually it is κ ++ n -directed (see [Git-Mag1]), but for our purposes κ n -directedness will be enough. Thus, using GCH, for some enumeration a α α < κ n of [κ n ] <κn so that for every successor cardinal δ < κ n a α α < δ enumerates [δ] <δ and every element of [δ] <δ appears stationary many times in each cofinality < δ in the enumeration. Let j n ( a α α < κ n ) = a α α < j n (κ n ). Then, a α α < λ will enumerate [λ] <λ [λ] <κ n. Let α i i < τ < κ n be an increasing sequence of ordinals below λ. Find α < λ\( i<τ α i + 1) such that a α = {α i i < τ}. Then, it is easy to show that α > En α i for every i < τ. V λ+1 M n, so M n -stationary subset of λ is really stationary. Hence we obtain the following: Lemma 1.0 For every set a λ of cardinality less than κ n there are stationary many α s < λ in every cofinality < λ so that α > En β for every β a. For every α, β < λ such that α En β we fix the projection π αβ : κ n κ n from the extender witnessing this. Let π αα = id. The following lemma is routine: Lemma 1.1 Let α, α i < λ i < τ < κ n. Assume that α En α i for every i < τ. Then there is a set A U nα so that for every i, j < τ, ν A (1) if α i En α j then π ααj (ν) = π αi α j (π ααi (ν)); and (2) if α i > α j then π ααj (ν) < π ααi (ν) Now we are ready to define our first forcing notion. We are aiming to blow up the power of κ to λ by adding λ Prikry sequences without adding new bounded subsets to κ. But now we will be much more modest. Fix some n < ω. Definition 1.2 Let Q n1 = {f f is a partial function from λ to κ n of cardinality at most κ}. We order Q n1 by inclusion. Denote this order by 1. Thus, Q n1 is basically the usual Cohen forcing for blowing the power of κ + to λ. The only minor change is that the functions are taking values inside κ n rather than 2 or κ +. 3

Definition 1.3 Let Q n0 be the set of triples a, A, f so that (1) f Q n1 (2) a λ such that (2)(i) a < κ n (2)(ii) a dom f = (2)(iii) a has a En maximal element. (3) A U nmax(a) (4) for every α, β, γ a, if α En β En γ, then π αγ (ρ) = π βγ (π αβ (ρ)) for every ρ π max(a),α A. (5) for every α > β in a and every ν A π max(a),α (ν) > π max(a),β (ν). The last two conditions require the full commutativity on A which is possible by Lemma 1.1. Definition 1.4 Let a, A, f, b, B, g Q n0. Then a, A, f 0 b, B, g ( a, A, f is stronger than b, B, g ) iff (1) f g (2) a b (3) π max(a),max(b) A B We now define a forcing notion Q n which is an extender analog of the one element Prikry forcing. 4

Definition 1.5 Q n = Q n0 Q n1. Definition 1.6 The direct extension ordering on Q n is defined to be 0 1. Definition 1.7 Let p, q Q n. Then p q iff either (1) p q or (2) p = a, A, f Q n0, q Q n1 and the following holds: (2)(a) q f (2)(b) dom q a (2)(c) q(max(a)) A (2)(d) for every β a q(β) = π max(a),β (q(max(a))). Clearly, the forcing Q n, is equivalent to Q n1, 1, i.e. the Cohen forcing. However, the following basic facts relate it to the Prikry type forcing notion. Lemma 1.8 Q n, is κ n -closed. Lemma 1.9 Q n,, satisfies the Prikry condition, i.e. for every p Q n and every statement σ of the forcing language there is q p deciding σ. Moreover, p and q have the same first coordinate. Proof. Let p = a, A, f. Suppose otherwise. By induction on ν A define an increasing sequence p ν ν A of elements of Q n1 with dom p ν a = as follows. Let p ρ ρ A ν be defined and ν A. Define p ν. Let g = ρ<ν p ρ. Then g Q n1. Consider q = a, A, g. Let q ν = g { β, π maxa,β (ν) β a}. If there is p 1 q ν deciding σ, then let p ν be some such p restricted to λ\a. Otherwise, set p ν = g. Notice that here there will always be a condition deciding σ. 5

Finally, let g = ν A p ν. Shrink A to a set B U nmax(a) so that p ν ν decides the same way or does not decide σ at all, for every ν B. By our assumption a, B, g σ. However, pick some h a, B, g, h Q n1 deciding on σ. Let h(maxa) = ν. Then, p ν ν decides σ. But this holds then for every ν B. Hence, already a, B, g decides σ. Contradiction. Let us now define the main forcing of this section by putting the blocks Q n together. Definition 1.10 The set P consists of sequences p = p n n < ω so that (1) for every n < ω p n Q n (2) there is l(p) < ω so that for every n < l(p) p n Q n1, for every n l(p) p n = a n, A n, f n Q n0 and a n a n+1. Definition 1.11 Let p = p n n < ω, q = q n n < ω P. We set p q (p q) iff for every n < ω p n Qn q n (p n Q n q n ). The proof of the next lemma is based on the argument 1.9. Lemma 1.12 P, satisfies κ ++ -c.c. It follows by the usual -system argument. For p = p n n < ω P we denote p n = p m m < n and p\n = p m m n. Let P n = {p n p P} and P\n = {p\n p P}. Then the following lemmas are obvious: Lemma 1.13 P P n P\n for every n < ω. Lemma 1.14 P\n, is κ n -closed, moreover, if p α α < δ < κ is a -increasing sequence with κ l(p0 ) > δ then there is p p α for every α < δ. The proof of the next lemma is base on the argument 1.9. Lemma 1.15 P,, satisfies the Prikry condition. Proof. Let p = p n n < ω P and σ be a statement of the forcing language. Suppose that there is no q p deciding σ. Assume for simplicity that l(p) = 0. Let p n = a n, A n, f n (n < ω). Assume also each A n consists of limit ordinals. We define by 6

induction on ν A 0 a -increasing sequence r ν ν A 0 {0} or ν = ν + 1 for some ν A 0 and a sequence q ν+1 ν A 0. Set r 0 = p. Let ν A 0 and assume that r µ µ A 0 ν or µ = µ for some µ A 0 ν, µ < ν, q µ+1 µ A 0 ν are defined. Assume, as an inductive assumption, that for each µ A 0 ν a 0 (r µ ) = a 0 and A 0 (r µ ) = A 0, where for t P, t = t n n < ω we denote by a n (t) the first coordinate of t n, by A n (t) the second and by f n (t) the third coordinate of t. Define r ν using 1.14 to be a -extension of r µ µ A 0 ν with a 0 (r ν ) = a 0. Consider r ν < ν >= r ν 0 < ν >, r ν 1,..., r ν n,... n < ω where r ν 0 < ν >= f 0 (r ν ) { β, π maxa0,β(ν) β a 0 }. If there is no q r ν < ν > deciding σ then set q ν+1 = r ν < ν > and r ν+1 = r ν. Otherwise, let q ν+1 be such a condition. Define r ν+1 = rn ν+1 n < ω as follows. For every n, 1 n < ω, set rn ν+1 = qn ν+1 and let r0 ν+1 = a 0, A 0, q0 ν+1 (λ\a 0 ). This completes the construction of r ν ν A 0 {0} or ν = ν + 1 for some ν A 0 and q ν+1 ν A 0. Using 1.14 and the inductive assumption it is easy to find a -extension r of r ν s so that a 0 (r ) = a 0 and A 0 (r ) = A 0. Shrink the set A 0 to a set A 0 so that for every ν A 0 r < ν > σ. Since r p and we assumed that no -extension of p decides σ, A 0 U 0,max(a0 ). Let p(0) be the condition obtained from r by replacing A 0 in it by A 0. Now we should repeat the argument above with p(0) replacing p and pairs ν 0, ν 1 from A 0 A 1 (p(0)) replacing ν s from A 0. This will define p(1). Continue in the same fashion for each n < ω. Finally any extension deciding σ of a -extension of p(n) n < ω will easily provide a contradiction. Combining these lemmas we obtain the following: Proposition 1.16 all the cardinals above κ +. The forcing P, does not add new bounded subsets to κ and preserves Actually, it is not hard to show that κ + is preserved as well. Finally, let us show that this forcing adds λ ω-sequences to κ. generic. For every n < ω define a function F n : λ κ n as follows: F n (α) = ν if for some p = p m m < ω G l(p) > n and p n (α) = ν. Thus, let G P be Now for every α < λ set t α = F n (α) n < ω. Let us show that the set {t α α < λ} has cardinality λ. Lemma 1.17 For every β < λ there is α, β < α < λ such that t α is different from every t γ with γ β. 7

Proof. Suppose otherwise. Then there is p = p n n < ω G and β < λ such that p α(β < α < λ γ β t = t α γ). ) For every n l(p) let p n = a n, A n, f n. Pick some α λ\( n<ω a n dom f n (β + 1). We extend p to a condition q so that q p and for every n l(q) = l(p) α b n, where q n = b n, B n, g n. Then q will force that t α dominates every t γ with γ < α. This leads to the contradiction. Thus, let γ < α and assume that q belongs to the generic subset of P. Then either t γ V or it is a new ω-sequence. If t γ V then it is dominated by t α by the usual density arguments. If t γ is new, then for some r q in the generic set γ c n for every n l(r), where r n = c n, C n, h n. Here we use the second part of 1.10(2). But also α c n since c n b n. This implies F n (α) > F n (γ) (see 1.3(5)) and we are done. 2. Short Extenders Replacing Long Ones In this section, we define basic tools which will be used in further forcing constructions. The material is simplified and adapted for further purposes from the version of [Git2]. We assume GCH. Let κ = n<ω κ n, κ 0 < κ 1 < < κ n < and for every n < ω κ n is λ n + 1-strong, where λ n is a regular and not the successor of a singular cardinal satisfying κ +n+2 n λ n < κ n+1. Thus, instead of one λ above κ + in Section 1, we have different λ n below κ. In this section, we will sketch the main result of [Git2] that even λ n = κ +n+2 n (n < ω) will be enough for blowing the power of κ to κ ++. For each n < ω we fix an extender E n witnessing λ n + 1-strongness of κ n. We define ultrafilters U nα (α < λ n ) as in Section 1 by setting X U nα iff α j n (X), where j n : V M Ult(V, E n ). Also the order En λ n is defined as in Section 1. Let λ be a regular cardinal above κ. The first idea for blowing power of κ to λ is to simulate the forcing P of Section 1. It was built from blocks Q n s. The essential part of Q n is Q n0 which typical element has a form a, A, f, where f is a Cohen condition, A is a set of measure one, but the main and problematic part a λ is actually a set of indexes of the extender E n. E n had length λ in Section 1 but now it is very short. Its length is λ n < κ n+1 < κ. Here we take a to be an order preserving function from λ into the set of indexes of E n, i.e. into λ n. Formally: Definition 2.1 Let Q n0 be the set of triples a, A, f so that (1) f Q n1, where Q n1 is defined in 1.2. over 8

(2) a is a partial order preserving function from λ to λ n such that (2)(i) a < κ n (2)(ii) dom a dom f = (2)(iii) rnga has a En maximal element (3) A U nmax(rnga) (4) for every α, β, γ rnga, if α En β En γ then π αγ (ρ) = π βγ (π αβ (ρ)) for every ρ π max(rnga),α A (5) for every α > β in rnga and ν A π max(rnga),α (ν) > π max(rnga),β (ν). The ordering 0 of Q n0 is defined as in 1.4 only (b), (c) and (d) of 1.7(2) should by now formulated as follows: (b) dom q dom a (c) q(max(dom a)) A (d) for every β dom a q(β) = π max(rnga),a(β) (q(max(a))). Lemmas 1.8, 1.9 are valid here with proofs requiring minor changes. The forcing P of 1.10 is defined here similarly: Definition 2.2 The set P consists of sequences p = p n n < ω so that (1) for every n < ω p n Q n (2) there is l(p) < ω so that for every n < ω p n Q n1, for every n l(p) p n = a n, A n, f n and dom a n dom a n+1. 9

Definition 2.3 Let p = p n n < ω, q = q n n < ω P. We define p q p n Qn q n (p n Q n q n ). (p q) iff for every n < ω For p = p n n < ω P let p n = p m m < n and p\n = p m m n. Set P n = {p n p P} and P\n = {p\n p P}. The following lemmas are obvious: Lemma 2.4 P P n P\n for every n < ω. Lemma 2.5 P\n, is κ n -closed. The proof of the Prikry condition is the same as 1.15. Lemma 2.6 P,, satisfies the Prikry condition. The ω-sequences t α = F α (n) n < ω defined as in Section 1 will witness that λ new ω-sequences are added by P,. Thus we obtain the following: Proposition 2.7 λ new ω-sequences to κ. The forcing P, does not add new bounded subsets to κ and it adds The problem is that κ ++ -c.c. fails badly. Thus, any two conditions p and q such that for infinitely many n s rnga n (p) = rnga n (q) but dom a n (p) dom a n (q) are incompatible. Using this it is possible to show that P, collapses λ to κ +. The rest of the section and actually of the paper will be devoted to the task of repairing the chain condition. Thus we shall identify various conditions in P. The basic idea goes back to the problem raised in [Git-Mit,Q.1] on independence of the assignment function of precovering sets and its solution in [Git1]. Roughly speaking it is possible to arrange a situation where a Prikry sequence may correspond to various measures of extenders E n s. Fix n < ω. For every k n we consider a language L n,k containing two relation symbols, a function symbol, a constant c α for every α < κ +k n and constants c λn, c. Consider a structure a n,k = H(χ +k ),, E n, the enumeration of [λ n ] <λn (as in 1.0), λ n, χ, 0, 1,..., α... α < κ +k n in this language, where χ is a regular cardinal large enough. For an ordinal ξ < χ (usually ξ will be below λ n ) we denote by tp n,k (ξ) the L n,k -type realized by ξ in a n,k. Let L n,k be the language obtained from L n,k by adding a new constant c. For δ < χ let a n,k,δ be the L n,k -structure obtained from a n,k by interpreting c as δ. The type tp n,k (δ, ξ) is the L n,k type realized by ξ in a n,k,δ. Further, we shall identify types with ordinals corresponding to them in some fixed well-ordering of the power sets of κ +k n s. 10

Definition 2.8 Let k n and β < λ n. β is called k-good iff (1) for every γ < β tp n,k (γ, β) is realized unboundedly many times below λ n ; (2) for every a β if a < κ n then there is α < β corresponding to a in the enumeration of [λ n ] <λn. β is called good if it is k-good for some k n. Further we will be interested mainly in k-good ordinals for k > 2. If α, β < λ n realize the same k-type for k > 2, then U nα = U nβ, since the number of different U nα s is κ ++ n. Recall that we assume that each λ n is a regular cardinal and is not the successor of a singular. Lemma 2.9 The set {β < λ n β is n good} {β < λ n cfβ < κ n } contains a club. Proof. Let us show first that the set {β < λ n γ < β tp n,n (γ, β) is realized unboundedly often } contains a club. Suppose otherwise. Let S be a stationary set of β s such that there is γ β < β with tp(γ β, β) realized only boundedly many times below λ n. Shrink S to a stationary S on which all γ β s are the same. Let γ β = γ for every β S. The total number of n-types over γ, i.e. tp n,n (γ, ) is κ +n+1 n < λ n. Hence, there is a stationary S S such that for every α, β S tp n,n (γ, α) = tp n,n (γ, β). In particular the type tp n,n (γ, β) is realized unboundedly often below λ n. Contradiction. Now, in order to finish the proof, notice that whenever N a n,n, β = N λ n < λ n and κ n > N N then β satisfies (2) of 2.8. Lemma 2.10 k 1-good ordinals below β. Proof. Suppose that n k > 0 and β is k-good. Then there are arbitrarily large Let γ < β. Pick some α > β realizing tp n,k (γ, β). The facts that γ < β < α and β is k 1-good can be expressed in the language L n,k. So the statement y(γ < y < x) (y is (k 1-good) belongs to tp n,k (γ, α) = tp n,k (γ, β). Hence, there is δ, γ < δ < β which is k 1-good. Let us now define a refinement of the forcing P of 2.2. 11

Definition 2.11 The set P is the subset of P consisting of sequences p = p n n < ω so that for every n, l(p) n < ω and β dom a n there is a nondecreasing converging to infinity sequence of natural numbers k m n m < ω so that for every m n a m (β) is k m -good, where p m = a m, A m, f m. The orders on P are just the restrictions of and of P. The following lemma is crucial for showing the Prikry property of P,,. Lemma 2.12. P, is κ 0 -closed. Proof. Let p α α < µ < κ 0 be a -increasing sequence of elements of P. Suppose for simplicity that l(p 0 ) = 0 and hence for every α < µ l(p α ) = 0. Let p α n = a α n, A α n, f α n for every n < ω and α < µ. For each n < ω set f n = α<µ f n α and a n = α<µ aα n. Let β be a sup dom n<ω a n. We like to extend a n by corresponding to β an ordinal δ n < λ n which is above (rnga n ), RK-above every element of rnga n and also is n-good. Such δ n exists by Lemmas 1.0 and 2.9. Set b n = a n { β, δn } and B n = α<µ π 1 δ nmax(rnga α) (Aα n). We define q n = b n, B n, f n and q = q n n < ω. Then q p α, for every α < µ and q P. Since the only new element added is β and for every n < ω b n (β) = δ n is n-good. Now it is routine to show analogue of 2.4.7 for P,,. Lemma 2.13. P,, satisfies the Prikry condition. Lemma 2.14. For every n < ω P P n P \n. Lemma 2.15. P, does not add new bounded subsets to κ and it adds λ new ω- sequences to κ. Unfortunately, P still collapses λ to κ +. Let us now define an equivalence relation on P. Definition 2.16 Let p = p n n < ω, q = q n n < ω P. We call p and q equivalent and denote this by p q iff (1) l(p) = l(q) (2) for every n < l(p) p n = q n 12

(3) there is a nondecreasing sequence k n l(p) n < ω with lim n k n = and k l(p) > 2 such that for every n, l(p) n < ω the following holds: (a) f n = g n (b) dom a n = dom b n (c) rnga n and rngb n are realizing the same k n -type, (i.e. the least ordinals coding rnga n and rngb n are such) (d) A n = B n, where p n = a n, A n, f n and q n = b n, B n, g n. Notice that, in particular the following is also true: (e) for every δ dom a n = dom b n a n (δ) and b n (δ) are realizing the same k n -type (f) for every δ dom a n = dom b n and l k n a n (δ) is l-good if b n (δ) is l-good (g) for every δ dom a n = dom b n max(rnga n ) projects to a n (δ) the same way as max(rngb n ) projects to b n (δ), i.e. the projection functions π max(ngan ),a n (δ) and π max(rngbn),bn(δ) are the same. Let us also define a preordering on P. Definition 2.17. Let p, q P. Set p q iff there is a sequence of conditions r k k < m < ω so that (1) r 0 = p (2) r m 1 = q (3) for every k < m 1 r k r k+1 or r k r k+1. The next two lemmas show that P, is a nice subforcing of P,. Lemma 2.18. Let p, q, s P. Suppose that p q and s p. Then there are s s and t q such that s t. 13

Proof. Let k n l(p) = l(q) n < ω be as in 2.16(3) witnessing p q. We need to define s = s n n < ω and t = t n n < ω. Set s n = t n = s n for every n < l(p) = l(q). Set also s n = s n for every n < l(s). Now let l(p) n < l(s). We show that q n = b n, B n, g n extends to s n in the ordering of Q n and then we ll set t n = s n. Let p n = a n, A n, f n. By 2.16(3), f n = g n and A n = B n. We know that s n a n, A n, f n (in the ordering of Q n ), hence s n (max(dom a n )) A n and for every β dom a n s n (β) = π max(rng an),a n(β)(s n (max(dom a n ))). But by 2.16(3) π max(rng (an)),an(β) = π max(rng bn),bn(β) and dom a n = dom b n. Thus, s n b n, A n, f n = q n. Suppose now that n l(s). Let p n = a n, A n, f n, q n = b n, A n, f n and s n = c n, C n, h n. Case 1. k n = 3. Then we first extend s n to a condition s n Q n1 and proceed as above. Case 2. k n > 3. Set s n = s n. Then rnga n and rngb n are realizing the same k n -type. Thus it is possible to find d n realizing the same k n 1-type over rngb n as rngc n over rnga n. Let d n be the order preserving function from dom a n onto d n. Set t n = d n, C n, h n. This completes the construction. s = s n n < ω and t = t n n < ω are as desired. Lemma 2.19 For every p, q P such that p q there is s p so that q s. The proof is an inductive application of the previous lemma. Thus, suppose for example that q c a b p 14

i.e. a, b, c are witnessing p q. We apply Lemma 2.18 to a, b and c. It provides equivalent c c and a a. But then a p and q a, since a c q c Lemma 2.20 P, satisfies λ-c.c. Proof. Let p α α < λ be a sequence of elements of P. Using the -system argument it is easy to find a stationary S λ, δ < mins, l < ω so that for every α, β S, α < β the following holds (a) l(p α ) = l (b) for every n < l p α n and p β n are compatible (c) for every n l let p α n = a α n, A α n, fn α, then (c)(i) A α n = A β n (c)(ii) f α n, f β n are compatible and min(dom f β n \δ) β > sup(dom f α n ) + sup(dom a α n) (c)(iii) a α n δ = a β n δ (c)(iv) min(dom a β n\δ) β > sup(dom f α n ) + sup(dom a α n) (c)(v) rng a α n = rng a β n. Let α < β be in S. We claim that p α and p β are compatible in P,. Define equivalent conditions p p α and q p β. First we set p n = q n = p α n p β n for n < l. Let τ α = ) ) min( n l dom aαn\δ and τ β = min( n l dom aαn\δ. Assume for simplicity that τ α dom a α l and τ β dom a β l. By 2.11 there is a nondecreasing converging to infinity sequences of natural numbers k m l m < ω so that for every m l a α m(τ α ) = a β m(τ β ) is k m -good. Let n l. 15

Case 1. k n 4. Pick some ν A α n = A β n. Set p n = q n = f α n f β n { γ, π max(rnga α n ),a α n(γ)(ν) γ dom a α n} { γ, π max(rng a β n ),a β n(γ) (ν) γ dom aβ n}. The condition (c) above insures that this is a function in Q n1. Case 2. k n > 4. Using Lemmas 2.9, 2.10 for a α n(τ α ) = a β n(τ β ), we find t α realizing the same k n 1-type over rnga α n δ = rnga β n δ as rng(a α n\δ) = rng(a β n\δ) does so that mint α > max(rnga α n). Set a n = rnga α n t α. rng(a β n\δ) realizes over rnga α n δ the same type as t α. Hence there is t β so that min(rnga β n\δ) = a β n(τ β ) > maxt β and if b n = rnga β n t β, then a n and b n are realizing the same k n 1-type. Now pick n-good ordinal ξ coding a n. Using the k n 1 equivalence of a n, b n find k n 2-good ordinal ρ coding b n and so that ξ and ρ (and hence also a n {ξ} and b n {ρ} realize the same k n 2-type. Pick some γ > ( ) k<ω dom f β k dom aβ k. Let a n be the order isomorphism between dom a α n dom a β n {γ} and a n {ξ}. Let b n be the order isomorphism between dom a α n dom a β n {γ} and b n {ρ}. We define p n = a n, A α n, f α n f β n and q n = b n, A α n, f α n f β n. By the construction such defined p and q are equivalent. So we are done.. Thus the forcing with P, preserves λ. However, it is not hard to see that all the cardinals (if any) in the interval (κ +, λ) are collapsed to κ +. In any case, starting with λ = κ ++ and λ n = κ +n+2 n (n < ω) we obtain the main result of [Git2]: The forcing with P, preserves the cardinals, does not add new bounded subsets to κ and makes 2 κ = κ ++. 3 The Gap Three Case The goal of this section will be to get 2 κ = κ +++ preserving κ ++ and κ +++. The problem with the straightforward generalization of the forcing P, of the previous section is that the -system argument of Lemma 2.20 breaks down, once replacing κ ++ by κ +++. The point is as follows. Suppose that at some level n < ω we have an α (κ ++, κ +++ ) corresponding to some α. Let cfα = cfα = ℵ 0. Then there is a cofinal in α sequence α m m < ω simply definable from α (say, for example, the least cofinal 16

sequence in the canonical well ordering). But now there are κ ++ (and not κ + as in Section 2) different cofinal ω-sequences in α that may correspond to αm m < ω. Clearly, different choices will provide incompatible conditions. In order to overcome this difficulty, we will pick an elementary submodel A of cardinality κ + with α inside and correspond it to an elementary submodel A on the level n with α inside. We allow only elements of A to correspond to elements of A. This will restrict the number of choices to κ +. The problem now will be how to choose and put together such models for different α s. This matter is handled generically using a preparation forcing P which will be κ ++ -strategically closed. It is desired on one hand to shrink generically P in order to get κ ++ -c.c. and on the the other hand to keep a large enough part of P in order to insure the Prikry condition. The main issue will be the definition of such forcing P. We start with a definition of a poset P which will serve as a part of P over κ. Definition 3.1 The set P consists of elements of the form A 00, A 10, A 01, A 11 so that the following holds (1) A 0i (i 2) is an elementary submodel of H(κ +3 ),, κ, κ +, κ ++ such that (a) A 0i = κ +i+1, A 0i κ +i+1 (b) κ+i A 0i A 0i (c) A 01 κ +3 is an ordinal (2) A 00 A 01 (3) for every i < 2 A 1i is a set of at most κ +i+1 elementary submodels of A 0i so that (a) A 0i A 1i (b) for every B A 11 B κ +3 is an ordinal (c) if B, C A 1i and B C then B C (d) if B, C A 11 then either B = C, B C or C B (e) if B, C A 10, B C, B C and C B then (i) otp(b κ +3 ) = otp(c κ +3 ) implies that B κ ++ = C κ ++ and there are D B A 11 A 00 and D C A 11 A 00 so that B C = D B B = D C C 17

(ii) otp(b κ +3 ) < otp(c κ +3 ) implies that there are B, C A 10 such that B B, C C otp(b κ +3 ) = otp(c κ +3 ), otp(b κ +3 ) = otp(c κ +3 ), both pairs (B, C ) and (B, C) satisfy (i), B C = B C = B C, B, B, < and C, C, < are isomorphic over B C. (f) if B A 10 is a successor point of A 10 then B has at most two immediate predecessors (under the inclusion) and is closed under κ-sequences (g) if B A 10 then either B is a successor point of A 10 or B is a limit element and there is a closed chain of B A 10 unbounded in B A 10 (h) A 11 is a closed chain of models with successor points closed under κ + -sequences, in particular {B κ +++ B A 11 } is a closed set of κ ++ ordinals (4) for every B A 11 there is B (A 00 A 11 ) {H(κ +3 )} so that B A 00 = B A 00. Let A 10 in be the set {B B B A 10 and B A 11 }. By (4), then A 10 in = {B B B A 10 and B (A 00 A 11 ) {H(κ +3 )}}. Definition 3.2 Let x = A 00, A 10, A 01, A 11, y = B 00, B 10, B 01, B 11 be elements of P. Then x y iff for every i < 2 (1) A 1i B 1i (2) for every A A 11 A B 01 B 11. (3) for every A A 10 A B 00 B 10 B 10 in. Definition 3.3 We define P 1 = { A 01, A 11 for some A 00, A 10 A 00, A 10, A 01, A 11 P }. For a generic G(P 1) P 1 we define P <1 = { A 00, A 10 there is A 01, A 11 G(P 1) A 00, A 10, A 01, A 11 P }. The following two lemmas are obvious. Lemma 3.4 P P 1 P <1. Lemma 3.5 P 1 is κ +3 -closed forcing. It is actually isomorphic to the Cohen forcing for adding a new subset to κ +3. 18

Lemma 3.6 P is κ ++ -closed. Proof. Let x α = A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α P, α < α < κ ++. Suppose that x α < x α+1 for every α < α. We define x α > x α for all α < α as follows. Let A 00 be the closure of α<α A 00 α { A 11 α α < α } under κ-sequences and Skolem functions. Set A 01 α α to be an elementary submodel of H(κ +3 ) including A 01 α α < α, A 00 α, closed under κ+ -sequences and having the intersection with κ +3 an ordinal. Let A 1i α = α<α A 1i α {A 0i α } { α<α A 0i α } for i < 2. We need to check that x α = A 00 α, A10 α, A01 α, A11 α is in P and is stronger than each x α for α < α. Most of the conditions are trivial. Let us check only 3.1(4). Thus let B A 11. We need to find B (A 00 α A11 α ) {H(κ+3 )} so that B A 00 α = B A 00 α. α \A00 α If B = A01 α then we take B = H(κ +3 ). Now suppose that B α<α A 1i α. If B κ +3 sup(a 00 α κ+3 ) then we can take again B = H(κ +3 ). Suppose that B κ +3 < sup(a 00 α κ+3 ). Let δ A 00 α κ+3 be the minimal above B κ +3. Recall that E = {D κ +3 D A 11 α } is a closed set of ordinals by 3.1(h). Also, E 1 = E\{max(E)} A 00 α. But then A00 α (E 1 is unbounded in δ). Hence δ E 1. So there is B α<α A 11 α A 00 α B κ +3 = δ. Then B A 00 α = A00 α δ = A00 α B. The following observation will be crucial for proving κ ++ -c.c. of the final forcing. Lemma 3.7 Suppose that A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α α α is an increasing sequence of elements of P. Assume that β<α A00 β A 10 α for every α α. Let B A 10 α and otp(b κ +3 ) < otp(a 00 0 κ +3 ). Then the set {B A 00 α α < α } is finite. Proof. Suppose otherwise. We pick the least ρ α so that for some B A 10 ρ with otp(b κ +3 ) < otp(a 0 0 κ +3 ) the set {B A 00 α α < ρ} is infinite. Notice that B α<ρ A00 α. Since otherwise B A 00 ρ for some ρ < ρ and then B A 00 α for all α, ρ α < ρ. So, {B A 00 α α < ρ } ℵ 0 which contradicts the minimality of ρ. Let C = α<ρ A00 α. Then C A 10 ρ. Now, both sets C\B and B \C are nonempty. The first one since otp(c κ +3 ) > otp(b κ +3 ). The second one since B C implies B C by 3.1(3(c)) but we just showed that B C. Then 3.1(e(ii)) applies. So there is C C A 10 ρ with otp(c κ +3 ) = otp(b κ +3 ) such that B C = B C and the pair (B, C ) satisfies 3.1(e(i)). Hence B C κ +3 = B C κ +3 = C D C κ +3 = B D B κ +3 where D B, D C witness 3.1(e(i)). Now, for every α < ρ B A 00 α κ +3 = (B C) A 00 α κ +3 = B C A 00 α κ +3 = C D C A 00 α κ +3 = (C A 00 α ) D C κ +3. This implies that the set {C A 00 α α < ρ} is infinite. But C C = α<ρ A00 α. So, as above we can now reduce ρ. Contradiction. 19

Lemma 3.8 Suppose that A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α α α is an increasing sequence of elements of P with α a limit ordinal. Let B A 10 α. Then there is α < α satisfying the following: (1) if otp(b κ +3 ) < otp(a 00 α κ +3 ) for some α < α and β<α A00 β A10 α for every α α then otp(b κ +3 ) < otp(a 00 α κ +3 ) and there are B A 00 α Aα 10, D B A 00 α A 11 α so that for every α, α > α α B A 00 α = B D B (2) if for every α < α otp(b κ +3 ) > otp(a 00 α κ +3 ) then there is D (A 00 α A 11 α ) {H(κ +3 )} so that for every α, α > α α B A 00 α = D A 00 α Remark 3.8.1 Notice that for B, C A 10 α if B κ++ < C κ ++ then otp(b κ +3 ) < otp(c κ +3 ) by 3.1(e). Proof. (1) By Lemma 3.7, there is α < α so that for every α, α α < α B A 00 α = B A 00 α. Using 3.2(3) for α and α we find B A 00 α A 10 α and D B A 00 α Aα 11 so that B A 00 α = B D B. (2) If B α<α A 00 α, then use D = H(κ +3 ). Suppose that B ( α<α A 00 α. Pick then the ) least δ α<α A 00 α \B κ +3. Let α < α be the least such that δ A 00 α. Clearly, B α<α A 00 α δ. Also, by 3.1(3e(ii)) δ > κ ++. Claim For every α, α α < α B A 00 α κ +3 = A 00 α δ. Proof. Suppose otherwise. Then there are α, α α < α and ξ B A 00 α \δ. Consider the least f ξ : κ ++ ξ. It belongs to B A 00 α. Now, δ A00 α ξ, so there is ν A00 α κ++ such that f τ (ν) = δ. But B A 00 α κ++, so ν B and hence also δ B. Contradiction. of the claim. Now, we apply 3.2(3) to B A 10 α and A00 α. It implies that B A 00 α Aα 10 A 10 in. Notice that B κ ++ > A 00 α κ ++. Hence B A 00 α / Aα 10. So B A 00 α A 10 in. It implies that for some D A 00 α A 11 α B Aα 00 = A 00 α D. 20

But D κ +++ is an ordinal. Hence, it should be exactly δ and we are done. Lemma 3.8.1. Suppose that A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α α α be an increasing sequence of elements of P with α a limit ordinal of uncountable cofinality. Let B A 10 α under ω-sequence of its elements and otp(b κ +3 ) > otp(a 00 α and D (A 00 α Aα 11 ) {H(κ +3 } so that be closed κ +3 ) then there are α < α (a) for every α, α > α α B A 00 α = D A 00 α (b) for every β B κ +3 \ sup(b A 00 α the least such γ is in A 00 α. κ +3 ) if there is γ ( α<α A 00 α κ +3 )\β then The proof is an easy application of 3.8 and fact that above sup(b A 00 α κ +3 ) only finitely many overlaps between B κ +3 and α<α A 00 α κ +3 are possible since ω B B. We are not going to force with P,, so the next lemma is not needed for the main results but we think that it contributes to the understanding of the main forcing and it will be used also in the proof for the main forcing. Lemma 3.9 P <1 satisfies κ +3 -c.c. in V P 1. Proof. Suppose otherwise. Let us assume that 00 P 1 A, A 10 α < α α κ+3 is an antichain in P <1. Define by induction an increasing sequence of conditions of P 1 A 01 α, A 11 α α < κ +3 and a sequence A 00 α, A 10 α α < κ +3 so that for every α < κ +3 A 01 α, A 11 α P 00 1 A, A 10 = α α Ǎ00 α, Ǎ10 α. P 1 does not add new sets of size κ ++, so there is no problem with the induction. Let A 10 α = {X αi i < κ + } for all α < κ +3. We now form a -system from A 00 α, A 10 α α < κ +3. Thus we can insure that the following holds for some δ < κ +3, for every β < α < κ +3 : (a) A 00 α δ = A 00 β δ, min(a00 α \δ) α > A 01 β κ+3 + sup(a 00 β κ+3 ). (b) the function taking X αi to X βi (i < κ + ) is an isomorphism between the structures A 01 α, and A 01 β, (c) A 00 α, < A 00 β, < by isomorphism π so that π A00 α every i < κ +. 21 δ = id and π X αi = X βi for

Let us now show that A 00 α, A 10 α and A 00 β, A10 β are compatible in P <1 for α < β < κ +3. It is enough to prove compatibility of A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α and A 00 β, A10 β, A01 β, A11 β in P. We define a condition A 00, A 10, A 01, A 11 stronger than both of the conditions above. Take A 01 = A 01 α and A 11 = A 11 α. Let A 00 be an elementary submodel of cardinality κ + including {A 00 α, A 00 β, A10 α, A 10 β, A01 α, A 11 α } and closed under κ-sequences. Set A 10 = A 10 α A 10 β {A 00 }. Let ν α = min(a 00 α \δ) and ν β = min(a 00 β \δ). Claim 3.9.1. There are D α A 11 α A 00 α and D β A 11 β A00 β D β κ +3 = ν β. Proof. so that D α κ +3 = ν α and Let us show this for α. The same argument will work also for β. We use 3.1(4) for A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α. Thus A 01 0 A 11 α, so A 01 0 A 00 α = D α A 00 α for some D α A 11 α A 00 α. But then D α κ +3 should be ν α since δ < A 01 0 κ +3 < α ν α A 00 α and (A 00 α κ +3 ) (δ, ν α ) =. of the claim Let us check that A 00, A 01, A 01, A 11 is a condition. The only problematic cases are 3.1(3e), (4). Thus let B, C be as in 3.1(3e)(i). Then B A 00 α {A 00 α } and C A 00 β {A00 β }. If B = A 00 α (or C = A 00 β ) then C = A00 β (or B = A00 α ). So, B C = B D α = C D β by the claim. Suppose otherwise. Find i < κ +3 such that B = X αi. Consider B = X βi. Then B A 10 β. We apply 3.1(3(e)(i)) to B and C inside A 10 β. There are D B A11 β A00 β D C A 11 β A00 β A00 β so that B C = D B B = D C C. Also B κ ++ = C κ ++. But δ > κ + and the isomorphism π of (c) is the identity on δ. So, B κ ++ = B κ ++ = C κ ++ B C κ +3 = B C δ = (B δ) C = (B δ) C δ = B C δ = C D C δ. Now, if D C κ +3 δ, then D C δ = δ and hence C D C δ = C D β. If D C κ +3 < δ, then C D C δ = C D C κ +3. Hence B C = C D β or B C = C D C. In order to find D A 11 α A 00 α so that B C = B D we just repeat the argument first picking C = X αj and working inside A 10 α, where C = X βj. Let us now check 3.1(e)(ii). Assume that B, C are as above but otp(b κ +3 ) < otp(c κ +3 ). We find i, j < κ + so that B = X αi and C = X βj. Let B = X αj. Then B A 10 α and otp( B κ +3 ) = otp(c κ +3 ) > otp(b κ +3 ). Apply 3.1(e(ii)) to B, B. There will be B, B A 10 α, B B, B B witnessing 3.1(e(ii)) for A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α. Find i, j such that B = X αi and B = X αj. Set C = X βj. Let us show that such B, C are as desired. First notice that otp(b κ +3 ) = otp( B κ +3 ) = otp(x αj κ +3 ) = otp(x βj κ +3 ) = otp(c κ +3 ) by condition (b) on -system. Similar, otp(b κ +3 ) = otp(c κ +3 ). Now, B C = B C δ = B B δ. By (a) and since the isomorphism π of (c) is identity on δ. We continue, B B δ = B B δ = B B δ by the choice of B, B. Again by and 22

the choice of π we obtain B B δ = B C δ and B B δ = B C δ. By (a) we have B C δ = B C and B C δ = B C. Hence B C = B C = B C. Also B, B, < and C, C, < are order isomorphic over B C. Since B, B, <, B, B, < are order isomorphic overb B, B, B, <, C, C B C κ +3 = B C δ. < are order isomorphic over δ and Let us now check 3.1(4). Suppose that B A 11 = A 11 α. Let ν = B κ +3. If ν sup A 00 then it is trivial. Suppose otherwise. Let ρ = mina 00 \ν. We picked A 00 so that A 11 α A 00. Hence, {D κ +3 D A 11 α } is unbounded in ρ and so for some D ρ A 11 α D ρ κ +3 = ρ. Then D ρ A 00 (it is uniquely determined by its ordinal part). Hence B A 00 = D ρ A 00 and we are done. Finally let us show that A 00, A 10, A 00, A 11 is stronger than A 00 α, A 10 α, A 01 α, A 11 α and A 00, A01. Let us show this for α. We need only to check 3.2(3). Thus β, A10 β β, A11 β let A A 10 = A 10 α A 10 β {A00 }. If A A α then A A 00 α = A A 10 α. If A = A 00 then A A 00 α = A 00 α A 10 α. Suppose now that A A 10 β. Then A A00 α = A δ. Let A = X βi for some i < κ +. Consider A = X αi. Then A δ = A δ. Let D α be as in the claim. It follows that A A 00 α = A δ = A δ = A D α. But D α A 11 α and A A 10, so A D α A 10 αin. Hence we are done. Let us now define our main preparation forcing. Definition 3.10 The set P consists of pairs of triples A 0τ, A 1τ, F τ τ < 2 so that the following holds: (0) A 00, A 10, A 01, A 11 P (1) F 0 F 1 P, where P,, is as defined in Section 2 (2) for every τ < 2 F τ is as follows: (a) F τ = κ +τ+1 (b) for every p = p n n < ω F τ if n < l(p) then every α appearing in p n is in A 0τ κ +3 ; if n l(p), and p n = a n, A n, f n, then every α appearing in f n is in A 0τ κ +3 and dom a n (A 01 κ +3 ) A 11 {B A 01 B = κ + } if τ = 1, dom a n (A 00 κ +3 ) A 10 A 10 in if τ = 0. We also require that every nonordinal member B of dom a n is closed under κ sequences if B = κ + and κ + -sequences if B = κ ++. Let l(p) n < ω and p n = a n, A n, f n. 23

(c) there is an element of dom a n, maximal under inclusion, it belongs to A 1τ or to A 1τ in A 1τ if τ = 0 and every other element of dom a n maximal under inclusion belongs to it. Let us further denote this element as max 1 (a n ) or max 1 (p n ). (d) if B dom a n \On, then a n (B) is an elementary submodel of a n,kn of Section 2 with 3 k n n. We require that a n (B) = κ +n+τ +1 n whenever B = κ +τ +1 (τ < 2). and κ+n+τ n (a n (B)) a n (B) (e) for every B dom a n \κ +3 and α dom a n κ +3 α B iff a n (α) a n (B) (f) for every B, C dom a n \κ +3 (f1) B C iff a n (B) a n (C) (f2) B\C and C\B iff a n (B)\a n (C) and a n (C)\a n (B). If this happens then the positions of B, C and a n (B), a n (C) are the same, i.e. 3.1(e(i),(ii)) holds simultaneously for both of the pairs. The next two conditions deal with cofinalities of correspondence: (g)(i) if α dom a n κ +3 and cfα κ + then a n (α) < κ +n+3 n and cf a n (α) κ +n+1 n (g)(ii) if α dom a n κ +3 and cfα = κ ++ then a n (α) < κ n +n+3. and cfa n (α) = κ +n+2 n. (h) if p F τ and q P is equivalent to p (i.e. p q as in Section 2) with witnessing sequence k n n < ω starting with k 0 4, then q F τ. (i) if p = p n n < ω F τ and q = q n n < ω P are such that (i) l(p) = l(q) (ii) for every n < l(p) p n = q n (iii) for every n l(p) a n = b n and dom g n A 0τ κ +3, where p n = a n, A n, f n, q n = b n, B n, g n then q F τ. The meaning of the last two conditions is that we are free to change (remaining inside A 0τ ) all the components of p except a n s. (k) for every q F τ and α A 0τ κ +3 there is p F τ p = p n n < ω, p n = a n, A n, f n (n l(p)) such that p q and α dom a n starting with some n 0 < ω. 24

(l) for every q F τ and B A 11, κ+ B B if τ = 1 or B A 10 A 10 in and κ B B if τ = 0, there is p F τ p = p n n < ω, p n = a n, A n, f n (n l(p)) such that p q B dom a n starting with some n 0 < ω and p is obtained from q by adding only B and the ordinals needed to be added after adding B. (m) if p F 0, B, C dom a n \κ +3, (n l(p)) and C is an initial segment of B then a n (C) is an initial segment of a n (B). The next condition provides a degree of closedness needed for the proof of the Prikry condition of the main forcing. (n) there is F τ F τ dense in F τ under such that every -increasing sequence of elements of F τ having upperbound in P has it also in F τ. Our last conditions will be essential for proving κ ++ -c.c. of the main forcing. (o) let p, q F τ be so that (i) l(p) = l(q) (ii) max 1 (p n ) = max 1 (p m ), max 1 (q n ) = max 1 (q m ) and max 1 (q n ) dom a n, where n, m l(p), p n = a n, A n, f n, q n = b n, B n, g n (iii) p n = q n for all n < l(p) (iv) f n, g n are compatible for every n l(p) (v) a n max 1 (q n ) b n for every n l(p), where a n B = { t B, s a n (B) t, s a n } then the union of p and q is in F τ, where the union is defined in obvious fashion taking p n q n for n < l(p), a n b n, f n g n etc. for n l(p). (p) let p = p n n < ω F τ and for every n, ω > n l(p) let B dom a n \κ +3 where p n = a n, A n, f n then p B F τ, where p B = p n B n < ω and for every n < l(p) p n B is the usual restriction of the function p n to B; if n l(p) then p n B = a n B, B n, f n B, with a n B defined in (o)(v), f n B the usual restriction and B n is the projection of A n by π max(pn ),B. (q) let p = p n n < ω F τ, p n = a n, A n, f n and A 0τ dom a n (ω > n l(p)). Let σ n ω > n l(p) be so that (i) σ n a n,kn for every n l(p) 25

(ii) k n n l(p) is increasing (iii) k 0 5 (iv) κ n σ n σ n for every n l(p) (v) rnga n σ n for every n l(p). Then the condition obtained from p by adding A 00, σ n to each p n with n l(p) belongs to F τ. Definition 3.11 Let A 0τ, A 1τ, F τ τ 1 and B 0τ, B 1τ, G τ τ 1 be in P. We define A 0τ, A 1τ, F τ τ 1 > B 0τ, B 1τ, G τ τ 1 iff (1) A 0τ, A 1τ τ 1 > B 0τ, B 1τ τ 1 in P (2) for every τ 1 (a) F τ G τ (b) for every p F τ and B B 11 (if τ = 1) or B B 10 Bin 10 (if τ = 0), if for every n l(p) B dom a n then p B G τ, where the restriction is defined as in 3.10(p), p = p n n < ω p n = a n, A n, f n for n l(p). Definition 3.12 Set P 1 = { A 01, A 10, F 1 < A 00, A 10, F 0 A 00, A 10, F 0, A 01, A 11, F 1 P}. Let G(P 1 ) P 1 be generic. Define P <1 = { A 00, A 10, F 0 A 01, A 11, F 1 G(P 1 ) A 00, A 10, F 0, A 01, A 11, F 1 P}. The following lemma is obvious. Lemma 3.13 P P 1 P<1. Let µ be a cardinal. Consider the following game G µ I p 0 p 2 p 2α II p 1 p 2α+1 26

where α < µ and the players are picking an increasing sequence of elements of P. The first plays at even stages (including the limit ones) and the second at odd stages. The second player wins if at some stage α < µ there is no legal move for I. Otherwise I wins. If there is a winning strategy for I in the game G µ, then we say that P is µ-strategically closed. Lemma 3.14 P is κ ++ -strategically closed. Proof. Let us describe a winning strategy for Player I, i.e. those who plays at even stages. Our main concern will be with limit stages. For successor one a similar and simpler argument will work. Thus, let α < κ ++ be a limit ordinal and x β β < α be a play in which Player I uses the desired strategy. We are supposed to define his next move x α = A 00 α, A 10 α, Fα, 0 A 01 α, A 11 α, Fα. 1 Set A 00 α to be the closure of β<α A00 β { A11 β β < α } { A10 β and Skolem functions, where x β = A 00 β, A10 β, F β 0, A01 β, A11 β, F β 1. Set A01 α to be an elementary submodel of H(κ +3 ) including A 01 β β < α, A00 β and having the intersection with κ +3 an ordinal. Let A 1i α β < α } under κ-sequences β α closed under κ+ -sequences = β<α A1i β {A0i α } { β<α A0i β } for i < 2. By Lemma 3.6 (actually its proof) A 00 α, A 10 α, A 10 α, A 11 α P. Let us turn to definitions of F 0 α and F 1 α. First we put β<α F 0 β inside F 0 α and β<α F 1 β inside F 1 α. Then we jump to definitions of dense closed subsets F 0 α will be defined from F 0 α and F 1 α and F 1 α in a direct fashion satisfying 3.10. of F 0 α and F 1 α. Final sets F 0 α and F 1 α We assume by induction that for every even β < α, i < 2 there is a dense closed F i β such that for every p = p n n < ω F i β the following holds: (1) A 0i β dom a n for all n l(p) (where as usual p n = a n, A n, f n ) (2) if γ < β is even and A 0i γ Also we assume that for every p Fβ 0 n l(q) = l(p) and q A 00 A typical element of Fα i sequence with union in P, p ν dom a n for every n l(p) then p A 0i γ F i γ. F β there is q Fβ 1 such that A 00 β dom b n for all β = p, where q n = b n, B n, g n. (i < 2) is obtained as follows: let p ν ν < ρ be a -increasing Fβν i for every ν < ρ and β ν ν < ρ is an increasing sequence of even ordinals below α. Let p ρ be the union of p ν ν < ρ. Extend p ρ to p by adding to it A 0i α (i.e. we add it to dom a n for each n l(p ρ )) and if i = 1 then also A 00 α provided that dom a ρ n A 00 α. Put this p into Fα i. Let us show that such defined Fα i is really closed. First notice that p ν ν < ρ as above can always be reorganized as follows. Set p ν = ρ>ν ν pν A 0i β ν for every ν < ρ. 27

Then p ν p ν (ν ν), by (1) above A 0i β ν dom a ν n by (2) p ν A i0 β ν with the same limit but in addition p ν F i β ν. Hence also p ν F i for every n l(p ν ) = l(p ν ), and β ν. So we obtain a new sequence p ν ν < ρ = p ν for every ν ν < ρ. Now suppose that A i0 β ν we have such an additional sequence q ξ ξ < µ corresponding to the increasing sequence γ ξ ξ < µ of ordinals below α. Assume that ν<ρ pν ξ<µ qξ. Consider A 0i β. There is ξ 0 < µ and n 0 l(q ξ 0 ) = l(q 0 ) such that A 0i β 0 belongs to the domain of the first coordinate of q ξ 0 n 0. Then the same is true for every n n 0. So, it remains only finitely many places between l(q 0 ) and n 0. Thus, there is ξ 0, µ > ξ 0 ξ 0 such that A 0i β 0 appears in q ξ 0 for every n l(q 0 ). But then q ξ 0 A i0 β 0 F i β 0 and, since q ξ A i0 ξ0 = q ξ 0 by our assumption, q ξ 0 A i0 β 0 p 0. Continuing in the same fashion, we find a nondecreasing sequence ξ ν ν < ρ such that A i0 β ν is in the domain of the first coordinate of q ξ ν n for every n l(q 0 ) and q ξ ν A i0 β ν p ν (ν < ρ). Also, q ξ ν A i0 β ν Fβ i ν. We deal with infinite increasing sequences from Fα i same way. Thus we put together everything below A i0 β 0 over all A i0 β first, then below A i0 β 1 s with even β appearing in the elements of the sequences. exactly in the and so on going The point that prevents us from obtaining κ ++ -closureness instead of only strategic κ ++ - closureness is 3.10(2(l)). Thus let B A 10 α A 10 αin and q Fα. 0 We like to add B to q. If B = A 00 α or it is an initial segment of A 00 α then this is clear since there is no problem to add the largest set. It remains the case when B β<α A00 β. Thus let B A00 β with β < α. If q γ<α F 0 γ, then q F 0 γ for some γ, β γ < α and 3.10(2)(l) is satisfied by A 00 γ, A 10 γ, F 0 γ. Then in this case B is addable to q. But now suppose that q is really new. Then by the construction of Fα 0 (or actually Fα 0 ) it is a union or is below a union of some sequence q ν ν < ρ such that A 00 γ appears in it, for some γ β and q ν A 00 γ = q ν A 00 starting with some ν 0 < ρ. Then B is addable to q ν 0 A 00 γ and hence to all the rest of the above. The proof of 3.14 actually provides more. Thus the following holds: Lemma 3.15 Let D α α < κ ++ be a list of dense open subsets of P,. Then there is an increasing sequence A 0i α, A 1i α, Fα iα i < 2 α < κ ++ of elements of P and an increasing under inclusion sequence Fα i α < κ ++ i < 2 so that for every α < κ ++ (i < 2) the following hold (1) A 00 α+1, A 10 α+1, F 0 α+1, A 01 α+1a 11 α+1, F 1 α+1 D α (2) F i α F i α is dense and closed (3) if α is limit then β<α A0i β A1i α. If we restrict ourselves to P 1 then the proof of 3.14 gives more closure: 28

Lemma 3.16 P 1 is κ +3 -strategically closed. Let G P be generic. We define our main forcing P to be {F 0 A 00, A 01, A 10, A 11, F 1 A 00, A 10, F 0, A 01, A 11, F 1 G}. The orderings and on P are just the restrictions of those of P. Notice that P, is not κ 0 -closed anymore. But 3.15 provides a replacement which is sufficient for showing that P, does not add new bounded subsets to κ and P,, satisfies the Prikry condition. Lemma 3.17 Let N be an elementary submodel of H(χ) (in V ) for χ big enough having cardinality κ + and closed under κ-sequences of its elements. Then there are an increasing sequence A 00 α, A 10 α, Fα, 0 A 01 α, A 11 α, Fα 1 α κ + of elements of P and an increasing under inclusion sequence Fα 0 α κ + so that (1) { A 00 α, A 10 α, F α, A 01 α, A 11 α, F 1 α, α < κ + } is N-generic (2) F 0 α F α is dense and closed for every α κ +. Our next subject will be chain conditions. First we need to show that κ +3 is preserved in V P. By 3.16, P 1 is κ +3 -strategically closed. Thus the following analogue of 3.9 will be enough. Lemma 3.18 P <1 satisfies κ +3 -c.c. in V P 1. Proof. Suppose otherwise. Let us assume that 00 P 1 A, A 10, F 0 α α α α < κ +3 is an antichain in P <1. Using 3.16, we define by induction an increasing sequence of conditions in P 1 A 01 α, A 11 α, Fα 1 α < κ +3 and a sequence A 00 α, A 10 α, Fα 0 α < κ +3 so that for every α < κ +3 and β<α A01 β A 01 α, A 11 α, Fα 1 00 P 1 A, A 10, F 0 α α α = Ǎ00 α, Ǎ10 α, ˇF 0 α A11 α. Let A 10 α = {X αi i < κ + }, Fα 0 = {p αi i < κ + }, p αi = p αi n n < ω (i < κ + ) and for every i < κ +, n l(p αi ) p αi n = a αi n, A αi n, fn αi for all α < κ +3. As in the proof of 3.9, we now form -system also including Fα s. 0 Thus we can assume that for some δ < κ +3, for every β < α < κ +3 (a), (b), (c) of 3.9 and in addition: (d) for every i, j < κ +, n < ω the following holds: (i) l(p αi ) = l(p βi ) 29