Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Similar documents
In reality; some cases of prisoner s dilemma end in cooperation. Game Theory Dr. F. Fatemi Page 219

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

Economics 431 Infinitely repeated games

Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Eco AS , J. Sandford, spring 2019 March 9, Midterm answers

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

14.12 Game Theory Midterm II 11/15/ Compute all the subgame perfect equilibria in pure strategies for the following game:

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Warm Up Finitely Repeated Games Infinitely Repeated Games Bayesian Games. Repeated Games

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Simon Fraser University Fall Econ 302 D200 Final Exam Solution Instructor: Songzi Du Wednesday December 16, 2015, 8:30 11:30 AM

Answers to Problem Set 4

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

(a) (5 points) Suppose p = 1. Calculate all the Nash Equilibria of the game. Do/es the equilibrium/a that you have found maximize social utility?

ECON/MGEC 333 Game Theory And Strategy Problem Set 9 Solutions. Levent Koçkesen January 6, 2011

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

Simon Fraser University Spring 2014

Notes for Section: Week 4

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

HW Consider the following game:

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game.

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5

Economics 171: Final Exam

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

CHAPTER 15 Sequential rationality 1-1

The Nash equilibrium of the stage game is (D, R), giving payoffs (0, 0). Consider the trigger strategies:

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

Repeated Games. September 3, Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality. Finitely Repeated Games. Infinitely Repeated Games

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization

Economic Management Strategy: Hwrk 1. 1 Simultaneous-Move Game Theory Questions.

Game Theory. Important Instructions

Dynamic Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Dynamic Games 1 / 18

1 x i c i if x 1 +x 2 > 0 u i (x 1,x 2 ) = 0 if x 1 +x 2 = 0

1 R. 2 l r 1 1 l2 r 2

University of Hong Kong ECON6036 Stephen Chiu. Extensive Games with Perfect Information II. Outline

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

Early PD experiments

1 Solutions to Homework 4

is the best response of firm 1 to the quantity chosen by firm 2. Firm 2 s problem: Max Π 2 = q 2 (a b(q 1 + q 2 )) cq 2

EconS 424 Strategy and Game Theory. Homework #5 Answer Key

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Infinitely Repeated Games

Repeated Games. EC202 Lectures IX & X. Francesco Nava. January London School of Economics. Nava (LSE) EC202 Lectures IX & X Jan / 16

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

1 Solutions to Homework 3

An introduction on game theory for wireless networking [1]

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Graduate School of Management and Economics

Extensive form games - contd

Player 2 L R M H a,a 7,1 5,0 T 0,5 5,3 6,6

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

ECO 5341 (Section 2) Spring 2016 Midterm March 24th 2016 Total Points: 100

Chapter 8. Repeated Games. Strategies and payoffs for games played twice

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

w E(Q w) w/100 E(Q w) w/

CHAPTER 14: REPEATED PRISONER S DILEMMA

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Econ 711 Final Solutions

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Advanced Microeconomics

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam

Module 3: "Dynamic games of complete information" Lecture 23: "Bertrand Paradox in an Infinitely repeated game" The Lecture Contains:

Noncooperative Oligopoly

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

Economics 335 March 2, 1999 Notes 6: Game Theory

HE+ Economics Nash Equilibrium

Problem Set 2 Answers

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Beliefs and Sequential Rationality

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002

13.1 Infinitely Repeated Cournot Oligopoly

Outline for Dynamic Games of Complete Information

Rationalizable Strategies

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Exercise Chapter 10

Université du Maine Théorie des Jeux Yves Zenou Correction de l examen du 16 décembre 2013 (1 heure 30)

Transcription:

. Economic Applications of Game Theory Fall 00 TA: Youngjin Hwang Problem 3 Solutions. (a) There are three subgames: [A] the subgame starting from Player s decision node after Player s choice of P; [B] the subgame starting from Player 3 s decision node following Player s P3; and [C] the entire game For subgame [A], we can find three NE: two pure strategy NE - x, l y,r with the associated payoffs of 3, and,3 respectively, and one mixed strategy NE - 3 x y, l 3 r with the payoff of 3, 3.And the unique NE for subgame [B] is a b, L R with the payoffs of 3, 3. Then for the entire game [C], we should consider the three following cases: i) for the first outcome of the subgame [A], Player will choose P; ii) for the second outcome, he will choose P3; iii) with the third outcome, he will choose P3. Therefore, SPE for this game are Px a b, l, L R, P3y a b, r, L R, and P3 3 x y a b, l 3 r, L R. (b) Consider the node where the subgame [A] starts. At this node, if it is ever reached, Player would believe Player s sequential rationality and foresee he will choose x, since the choice of y by Player gives him at most (which is less than 3/, the minimum payoff he would expect to get if he has chosen P3 and given a best response to his belief about player 3 s play), Player will choose l. Therefore the second SPE is not consistent with Forward Induction. In a similar way, the third equilibrium also can be eliminated.. (a) The monopoly price is p m /, and consider the following trigger strategy. - Start with playing p m, and play p m if everyone has played p m all the previous periods. - Play 0 if anyone has played something else different from p m at least once. By the single-deviation principle, it is sufficient to check if there are incentives to deviate only once, in order to check when this is actually a subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium. First, check the incentive when no one has deviated from p m before. If a firm plays p m,as suggested by the strategy, then everyone will be playing p m all the time in the future, and each firms s profit per period is given by p m p m 8 and the present discounted sum of the profit sequence from today is 8 8 8 3 8 8

If the firm is to deviate, the best it can do today is to set its price slightly less then p m and get the the whole monopoly profit p m p m If the firm deviates, everyone will be playing 0 from the next period, yielding per period payoff of 0. Therefore, the present discounted sum of the profit sequence from today is 0 0 3 0 The firm has no incentive to deviate if and only if or 8 Second, let s check the incentive when someone has ever deviated from p m before. In this case, a firm s action today doesn t affect its future payoffs because everyone will be playing 0 in the future no matter what happens today. Therefore, it is sufficient to check if the firm can increase the present profit by deviating. If it plays p 0, as suggested the strategy, it gets a payoff of 0. If it deviates and plays p 0, it gets again because all consumers buy from the other firm which is choosing p 0.Therefore it can t benefit from deviating. To conclude, the trigger strategy constitutes a subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium if /. (b) When there are n firms, we can again use the trigger strategy constructed in part (a). As we did in part (a) we check incentives to deviate before and after any deviation. First, check the incentive to deviate when nobody has deviated from p m before. If a firm plays p m, as suggested by the strategy, then everyone will be playing p m all the time in the future, and each firm s profit per period is p m p m n n, and the present discounted sum of the profit stream from today is n n. n n If the firm is to deviate, the best it can do today is to set a price slightly less then p m,and get the whole monopoly profit p m p m If the firm does deviate, everyone will be playing 0 from the next period, yielding per period payoff of zero. Therefore, the present discounted sum of the profit streams from today is

0 0. The firm has no incentive to deviate if and only if or n n n To check the incentive when some one has never deviated from p m before, the same argument as in part (a) holds. To conclude, the trigger strategy constitutes a subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium if n n. 3. (a) To begin with, let s find the subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium of the stage game. We can do this by backward induction. The long-run firm, observing the short-run firms s quantity x t, chooses its quantity y t to maximize its profit t L y t x t y t Solving the first order condition, the optimum is determined as y t x t x t The short-run firm chooses its quantity x t to maximize its profit t S x t x t y t knowing that if it chooses x t, the long-run firm reacts with y t x t xt Therefore, the short-run firm s objective function can be written as a function of x t ; t S x t x t xt Solving the first order condition, the optimum is x t Therefore, the subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium of the stage game is x t, y t x t xt Now let s solve for the subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium of the finitely repeated game.

Since it is a finite horizon game with perfect information, we can use backward induction. At the last period, t T, the players don t care about the future, and they concern only about the payoffs of that period. Therefore they must play the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium of the stage game, regardless of what happened in the past. At time t T,players know that their actions today don t affect tomorrow s outcome, so they will concern only about the payoff of that period. Therefore, they again must play the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium of the stage game. We can repeat this argument until we reach the first period. Therefore, the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium of the finitely repeated game is regardless of history. (b) Consider the following trigger strategy. x t, y t x t xt for all t [Long-run firm] ) Start with playing the following strategy (*): - yx / if x t / - yx x t if x t / Keep playing this strategy as long as it has not deviated from it. ) Play y t x t xt if it has deviated from (*) at least once. [Short-run firms] ) Play x t if the long-run firm has never deviated from (*) before. ) Play x t if the long-run firm has deviated from (*) at least once. To see this is actually a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, let s check incentive to deviate. First, consider the long-run firm s incentive when it has never deviated from (*) before. is Case : x t / If it follows the strategy and chooses y t /, the present period profit of the long-run firm x t. Starting from the next period, the outcome will be x t / and y t / every period, and the long-run firm s per period profit is /8, and therefore the present discounted value of the profit stream is x t. 8 If it is to deviate, the best it can do today is play and get the payoff of y t xt

x t. However, starting from next period the outcome will be x t / and y t / and the long-run firm s per period profit is /6. Therefore the present discounted value of the profit stream is If 0.99, x t 6 x t 8 xt 6, and therefore it is better to follow the equilibrium strategy than to deviate. Case : x t / If it follows the strategy, then p t 0, and today s payoff is 0, and the outcome will be x t / and y t / every period, starting the next period. The long-run firm s per period profit is /8, and therefore the present discounted value of the profit sequence is 8 If it is to deviate, the best it can do today is play y t xt, and get the payoff of xt. However, starting from next period, the outcome will be x t / and y t /, and the long-run firm s per period profit is /6. Therefore the present discounted value of the profit stream is x t 6. This value is the largest when x t /, and is equal to 6 6 If 0.99, it is better to follow the equilibrium strategy path than to deviate. Second, consider the long-run firm s incentive when it has deviated from (*) before. According to the strategy profile, future outcomes don t depend on today s behavior. Therefore the long-run firm cares only about its payoff today. Actually, by following the strategy, it is taking best response to the short-run firm. Finally,consider the short-run firm s incentives. Since they never care about future payoff, it must be playing a best response to the long-run firm s strategy, which is actually true. (c) In the equilibrium we saw in part (b), the per period profits on the equilibrium path were /8 for the long-run firm and /6 for the sort-run firms. If there is a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium where x t y t / on the equilibrium path, then the per period profits on the equilibrium path are /8 for the long-run firm and /8 for the short-run firm. Construct the following trigger strategy, which is different from part (b) only in (*) where

x t /: [Long-run firm] ) Start with playing the following strategy (*): - y t x t / if x t / - y t x t / if x t / and x t / - y t x t / if x t / Keep playing this strategy as long as it has not deviated from it. ) Play y t x t x t /, if it has deviated from (*) at least once. [Short-run firms] ) Play x t / if the long-run firm has not deviated from (*) before. ) Play x t / if the long-run firm has deviated from (*) at least once. The incentive of the long-run firm when it is supposed to play (*) and x t / is satisfied because it gets current payoff of /8, which is the same as part (b), and what it can get by deviating is the same as part (b). Thus, the incentive problem of the long-run firm is the same as in part (b). The incentive of the short-run firms is also satisfied because the payoff from following the strategy is larger than in part (b), and the payoff when deviating is the same as in part (b).. We can use the single deviation principle to check each case. (a) No. Since deviation is profitable given that other player is playing D (6 5), this cannot be a SPE. (b) Yes. Since deviation does not yield higher payoff than playing D (0 ), this is a SPE. (c) Yes. Let s first check Player s incentive. If he deviates and plays D when he is supposed to play C, then his payoff is less than that of the case he sticks to the equilibrium, that is, 6 3 6 5 6 5 3 6 5 6 And it is clear that there is no incentive for him to deviate when he is supposed to play D. Next, check Player s incentive. ) If she deviates to play D when Player is supposed to play C, then her payoff is less than that of the case when she stays in the equilibrium, that is, 6 3 6 5 0 5 3 0 5 ) If she deviates to play D when Player is supposed to play D, then again her deviation is

not profitable since 3 0 5 0 3 5 5 Since deviation is not profitable for both players, this is SPE. (d) No. Suppose that a player has deviated in the previous period and sticks to the strategy, then from next period he will get 0 0 5 0 0.While if he deviates from this (C, D) mode and plays D, he can get strictly positive payoff, making deviation profitable. Hence, this cannot be a SPE. (e) No. In DD mode, both players have no incentives to deviate. In CC mode, suppose that a player has deviated to play D. If both players stick to the strategies described in the question, then he will get 6 0 0 3 0 0 5 0 6 6 7 6 6 66 which is less than the payoff if he stays in the equilibrium. Now consider P mode. During this punishment mode, if Player deviates to play D although he is supposed to play C, he will get payoff greater than 0 0 3 0 0 5 0 0, the payoff when he sticks to the strategy in the question. Hence, the deviation is profitable for Player in P mode (Due to the symmetric nature of the game, we can apply the same argument to P mode.). To conclude, this cannot be a SPE.