A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM

Similar documents
On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences *

HANDBOOK OF EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS RESULTS

The Binarized Scoring Rule

Inflation Expectations and Behavior: Do Survey Respondents Act on their Beliefs? October Wilbert van der Klaauw

8/31/2011. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. Suggested approximation (See Benartzi and Thaler, 1995) The value function (see Benartzi and Thaler, 1995)

Finish what s been left... CS286r Fall 08 Finish what s been left... 1

Decision Markets With Good Incentives

Decision Markets with Good Incentives

Decision Markets With Good Incentives

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

Definition of Incomplete Contracts

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Reduction of Compound Lotteries with. Objective Probabilities: Theory and Evidence

A Nearly Optimal Auction for an Uninformed Seller

Preference Reversals and Induced Risk Preferences: Evidence for Noisy Maximization

Investment Decisions and Negative Interest Rates

Contents. Expected utility

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING?

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS. A. Schepanski The University of Iowa

Expected utility inequalities: theory and applications

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Endowment effects. Becker-DeGroot-Marschak mechanism. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. Endowment effects and aversion to modest risk

Ambiguity Aversion. Mark Dean. Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University

Reference Dependence and Loss Aversion in Probabilities: Theory and Experiment of Ambiguity Attitudes

Paradoxes and Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Ulrich Schmidt

THE BECKER-DEGROOT-MARSCHAK MECHANISM AND GENERALIZED UTILITY THEORIES: THEORETICAL PREDICTIONS AND EMPIRICAL OBSERVATIONS

Eliciting Objective Probabilities via Lottery Insurance Games

A Multi-Agent Prediction Market based on Partially Observable Stochastic Game

UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA

The Edgeworth exchange formulation of bargaining models and market experiments

Ideal Bootstrapping and Exact Recombination: Applications to Auction Experiments

CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #18: Multi-Parameter Revenue-Maximization

Reduction of Compound Lotteries with. Objective Probabilities: Theory and Evidence

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application

Asset Pricing in Financial Markets

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

A MODIFIED MULTINOMIAL LOGIT MODEL OF ROUTE CHOICE FOR DRIVERS USING THE TRANSPORTATION INFORMATION SYSTEM

arxiv: v3 [cs.gt] 30 May 2018

Behavioral Economics & the Design of Agricultural Index Insurance in Developing Countries

On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries. James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt

WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

Auctions. Michal Jakob Agent Technology Center, Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering, FEE, Czech Technical University

Context Dependent Preferences

ARE LOSS AVERSION AFFECT THE INVESTMENT DECISION OF THE STOCK EXCHANGE OF THAILAND S EMPLOYEES?

Is Status Quo Bias Consistent with Downward Sloping Demand? Donald Wittman* RRH: WITTMAN: IS STATUS QUO BIAS CONSISTENT? Economics Department

Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky- Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function: A Cautionary Note

CrowdWorx Market and Algorithm Reference Information

Notes 10: Risk and Uncertainty

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

Framing Lottery Choices

Expected shortfall or median shortfall

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Evaluating Strategic Forecasters. Rahul Deb with Mallesh Pai (Rice) and Maher Said (NYU Stern) Becker Friedman Theory Conference III July 22, 2017

INDIVIDUAL AND HOUSEHOLD WILLINGNESS TO PAY FOR PUBLIC GOODS JOHN QUIGGIN

Choose between the four lotteries with unknown probabilities on the branches: uncertainty

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

Insights from Behavioral Economics on Index Insurance

Chapter 2 Uncertainty Analysis and Sampling Techniques

Moral Hazard: Dynamic Models. Preliminary Lecture Notes

PhD Qualifier Examination

Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences

Time Diversification under Loss Aversion: A Bootstrap Analysis

Journal of Computational and Applied Mathematics. The mean-absolute deviation portfolio selection problem with interval-valued returns

Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

An Introduction to the Mathematics of Finance. Basu, Goodman, Stampfli

An Empirical Note on the Relationship between Unemployment and Risk- Aversion

Decentralized supply chain formation using an incentive compatible mechanism

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Contract Nonperformance Risk and Ambiguity in Insurance Markets

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market

Experience Weighted Attraction in the First Price Auction and Becker DeGroot Marschak

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Volume 29, Issue 3. The Effect of Project Types and Technologies on Software Developers' Efforts

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Summer 2003 (420 2)

Diminishing Preference Reversals by Inducing Risk Preferences

Topics in Game Theory - Prediction Markets

Recovering Subjective Probability Distributions

Mechanism Design and Auctions

Choice under Uncertainty

Economics and Computation

PURE-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA WITH NON-EXPECTED UTILITY PLAYERS

Lecture 12: Introduction to reasoning under uncertainty. Actions and Consequences

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

Transcription:

The Journal of Prediction Markets 2016 Vol 10 No 2 pp 14-21 ABSTRACT A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM Arthur Carvalho Farmer School of Business, Miami University Oxford, OH, USA, 45056 arthur.carvalho@miamioh.edu Incentive-compatible methods for eliciting beliefs, such as proper scoring rules, often rely on strong assumptions about how humans behave when making decisions under risk and uncertainty. For example, standard proper scoring rules assume that humans are risk neutral, an assumption that is often violated in practice. Under such an assumption, proper scoring rules induce honest reporting of beliefs, in a sense that experts maximize their expected scores from a proper scoring rule by honestly reporting their beliefs. Sandroni and Shmaya [Economic Theory Bulletin, volume 1, issue 1, 2013] suggested a remarkable mechanism based on proper scoring rules that induces honest reporting of beliefs without any assumptions on experts risk attitudes. In particular, the authors claimed that the mechanism relies only on the natural assumptions of probabilistic sophistication and dominance. We suggest in this paper that the reduction of compound lotteries axiom is another assumption required for Sandroni and Shmaya s mechanism to induce honest reporting of beliefs. We further elaborate on the implications of such an extra assumption in light of recent findings regarding the reduction of compound lotteries axiom. Keywords: Proper Scoring Rules; Belief Elicitation; Reduction of Compound Lotteries Axiom 1 INTRODUCTION Consider the scenario where a decision maker is interested in a forecast (belief), which is represented by a discrete probability distribution over a set of exhaustive and mutually exclusive outcomes θ 1, θ 2,, θ n. The decision maker elicits beliefs from human experts, who have no influence on or stakes in the outcomes of interest. We denote an expert's belief by the probability vector p = (p 1, p 2,, p n ), where p k is his subjective probability regarding 14

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM the occurrence of outcome θ k. Experts are potentially strategic, meaning that they are not necessarily honest when reporting their beliefs. Therefore, we distinguish between an expert's true belief p and his reported belief q = (q 1, q 2,, q n ). Clearly, from a decision making perspective, it is desirable to obtain q = p. When this happens, we say that the expert is honestly reporting his belief. Proper scoring rules (Winkler & Murphy 1968) are traditional techniques to induce risk-neutral agents to honestly report their beliefs. A scoring rule R(q, θ x ) evaluates the accuracy of a reported belief q by providing a realvalued score upon observing an outcome θ x, for x {1,, n}. In order to become relevant, scores are often coupled with financial and/or socialpsychological rewards, which naturally implies that experts seek to maximize the obtained scores. A scoring rule is called (strictly) proper when an expert receives his maximum expected score if (and only if) his reported belief q matches his true belief p (Winkler & Murphy 1968). The expected score of q at p for a real-valued scoring rule R(q, θ x ) is: E p [R(q, )] = n x=1 p x R(q, θ x ). Arguably, the logarithmic proper scoring rule, R(q, θ x ) = log q x, and the quadratic rule, R(q, θ x ) = 2q x n 2 k=1 q k, are the most popular proper scoring rules. Proper scoring rules rely on the assumption that experts are risk neutral, which is a strong and often unrealistic assumption when experts are humans (Weber & Chapman 2005; Armantier & Treich 2013). An expert s risk attitude might influence the way the expert reports his belief under standard proper scoring rules. For example, risk-seeking experts tend to report sharp beliefs, whereas risk-averse experts tend to report beliefs close to the uniform distribution (Winkler & Murphy 1970; Armantier & Treich 2013; Holt & Laury 2002; Offerman et al. 2009). An alternative when risk neutrality does not hold true is to reward the expert using the scoring rule U 1 (R(q, θ x )), which results into a proper scoring rule for the utility function U( ) (Winkler 1969). Clearly, this approach relies on two conditions: 1) the decision maker knows that the expert behaves according to expected utility theory; and 2) the decision maker knows the shape of the expert s utility function U( ). When utility functions are unknown, standard proper scoring rules for eliciting the probability of an event using deterministic payments no longer exist (Schlag & van der Weele 2013). One approach to circumvent the above impossibility result is to elicit the components that drive an expert s risk attitude towards uncertainty before eliciting the expert s belief using a proper scoring rule. Thereafter, the decision maker is able to calibrate the expert s reported belief a posteriori by removing the influence of those components in order to obtain the expert s true belief (Carvalho 2015; Offerman et al. 2009; Kothiyal et al. 2011). Clearly, the decision maker must assume that experts behave according to a certain decision model in order for this approach to work. When the assumed 15

2016 10 2 THE JOURNAL OF PREDICTION MARKETS model is wrong, the final calibrated belief can be very different from the expert s true belief (Carvalho 2015). Another alternative to circumvent the above impossibility result is to make payments in lotteries, instead of using deterministic payments. For example, Allen (1987) presented a randomized payment method that relies on the linearization of utility through conditional lottery tickets to induce honest reporting when an expert s utility function is unknown. More recently, Karni (2009) proposed a method with two fixed prizes where the payment function is determined by comparing the expert s reported probability value to a random number drawn uniformly from [0,1]. Under Karni s method, if an expert exhibits probabilistic sophistication and dominance, then it is in the best interest of the expert to report honestly regardless of his risk attitudes. In spirit, the methods by Allen (1987) and Karni (2009) are analogous to the classic Becker DeGroot Marschak mechanism (Becker et al. 1964). Some subjects have been found to have a hard time dealing with Becker-DeGroot- Marschak mechanisms in experimental settings (Cason & Plott 2014; Plott & Zeiler 2005; Rutström 1998). Sandroni & Shmaya (2013) proposed a simpler, yet elegant stochastic payment scheme based on proper scoring rules, which we discuss next. We argue, however, that Sandroni and Shmaya s mechanism only induces honest reporting of beliefs when the reduction of compound lotteries axiom holds true, an assumption not mentioned by the authors. We discuss in Section 3 the practical implications of such an assumption. 2 SANDRONI-SHMAYA MECHANISM From an expert s perspective, reporting a belief under a proper scoring rule is equivalent to choosing a lottery over a potentially infinite number of lotteries (Carvalho 2015). Consider a scenario involving only two outcomes (n = 2). Formally, the implicitly chosen lottery associated with a reported belief q = (q 1, q 2 ) is: [R(q, θ 1 ): p 1 ; R(q, θ 2 ): p 2 ] which means that the expert believes he will receive the score R(q, θ 1 ) with probability p 1, and R(q, θ 2 ) otherwise. Now, consider the following lotteries involving the fixed values > and probabilities 0 ρ, ρ 1: A = [ : ρ; : 1 ρ] and B = [ : ρ ; : 1 ρ ] We say that probabilistic dominance holds true when an expert strictly prefers A over B if and only if ρ < ρ. Sandroni & Shmaya (2013) argued that probabilistic dominance is the only assumption required in our setting (where probabilistic sophistication already holds true) when inducing honest reporting of beliefs. Specifically, the authors proposed the following payment scheme: 16

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM If outcome θ 1 happens: the expert receives the payoff with probability S(q, θ 1 ) and with probability 1 S(q, θ 1 ); If outcome θ 2 happens: the expert receives the payoff with probability S(q, θ 2 ) and with probability 1 S(q, θ 2 ); where S(q, θ x ) [0,1] is a normalized proper scoring rule. We note that any bounded proper scoring rule can be used to create a normalized scoring rule, which in turn is still proper since a positive affine transformation of a proper scoring rule is still proper (Gneiting & Raftery 2007). We argue that, from an expert s point of view, the above payment scheme is equivalent to the following compound lottery: Figure 1 p 1 θ 1 S(q, θ 1 ) 1 S(q, θ 1 ) p 2 θ 2 S(q, θ 2 ) 1 S(q, θ 2 ) Sandroni & Shmaya (2013) suggested that the probability of receiving the highest payment is: p 1 S(q, θ 1 ) + p 2 S(q, θ 2 ) Furthermore, under the assumption of probabilistic dominance, the expert will behave so as to maximize the above probability. Note that the above value is the expected score of the proper scoring rule S( ), which in turn is maximized when q = p, i.e., when the expert reports honestly. A remarkable characteristic of Sandroni and Shmaya s mechanism is that it does not rely on any assumptions about experts risk attitudes. By fixing a couple of prizes, all bounded proper scoring rules can be transformed into randomized rules that induce honest reporting for all risk preferences. This mechanism differs from Becker DeGroot Marschak based mechanisms in that no external randomization device other than nature is required to determine an expert s payment. One implicit assumption not mentioned by 17

2016 10 2 THE JOURNAL OF PREDICTION MARKETS Sandroni & Shmaya (2013) is, however, that the expert must be indifferent between the lottery in Figure (1) and the following lottery: Figure 2 p 1 S(q, θ 1 ) + p 2 S(q, θ 2 ) p 1 (1 S(q, θ 1 )) + p 2 (1 S(q, θ 2 )) In other words, there is an implicit assumption that the reduction of compound lotteries (ROCL) axiom holds true (Harrison et al. 2015). The original mechanism by Sandroni & Shmaya (2013) focused only on binary outcomes. The authors mentioned that the mechanism can be extended to many events and many experts, by running separate mechanisms to different experts and events. Clearly, this approach is problematic when the number of outcomes n is large. This happens because the decision maker has to run the mechanism once for eliciting the probability associated with each individual outcome. We note next that the same mechanism is easily extendable to multiple outcomes, where the payment scheme becomes: Figure 3 p 1 θ 1 S(q, θ 1 ) 1 S(q, θ 1 ) p 2 p n θ 2 S(q, θ 2 ) 1 S(q, θ 2 ) S(q, θ n ) θ n 1 S(q, θ n ) If outcome θ 1 happens: the expert receives the payoff with probability S(q, θ 1 ) and with probability 1 S(q, θ 1 ); If outcome θ 2 happens: the expert receives the payoff with probability S(q, θ 2 ) and with probability 1 S(q, θ 2 ); 18

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM If outcome θ n happens: the expert receives the payoff with probability S(q, θ n ) and with probability 1 S(q, θ n ); The above payment scheme is equivalent to the compound lottery in Figure 3. Under the ROCL assumption, the above lottery reduces to: n [ : p x (1 S(q, θ x )) ; : p x S(q, θ x )], x=1 in which case the probability of receiving the highest payoff is maximized when q = p. Once again the crucial assumption missing in the analysis by Sandroni & Shmaya (2013) is that the ROCL axiom must hold true. We discuss in the following section the validity of such an assumption. 3 DISCUSSION At this point, a question that arises is: when does the ROCL axiom hold true in practice? Results from prior empirical work are mostly negative in terms of the validity of the ROCL assumption, e.g., see Appendix B in the paper by Harrison et al. (2015). However, Harrison et al. (2015) suggested that these negative results could had been driven by the underlying payment scheme. In particular, the use of the well-known random lottery incentive mechanism might induce violations of ROCL. The random lottery incentive mechanism repeatedly (for a total of k times) presents two lotteries to subjects and asks them to select the most desirable one. Eventually, the mechanism randomly selects and plays out one of the chosen lotteries. Interesting, Harrison et al. (2015) showed that there is no longer evidence of violations of ROCL when subjects face only one binary choice (k = 1). Experts also face a single-decision situation when they report their beliefs under Sandroni and Shmaya s mechanism as defined is this paper. Hence, ROCL might be satisfied according to the results by Harrison et al. (2015) and, consequently, Sandroni and Shmaya s mechanism might still induce honest reporting of beliefs. We note, however, that the setting investigated by Harrison et al. (2015) involved only binary choices, i.e., choices over two lotteries. When an expert is asked to report a belief under a proper scoring rule, each potential reported belief generates a lottery. Hence, the expert s choice is over a potentially infinite number of lotteries (reported beliefs). Furthermore, Harrison et al. (2015) derived their results in the domain of risk, which is a subcase of the uncertainty domain when all the experts beliefs are equal to each other (Wakker 2010). The extent to which the results by Harrison et al. (2015) hold true under uncertainty and for an infinite number of choices is still an open and exciting research question. An answer to such a 19 n x=1

2016 10 2 THE JOURNAL OF PREDICTION MARKETS question will determine the empirical validity of Sandroni and Shmaya s mechanism for inducing honest reporting of beliefs. 4 REFERENCES Allen, F., 1987. Discovering Personal Probabilities when Utility Functions are Unknown. Management Science, 33(4), pp.542 544. Armantier, O. & Treich, N., 2013. Eliciting Beliefs: Proper Scoring Rules, Incentives, Stakes and Hedging. European Economic Review, 62, pp.17 40. Becker, G.M., Degroot, M.H. & Marschak, J., 1964. Measuring Utility by a Single-Response Sequential Method. Behavioral Science, 9(3), pp.226 232. Carvalho, A., 2015. Tailored Proper Scoring Rules Elicit Decision Weights. Judgment and Decision Making, 10(1), pp.86 96. Cason, T. & Plott, C., 2014. Misconceptions and Game Form Recognition: Challenges to Theories of Revealed Preference and Framing. Journal of Political Economy, 122(6), pp.1235 1270. Gneiting, T. & Raftery, A.E., 2007. Strictly Proper Scoring Rules, Prediction, and Estimation. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 102(477), pp.359 378. Harrison, G.W., Martínez-Correa, J. & Swarthout, J.T., 2015. Reduction of Compound Lotteries with Objective Probabilities: Theory and Evidence. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 119, pp.32 55. Holt, C.A. & Laury, S.K., 2002. Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects. American Economic Review, 92(5), pp.1644 1655. Karni, E., 2009. A Mechanism for Eliciting Probabilities. Econometrica, 77(2), pp.603 606. Kothiyal, A., Spinu, V. & Wakker, P., 2011. Comonotonic Proper Scoring Rules to Measure Ambiguity and Subjective Beliefs. Journal of Multi- Criteria Decision Analysis, 17(3-4), pp.101 113. Offerman, T., Sonnemans, J., Van De Kuilen, G., Wakker, P.P., 2009. A Truth Serum for Non-Bayesians: Correcting Proper Scoring Rules for Risk Attitudes. Review of Economic Studies, 76(4), pp.1461 1489. Plott, C.R. & Zeiler, K., 2005. The Willingness to Pay-Willingness to Accept Gap, the Endowment Effect, Subject Misconceptions, and Experimental Procedures for Eliciting Valuations. American Economic Review, 95(3), pp.530 545. Rutström, E.E., 1998. Home-Grown Values and Incentive Compatible Auction Design. International Journal of Game Theory, 27(3), pp.427 441. Sandroni, A. & Shmaya, E., 2013. Eliciting Beliefs by Paying in Chance. Economic Theory Bulletin, 1(1), pp.33 37. Schlag, K.H. & van der Weele, J.J., 2013. Eliciting Probabilities, Means, Medians, Variances and Covariances without Assuming Risk Neutrality. 20

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM Theoretical Economics Letters, 3(1), pp.38 42. Wakker, P.P., 2010. Prospect theory: For Risk and Ambiguity, Cambridge University Press. Weber, B.J. & Chapman, G.B., 2005. Playing for Peanuts: Why is Risk Seeking More Common for Low-Stakes Gambles? Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 97(1), pp.31 46. Winkler, R.L., 1969. Scoring Rules and the Evaluation of Probability Assessors. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 64(327), pp.1073 1078. Winkler, R.L. & Murphy, A.H., 1968. Good Probability Assessors. Journal of Applied Meteorology, 7(5), pp.751 758. Winkler, R.L. & Murphy, A.H., 1970. Nonlinear Utility and the Probability Score. Journal of Applied Meteorology, 9, pp.143 148. 21