October 9. The problem of ties (i.e., = ) will not matter here because it will occur with probability

Similar documents
March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions.

Other Regarding Preferences

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

Economics 502 April 3, 2008

THE PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIVERSITY. Department of Economics. January Written Portion of the Comprehensive Examination for

January 26,

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Repeated, Stochastic and Bayesian Games

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Warm Up Finitely Repeated Games Infinitely Repeated Games Bayesian Games. Repeated Games

Simon Fraser University Spring 2014

AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July time : 1 hour. Do all 4 questions. All count equally.

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance

Recap First-Price Revenue Equivalence Optimal Auctions. Auction Theory II. Lecture 19. Auction Theory II Lecture 19, Slide 1

Auctions: Types and Equilibriums

Notes on Auctions. Theorem 1 In a second price sealed bid auction bidding your valuation is always a weakly dominant strategy.

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Optimal Auctions. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

Games with incomplete information about players. be symmetric or asymmetric.

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

w E(Q w) w/100 E(Q w) w/

Microeconomic Theory II Spring 2016 Final Exam Solutions

Answers to Problem Set 4

Economics 171: Final Exam

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

ECO 463. SequentialGames

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Notes for Section: Week 7

Day 3. Myerson: What s Optimal

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

Economics 51: Game Theory

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Subject : Computer Science. Paper: Machine Learning. Module: Decision Theory and Bayesian Decision Theory. Module No: CS/ML/10.

Chapter 7 Review questions

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

While the story has been different in each case, fundamentally, we ve maintained:

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

EconS Games with Incomplete Information II and Auction Theory

Beliefs and Sequential Rationality

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

Exercise Chapter 10

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

Outline for today. Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 13: General-Sum Games. General-sum games. General-sum games. Dominated pure strategies

In reality; some cases of prisoner s dilemma end in cooperation. Game Theory Dr. F. Fatemi Page 219

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

Markets with Intermediaries

Markets with Intermediaries

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Advanced Microeconomics

Decision Analysis CHAPTER LEARNING OBJECTIVES CHAPTER OUTLINE. After completing this chapter, students will be able to:

Game Theory: Global Games. Christoph Schottmüller

October An Equilibrium of the First Price Sealed Bid Auction for an Arbitrary Distribution.

Econ 618 Simultaneous Move Bayesian Games

Price Theory Lecture 9: Choice Under Uncertainty

ECO303: Intermediate Microeconomic Theory Benjamin Balak, Spring 2008

Decision Theory. Mário S. Alvim Information Theory DCC-UFMG (2018/02)

9.2 Adverse Selection under Certainty: Lemons I and II. The principal contracts to buy from the agent a car whose quality

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Infinitely Repeated Games

In Class Exercises. Problem 1

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Using the Maximin Principle

Strategy -1- Strategy

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 6. Separation of Ownership and Control

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

ECON106P: Pricing and Strategy

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

Auctions. Michal Jakob Agent Technology Center, Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering, FEE, Czech Technical University

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW-PART 2. Contracts. I.1 Investment in Performance

Game theory for. Leonardo Badia.

A brief introduction to economics

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

Simon Fraser University Fall Econ 302 D200 Final Exam Solution Instructor: Songzi Du Wednesday December 16, 2015, 8:30 11:30 AM

PROBLEM SET 7 ANSWERS: Answers to Exercises in Jean Tirole s Theory of Industrial Organization

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 395

HW Consider the following game:

A brief introduction to economics. Outline. Reading reminder. Risk attitude example (take 3): antivirus software. Notes. Notes. Notes. Notes.

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

Transcription:

October 9 Example 30 (1.1, p.331: A bargaining breakdown) There are two people, J and K. J has an asset that he would like to sell to K. J s reservation value is 2 (i.e., he profits only if he sells it for more than 2). Let denote K s reservation value for the asset. J regards as drawn from the uniform distribution on [0 5]. This is the Bayesian Hypothesis, i.e., when a person does not know something, he has probabilistic beliefs about it; the probability distribution models J s uncertainty about the value of. Suppose J makes a "take it or leave it" offer to K: J proposes a price, which K can accept or reject. We can depict this as an extensive form game: I ve assumed here that both players are risk neutral and so their utilities are simply "money plus or minus reservation value," depending on whether the person acquires the item or sells it. I have also assumed that utility is normalized to equal 0 in the case of no trade. We construct an equilibrium. As argued before, subgame perfection implies that K will accept if 0 The problem of ties (i.e., = ) will not matter here because it will occur with probability 0. J should choose to maximize his expected profit ³ 1 5 ( 2) The (1 5) is the probabilility that [ 5], in which case trade occurs. The "1 5" reflects the density of the uniform distribution on [0 5]. Taking the derivative with respect to produces 0= 1 ³ 5 ( 2) + 1 = 2 5 5 + 7 5 = 7 2 =3 5 The second derivative test verifies that this value of maximizes J s expected utility. Besides introducing the Bayesian approach to decision-making, the point of the exam- 60

ple is the potential inefficiency of the outcome: for values of (2 3 5), it is possible for both J and K to profitably trade (i.e., gains from trade exist) but these gains are not achieved in the equilibrium that we ve derived. The inefficiency can be attributed to the incomplete information (i.e., J does not know what K will accept). Would it matter if we changed the bargaining game? Yes, but the problem demonstrated with this example has some generality. It forms a major theme in information economics, namely, incomplete information may prevent the attainment of the best possible outcome. This is quite a different theme from the efficiency of trading as taught in Intermediate Microeconomics (302). How would the problem change if J and K were risk averse? K s decision will not change, but risk aversion will change J s proposal. Suppose his utility function is ( ) = He would then choose to maximize his expected utility of profit, ³ 1 5 p 2 Taking the derivative with respect to produces 2 0= + 1 5 2 5 2 2 5 Cross-multiplying produces 2( 2) = 5 3 = 9 = 3 = 1 5 2 2 0.0.12.1 Alternative Methods of Decision-Making When You Don t Know Something. We have adopted the Bayesian Hypothesis, namely, if a person does not know something, then he has probabilistic beliefs about its possible values and makes decisions according to his expected utility. This a big assumption and it does not hold in many practical examples. There are other ways of modeling how individuals make decisions when they are not fully informed. 3 One approach is a worst-case analysis in which one maximizes one s utility assuming that the unknown turns out to be the worst case from one s perspective. This is common in engineering. You wouldn t design a bridge or a levee to withstand the weather of a typical or average day. Instead, you envision the worst possible weather that the structure might be forced to endure during its lifespan and design accordingly. Let s be a bit more precise about this. An individual must take an action. His utility is ( ) where is the state. The individual knows the set but does not observe the state itself. We think about as the range of possibilities. In the bargaining example above, the state is K s reservation value and =[0 5]. In the engineering example, would 3 See Chapter 13 of Luce and Raiffa s Games and Decisions for further discussion. 61

be the set of all possible weather that the structure might be faced with during its lifespan. The Bayesian approach assumes that the individual has a probability distribution on and then chooses to maximize his expected utility. The worst-case approach is max min ( ) i.e., different s are compared under the hypothesis that the worst possible state occurs for each. There is not a single "worst-case" state; a different state may be most challenging for each different. (The weather that most challenges a wooden bridge may not be the same as the weather that most challenges a stone bridge.) Another approach is minimizing maximum regret (also known as minimizing maximum risk). The regret associated with a particular action 0 in a state is max ( ) ( 0 ) In words, it s the "missed opportunity" from taking the action 0 in comparison to the action that would have been best in that state. The maximum regret associated with a particular action 0 is max max ( ) ( 0 ) i.e., it s the most that the individual might rue or regret from taking the action 0. Minimizing maximum regret selects the action 0 to minimize maximum regret, i.e., one evaluates each action s maximum regret and then chooses the action that has the smallest maximum regret. In a sense, it is a "cover your bases" way of making decisions: you choose your action to minimize your maximum possible loss after the fact. We ll mostly deal with the Bayesian approach in this course. Sometimes, however, it is implausible and it is good to know that alternative approaches exist. Example 31 Assume in the above example that K follows his dominant strategy of accepting any that is less than or equal to his value. What price does J propose if he takes a maxmin approach? What price does J propose if he minimizes his maximum regret? Maxmin: When J (the seller) proposes, one of two things happens: 1. K accepts and J gets 2; 62

2. K rejects and J gets 0. The smaller (or the "min") of these two is 2 0 if 2and 0 if 2. We therefore have max min ( ) =0 and every 2 is a maxmin strategy (i.e., each 2 guarantees J a payoff of at least 0, which is the most that J can guarantee himself in this game). As this example illustrates, a weakly dominated strategy (here, 2) cannot be a maxmin strategy. Maxmin is not particularly helpful in this example in guiding J in the selection of. Minimizing maximum regret is a bit complicated in this example; we ll return to it after working some easier examples. We ve digressed a bit from our study of auctions to consider alternatives to Bayesian decision-making (i.e., expected utility maximization). Auctions typically involve uncertainty for the seller concerning what the potential buyers are willing to pay for the items for sale. This uncertainty is what motivates the seller to run the auction instead of simply posting a price. A potential buyer may also not know what other potential buyers are willing to pay for the items. The issue is how should we model this incomplete knowledge of the participants. One approach is to make the Bayesian Hypothesis, which is that each participant has probabilistic beliefs about everything that he does not know (e.g., the reservation values of the potential buyers). This is the most common approach to modeling uncertainty in economic theory. It is a big assumption, however, to assume that participants have beliefs that obey the laws of probability. We digress here to consider alternatives to Bayesian decision-making that do not require the assumption of beliefs. These alternative decision criteria are also useful in themselves. Example 32 We discussed the maxmin approach last time. Consider the following decision problem: action/state 1 2 1 0 100 2 1 1 The maxmin approach selects the action 2. This remains true if the 1 is replaced by 0 000001 and the 100 by 10000000. Some have argued that 2 is reasonable if Nature (the selector of the state) is malicious with the objective of harming the decisionmaker. Is it reasonable if Nature is indifferent? Example 33 To analyze this decision problem from the perspective of minimizing maximum regret, we first derive the regret max ( ) ( 0 ) associated with each action in each state: 63

decision problem action/state 1 2 1 0 100 2 1 1 regret action/state 1 2 1 1 0 2 0 99 The number 99 in the action 2 and state 2 entry, for instance, represents the difference between what the decision maker could have obtained in state 2 (100, by choosing 1 ) minus what he actually got in state 2 by choosing 2. The maximum regret associated with each of the two possible actions is action maximum regret 1 1, 2 99 and so the action 1 minimizes the maximum regret. What is the rationale for picking 1 over 2? If one picks 2 and the state is 2, then it appears after the fact that one made a really bad decision. It is interesting that maxmin and minimizing maximum regret select different actions in this example. We can apply maxmin and minimax regret in multiplayer games by assuming that a player regards the set of all possible profiles of actions by the other players as the set of states. This can lead to problems in the application of these ideas because the selection of actions by opponents in a game is not the same as a nonintelligence "choice" of Nature of a state; an opposing player in a game presumably makes his choices intelligently and in his own self-interest; solution concepts such as Nash equilibrium may be more sensible in such situations. We apply maxmin and minimax regret to games in which a player does not know enough about the preferences of his opponents in order to deduce how they will behave. Example 34 An individual is about to retire and has accumulated $2 million dollars in a tax deferred retirement account such as a 401k. The actions that he might take are his choices of investments for the remainder of his life; a state determines his future date of death and the sequence of investment returns for all possible investment choices between the present and that future date of death. The set of states is very big in this example! How might the individual think about his investment options? 1. If he has significant other wealth, and if he is interested in leaving a large amount of money to his heirs, then he may be interested in maximizing the expected value of his investments at the time of his passing. This is best modeled using the Bayesian approach (the use of the word "expected" is a tip-off). 2. Suppose that the individual is most concerned about these funds being sufficient to support him through the remainder of his life. A maxmin approach may be appropriate, i.e., what investment strategy will guarantee that the investments are sufficient to fund the individual s support through the remainder of his life? The purchase of an annuity might be an appropriate decision for the individual. 3. The individual measures the performance of his investments each year against the returns of major mutual funds and market indices. He thinks he is a smart guy and can 64

pick investments for himself, which is contrary to the well-known advice to invest in a portfolio of inexpensively managed mutual funds. He feels really badly if his investment choices do not come close to these statistical measures. This might be modeled as the regret of not having simply bought index funds or the mutual funds themselves. While he may hope to beat these statistical measures, he may also act to insure that he will not be far off from them in any state. This suggests the strategy of minimizing maximum regret. Example 35 Solve the following decision problem using maxmin and minimax regret. action/state 1 2 3 1 10 5 1 2 0 10 4 3 5 2 10 For maxmin, we have the worst payoffs for each action as action worst 1 1 2 0 3 2 The maxmin criterion selects action 3 because it guarantees the decision maker the largest payoff. For minimax regret, we have the following regret associated with each action and each state: action/state regret 1 regret 2 regret 3 1 0 5 9 2 10 0 6 3 5 8 0 Now maximizing over states produces action/state max. regret 1 1 9 2 10 3 8 Action 3 minimizes the maximum regret. 65