Choose between the four lotteries with unknown probabilities on the branches: uncertainty

Similar documents
CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Key concepts: Certainty Equivalent and Risk Premium

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Choice under risk and uncertainty

DECISION MAKING. Decision making under conditions of uncertainty

1. A is a decision support tool that uses a tree-like graph or model of decisions and their possible consequences, including chance event outcomes,

Managerial Economics

Probability. An intro for calculus students P= Figure 1: A normal integral

05/05/2011. Degree of Risk. Degree of Risk. BUSA 4800/4810 May 5, Uncertainty

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Lecture 06 Single Attribute Utility Theory

FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2

NOTES ON ATTITUDE TOWARD RISK TAKING AND THE EXPONENTIAL UTILITY FUNCTION. Craig W. Kirkwood

Uncertainty. Contingent consumption Subjective probability. Utility functions. BEE2017 Microeconomics

Investment and Portfolio Management. Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Decision Theory Using Probabilities, MV, EMV, EVPI and Other Techniques

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Expected value is basically the average payoff from some sort of lottery, gamble or other situation with a randomly determined outcome.

Characterization of the Optimum

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

Dr. Abdallah Abdallah Fall Term 2014

Financial Mathematics III Theory summary

Biostatistics and Design of Experiments Prof. Mukesh Doble Department of Biotechnology Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno. Economics 103: Economics of uncertainty and information PRACTICE PROBLEMS

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

ECON 312: MICROECONOMICS II Lecture 11: W/C 25 th April 2016 Uncertainty and Risk Dr Ebo Turkson

Expected utility inequalities: theory and applications

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Project Risk Analysis and Management Exercises (Part II, Chapters 6, 7)

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

Problem Set 3 Solutions

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

What do Coin Tosses and Decision Making under Uncertainty, have in common?

Choosing the Wrong Portfolio of Projects Part 4: Inattention to Risk. Risk Tolerance

Decision Making. DKSharma

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

Concave utility functions

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Learning Objectives 6/2/18. Some keys from yesterday

if a < b 0 if a = b 4 b if a > b Alice has commissioned two economists to advise her on whether to accept the challenge.

Lecture 12: Introduction to reasoning under uncertainty. Actions and Consequences

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

TECHNIQUES FOR DECISION MAKING IN RISKY CONDITIONS

Symmetric Game. In animal behaviour a typical realization involves two parents balancing their individual investment in the common

The Course So Far. Decision Making in Deterministic Domains. Decision Making in Uncertain Domains. Next: Decision Making in Uncertain Domains

Measuring and Utilizing Corporate Risk Tolerance to Improve Investment Decision Making

The Two-Sample Independent Sample t Test

SCHOOL OF BUSINESS, ECONOMICS AND MANAGEMENT. BF360 Operations Research

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

MA 1125 Lecture 14 - Expected Values. Wednesday, October 4, Objectives: Introduce expected values.

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Decision Analysis CHAPTER LEARNING OBJECTIVES CHAPTER OUTLINE. After completing this chapter, students will be able to:

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

An Introduction to the Mathematics of Finance. Basu, Goodman, Stampfli

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Outline. Decision Making Theory and Homeland Security. Readings. AGEC689: Economic Issues and Policy Implications of Homeland Security

u (x) < 0. and if you believe in diminishing return of the wealth, then you would require

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

Decision Making. BUS 735: Business Decision Making and Research. Learn how to conduct regression analysis with a dummy independent variable.

FIN 6160 Investment Theory. Lecture 7-10

Module 15 July 28, 2014

Aversion to Risk and Optimal Portfolio Selection in the Mean- Variance Framework

Random Variables and Probability Distributions

ECMC49S Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Feb 27, 2007 Duration: From 3:05pm to 5:00pm Total Marks: 100

Problem set 5. Asset pricing. Markus Roth. Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz. Juli 5, 2010

Subject : Computer Science. Paper: Machine Learning. Module: Decision Theory and Bayesian Decision Theory. Module No: CS/ML/10.

Optimal Taxation : (c) Optimal Income Taxation

u w 1.5 < 0 These two results imply that the utility function is concave.

Microeconomics 3200/4200:

ECO 203: Worksheet 4. Question 1. Question 2. (6 marks)

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

King s College London

University 18 Lessons Financial Management. Unit 12: Return, Risk and Shareholder Value

Lecture 11 - Risk Aversion, Expected Utility Theory and Insurance

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 9. Demand for Insurance

AMS Portfolio Theory and Capital Markets

Project Management Chapter 13

Textbook: pp Chapter 11: Project Management

Problem Set 4 Answers

On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences *

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

Transcription:

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-1 2.11 Utility Choose between the four lotteries with unknown probabilities on the branches: uncertainty A B C D $25 $150 $600 $80 $90 $98 $ 20 $0 $100$1000 $105$ 100

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-2 Five possibile answers There are several possibilities: 1. The extreme pessimist: choose the lottery with the highest minimum payoff. known as maxmin decision making, from maximising the minimum payoff. would result in choice of lottery B. 2. The extreme optimist: choose the lottery with the highest maximum payoff. known as maxmax decision making, from maximising the maximum payoff. In this case such a rule would result in choice of lottery C.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-3 2a. Hurwicz: choose the lottery with the highest value of a weighted average of the minimum and maximum, say α lottery X s minimum payoff + (1 α) lottery X s maximum payoff. When α = 1, the Extreme Pessimist Rule; when α = 0, the Extreme Optimist Rule. If more than two possible payoffs, this rule ignores the intermediate payoffs, which shouldn t happen. 3. Choose the lottery with the highest average payoff. has the advantage that it includes all payoffs, not just the extreme ones, but it imputes equal probabilities to each payoff s occurrence. (The Laplace criterion.) Moreover, it also assumes a risk-neutral decision maker.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-4 4. For lotteries with more common structure say, a matrix R ij, where lottery i and state of the world j result in payoff R ij we can use the Savage rule of minimum regret for the wrong decision: (see Apocalypse Maybe, in the Package) choose the lottery which minimises the maximum regret, where regret is the difference between the contingent outcome s payoff in the lottery you chose and the highest contingent outcome s payoff. If we have the probabilities of the lotteries outcomes (say, from a smoothly working roulette wheel), a new rule is possible: 5. Choose the lottery with the highest expected payoff: weight each outcome with the probability of its occurrence. Includes all payoffs and the probabilities of their occurrence, but still assumes a riskneutral decision maker.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-5 Risk aversion Risk aversion: the clear evidence that many people will forgo expected profit to ensure certainty by selling a gamble at a price less than the expected profit. Risk aversion is not indicated by the slope of the utility curve: it s the curvature: if the utility curve is locally 1. linear (say, at a point of inflection), then the decision maker is locally risk neutral. 2. concave (its slope is decreasing Diminishing Marginal Utility), then the decision maker is locally risk averse; 3. convex (its slope is increasing), then the decision maker is locally risk preferring.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-6 Go with the flow? Frustrating to search for good decision rules: the five above can result in quite different choices. What if a decision maker just states her preferences as she feels them, and acts accordingly, without trying to justify her actions by referring to universally accepted principles? She may simply consider it more important to satisfy herself than to satisfy axioms.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-7 Inconsistencies She may be perfectly happy to follow her own preferences until someone points out that her preference ordering contains some obvious contradictions. There are two common sorts: inconsistencies with respect to preferences over the possible outcomes, and inconsistencies with respect to beliefs about the probabilities of the possible states of the world.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-8 Expected utilities There exist orderings which do not contain any of these two types of inconsistencies. One: Assign utilities to all payoffs and probabilities to all states of the world, and then rank lotteries by their expected utilities. The utility of a lottery is its expected utility. (by definition) According to Savage, this is the only ordering which satisfies five general conditions we d like a good decision rule to satisfy the five axioms of: Completeness and Transitivity, Continuity, Substitutability, Monotonicity, and Decomposability.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-9 Wealth Independence? Acceptance of a sixth property, the Wealth Independence Property (or Delta Property), restricts possible utility functions to be linear (i.e. risk neutral) or exponential: U (X) = a + be γ X, where γ = U (X) is the risk aversion U (X) coefficient. When γ = 0, the decision maker is risk neutral; when γ is positive, risk averse; when γ is negative, risk preferring.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-10 2.11.1 Application to Finance Suppose we consider a lottery on x described by the probability density function f x (.). Its Certainty Equivalent, x, must satisfy the equation: u (x ) = f x (x 0 ) u (x 0 ) dx 0. Substituting the exponential form for u (.), we can derive: x = 1 ln e γ x = 1 e fx (γ ), γ γ where f e x (.) represents the exponential transform of the density function f x (.), and where e γ x is the mean of the function e γ x for the lottery. The Certain Equivalent of any lottery is therefore the negative reciprocal of the risk aversion coefficient times the natural logarithm of the exponential transform of the variable evaluated at the risk aversion coefficient. (So there!)

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-11 As γ approaches zero, this expression approaches x _ : the Certain Equivalent of any lottery to a risk-indifferent individual is the expected value, x _. as γ 0, x x _. The Certain Equivalent of a normal (or Gaussian) lottery to a constant risk averter with a risk aversion coefficient 1 γ = the mean minus a half γ times the variance, or 1 x = m 2γ σ 2 Hence a risk-averse individual will prefer the lottery with the lower variance σ 2, when both have the same expected value, or mean m. (See Finance.) 1. For a normal distribution, the exponential transform of the density function, f x e (γ ), is given by e γ m + 1 2 γ 2 σ 2.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-12 2.12 Risk Aversion The Delta property: an increase of all prizes in a lottery by an amount increases the Certain Equivalent (the minimum you d sell the lottery ticket for) by. Suppose you say that your Certain Equivalent for an equiprobable lottery on $0 and $100 is $25. The lottery owner agrees to pay you an additional $100 regardless of outcome: your final payoffs will be $100 and $200 with equal probability. If you feel that your Certain Equivalent would now be $125 and reason consistently in all such situations, then you satisfy the Delta property.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-13 Accepting Wealth Independence Acceptance of the Delta property has strong consequences: The utility curve is restricted to be either linear or an exponential: u (x) must either have the form: or the form: u (x) = a + bx u (x) = a + be γ x, where a, b, and γ are constants. The buying and selling prices of a lottery will be the same for any individual. Satisfying the Delta property means that the Certain Equivalent of any proposed lottery is independent of the wealth already owned. This wealth is just a that does not affect the preference: The linear and exponential utility curves are called wealth-independent.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-14 Exponential utility functions Parameterise the exponential utility function as: 1 e γ x u (x) = 1 e γ, where u (0) = 0 and u (1) = 1. γ is the risk aversion coefficient. Sign of γ Risk profile γ = 0 risk neutral γ > 0 risk averse γ < 0 risk preferring Acceptance of the Delta property leads to the characterisation of risk preference by a single number, the risk aversion coefficient. The reciprocal of the risk aversion coefficient is known as the risk tolerance, R =1/γ.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-15 2.12.1 Assessing your Risk Tolerance. The exponential utility function is given by: U (x) = 1 e x R, where R is a parameter that determines how riskaverse the utility function is, the risk tolerance. R = γ 1, where γ is the risk-aversion coefficient. Larger values of R make the exponential utility function less curved and so closer to risk neutral, while smaller values of R model greater risk aversion. As we have seen, the exponential utility function is appropriate if the individual s preferences satisfy the Delta Property of wealth independence.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-16 Consider the gamble: 1 Win $Y with probability 2 1 Lose $Y/2 with probability 2 You Yes No N $0 1 1 2 2 $Y $Y 2 Q: What is the maximum size of Y at which you d prefer doing nothing to having this lottery: the point at which you d give the lottery ticket away? This Y is approximately equal to your risk tolerance R in the exponential utility function. (See Clemen, Making Hard Decisions, pp. 379 382.)

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-17 2.12.2 Approximation of Certainty Equivalence Consider the gamble: Win $2000 with probability 0.4 Win $1000 with probability 0.4 Win $500 with probability 0.2 Its mean = $1300, standard deviation = $600. Variance = Σ n [x i µ] 2 Prob.(X = x i ), i =1 where the mean µ = Σ n x i Prob.(X = x i ). i =1 (Standard deviation σ = square root of the variance.) Expected utility of this gamble (with R = 900) is 0.7102, and the c.e. is $1114.71. This can be approximated with the equation: 1 c.e. exp. value Variance 2 Risk Tolerance which gives $1100.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-18 Howard (1988) gives reasonable values of determining a company s risk tolerance in terms of sales, net income, or equity. R is about 6.4% of sales, 1.24 net income, or 15.7% of equity. Exponential utility functions exhibit constant risk aversion; logarithmic utility functions exhibit falling risk aversion more realistic? See: Howard R A (1988), Decision analysis: practice and promise, Management Science, 34, 679-695. (In the Package)

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-19 2.13 Eliciting Utility Functions Choose among the four gambles depicted below: A B C D.7.2.1.2.58.22.6.1.2.1.95.05 $25 $150 $600 $80 $90 $98 $ 20 $0 $100$1000 $105$ 100 The probabilities are objectively determined: the gambles are all based on things like the spin of a smooth roulette wheel, etc. Difficult to choose: difficult to think about probabilities such as.22, and about gambles with four possible prizes. But if I subscribe to the three axioms of utility theory (Transitivity, Substitution, Continuity), then I know that my choice should be based on: maximising the expectation of a utility function. So I want my choice behaviour among the four gambles to conform to my expected utility maximisation. I need to discover my own utility function: how?

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-20 I can assess my utility function: by making some judgements that are easier than those called for in a direct choice among the four gambles above. Question 1: What is my Certainty Equivalent for: 1 probability 2 of getting $1000 and 1 probability 2 of getting $ 100? This gamble is selected so that its two prizes span all the prizes in the four gambles from which I 1 must choose, and it gives probability 2 to each: 1 1 2 2 $ 100 $1000 Not a trivial judgement to make, but not so hard, because: comparing a sure thing with a gamble having only two prizes and a simple 50 50 probability structure. Answer 1: indifferent between the gamble above and $400 for sure.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-21 Question 2: What is my Certainty Equivalent for the gamble: 1 1 2 2 This gamble has: $400 $1000 top prize equal to the upper prize from the question, and bottom prize equal to my previously assessed Certain Equivalent. Answer 2: Approximately $675. Question 3: What is my Certain Equivalent for the gamble: 1 1 2 2 $ 100 $400 Answer 3: Approximately $100.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-22 Why these questions? If I can answer these questions, then I ll have five points on my utility function in the range $ 100 to $1000: arbitrarily assigning $ 100 utility = 0 and $1000 utility = 1, then the answers reveal that my utility = 0.5 at $400, my utility = 0.75 at $675, and my utility = 0.25 at $100. With these five values, I can rough in a pretty good approximation of my utility function and compute expected utilities for the four original gambles, making my choice accordingly. Even if my approximation is off, it is close to my true utility then the choice according to the approximation will be nearly as good as the best gamble using my true utility. I m making some judgement calls above, and I may not be doing so well. The data above allow me to run consistency checks, such as: What is my Certainty Equivalent for: 1 1 2 2 $100 $675

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-23 It should be $400. Why? Because this is a gamble whose prizes have utilities of 0.25 and 0.75, so that it has expected utility of 0.5, and the certain amount of money that has utility 0.5 is $400. My assessed Certainty Equivalent for this gamble is approximately $375, but now I can return to my original assessments and iterate so that I have five consistent values. Why is this procedure better than just choosing one of the original gambles? Because the numerical judgements that I m asking myself to make are for the easiest conceivable cases that aren t trivial two-prize lotteries with equally likely outcomes. I m quite ready to believe that I m better at processing that sort of gamble than I am at the four more complicated gambles with which we started. Is this benefit coming for free? No I also had to make a qualitative judgement that in this choice situation, the three axioms are good guides for choice behaviour. But because I know where the pitfalls in those axioms are, I am confident that, in this case, the axioms are a sound guide to behaviour.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-24 2.14 The Utility Curve How does eliciting the Certain Equivalents of simple lotteries allow us to construct my utility curve? Using the rule that the utility of a lottery is its expected utility, and setting u($ 100) = 0 and u($1000) = 1, so that the utility function spans the possible payoffs, we see that the utility of the first of the simple lotteries above (the lottery over $ 100 and $1000, c.e $400) is 1 1 2 0+ 2 1 = 0.5; the utility of the second (over $400 and $1000, c.e. $675) is 1 1 2 0.5 + 2 1 = 0.75; the utility of the third (over $ 100 and $400, c.e. $100) is 1 1 2 0+ 2 0.5 = 0.25; and the utility of the fourth (over $100 and $675, c.e. $375) is 1 1 2 0.25 + 2 0.75 = 0.5. The last three c.e.s ($675, $100, and $375) have been plotted against the lotteries utilities (0.75, 0.25, and 0.5, resp.) on the following graph, and I ve joined the five points with straight lines, to get an approximation for my utility function. Iterate.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-25 Utility 1.75... $675.5... $375.25... $100 0 $ 100 $250 $500 $750 $1000 The Utility Curve

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-26 We can use the utility function as plotted to calculate the utilities of the four lotteries, A, B, C, and D, of the last lecture. Simply a matter of reading off the utilities of the dollar payoffs of the lotteries, and calculating the expected utilities of the four lotteries. Dollars Utility $ 100 0.000 $ 20.100 $0.125 $25.156 $80.225 $90.238 $98.248 $100.250 $105.255 $150.295 $600.69 $1000 1.0

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-27 The expected utility of lottery A is: 0.7 0.156 + 0.2 0.295 + 0.1 0.69 = 0.237 of lottery B: 0.2 0.225 + 0.58 0.238 + 0.22 0.248 = 0.238 of lottery C: 0.6 0.100 + 0.1 0.125 + 0.2 0.250 + 0.1 1 = 0.223 and of lottery D: 0.95 0.255 + 0.05 0 = 0.248 So I would choose lottery D. The risk-neutral decision maker would choose the lottery with the highest expected dollar payoff. The expected dollar payoff of lottery A is: 0.7 $25 + 0.2 $150 + 0.1 $600 = $107.50 of lottery B: 0.2 $80 + 0.58 $90 + 0.22 $98 = $89.76 of lottery C: 0.6 $ 20 + 0.1 $0 + 0.2 $100 + 0.1 $1000 = $108.00 and of lottery D: 0.95 $105 + 0.05 $ 100 = $94.75 So the risk-neutral player would choose lottery C (or perhaps lottery A).

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-28 2.15 The Decision-Analysis Procedure We can break the procedure into: 1. a deterministic phase values, trade-offs, time-discounting with no uncertainty and 2. a probabilistic phase uncertainty, risk aversion, and lotteries. 1. The Deterministic Phase define the decision: What decision must be made? identify the alternatives by listing all possible eventualities: What courses of action are open to us? assign values to outcomes: How to determine which outcomes are good and which are bad? select state variables: If you had a crystal ball, then what numerical questions would you ask it about the outcome in order to specify your profit measure? how are the state variables related to each other: a profit function or cost function the rate of time preference, the discount rate: How does profit received in the future compare in value with profit received today?

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-29 then the following analysis: a. determine dominance in order to eliminate alternatives, if possible b. determine sensitivities in order to identify crucial state variables Influence Diagrams? See Clemen & MDM 2. The Probabilistic Phase encode uncertainty on crucial state variables; assign probabilities to the possible levels of each state variable. Analysis: develop a profit lottery. encode risk preference; develop a utility function on $, in practice, having calculated the expected returns, using the values and probabilities, subtract from each an appropriate risk premium. Analysis: select the best alternative, the one with the highest risk-adjusted return. 3. The Post-Mortem Phase Analysis: a. determine the value of eliminating uncertainty in crucial state variables: the maximum value of (im)perfect information b. develop the most economical information-gathering program: reductions in which uncertainties are most valuable?

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-30 Three reasons for using Decision Analysis in your decision making: Decision Analysis (DA) requires you to think through the structure of the decision to be made: the structure includes the possible outcomes, your alternative courses of action, and the areas of uncertainty. DA will help you make the most prudent decisions in cases where you don t know with any certainty the outcomes of the different courses of action open to you. There can be no guarantees that the best decision will invariably give the best outcome the best-laid plans o mice an men gang aft agley, as the poet Robbie Burns reminds us so we should distinguish between good decisions and good outcomes. Prudent decisions will in the long run give you better odds of good outcomes than will ad hoc decisions. By using the DA method, you ll be able to put a maximum value on additional information to reduce the uncertainty in the decision-making process, before knowing what it is. This will put limits on the amounts you should spend in the process of making specific decisions.

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-31 2.16 Implementation DA is increasingly used in business. In the U.S. it has been used by Du Pont, Ford, Pillsbury, General Mills, and General Electric. The Pillsbury Company used it to determine whether the company should switch from a box to a bag as a package for a certain grocery product. General Electric used it to increase by a factor of twenty the R & D budget for a new product. Major consulting firms have reported numerous applications for their clients. To increase the use of DA: The CEO must see decision analysis as useful and necessary. His or her support is a must. The key executives involved must understand what DA can do for them. Chose a problem and run a trial to show the usefulness of the method. Develop inside specialists so that staff expertise is available. Keep DA relevant and meaningful: don t get lost in the techniques, which should never dominate the analysis only the decision makers should. (Software helps see Treeage s DATA in the student lab.)

R.E.Marks 2000 Lecture 8-32