E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space.

Similar documents
E&G, Ch. 1: Theory of Choice; Utility Analysis - Certainty

Investment and Portfolio Management. Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Characterization of the Optimum

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

ECMC49F Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Oct 26, 2005 Duration: 1 hour 50 mins Total Marks: 100. [1] [25 marks] Decision-making under certainty

Choice under Uncertainty

u (x) < 0. and if you believe in diminishing return of the wealth, then you would require

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

Lecture Notes #3 Page 1 of 15

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

Expected value is basically the average payoff from some sort of lottery, gamble or other situation with a randomly determined outcome.

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Consumer s behavior under uncertainty

Key concepts: Certainty Equivalent and Risk Premium

AMS Portfolio Theory and Capital Markets

Chapter 1. Utility Theory. 1.1 Introduction

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

Choice Under Uncertainty (Chapter 12)

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

3.1 The Marschak-Machina triangle and risk aversion

Optimal Portfolio Selection

05/05/2011. Degree of Risk. Degree of Risk. BUSA 4800/4810 May 5, Uncertainty

CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL JANUARY 19, 2018

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

ECON Financial Economics

Mean-Variance Analysis

FIN 6160 Investment Theory. Lecture 7-10

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Tuesday October 6 Portfolio Allocation Mean-Variance Approach

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Learning Objectives 6/2/18. Some keys from yesterday

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Quantitative Portfolio Theory & Performance Analysis

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

CHAPTER 6: RISK AND RISK AVERSION

Investments Background and Introduction. I. Course Objectives to address the following Questions:

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Solutions to questions in Chapter 8 except those in PS4. The minimum-variance portfolio is found by applying the formula:

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

Economic Risk and Decision Analysis for Oil and Gas Industry CE School of Engineering and Technology Asian Institute of Technology

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS SEPTEMBER 13, 2010 BASICS. Introduction

Optimizing Portfolios

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

Economics Homework 5 Fall 2006 Dickert-Conlin / Conlin

Key investment insights

ECON 312: MICROECONOMICS II Lecture 11: W/C 25 th April 2016 Uncertainty and Risk Dr Ebo Turkson

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

5. Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

Risk and Return and Portfolio Theory

Capital Allocation Between The Risky And The Risk- Free Asset

CHAPTER 6: RISK AVERSION AND CAPITAL ALLOCATION TO RISKY ASSETS

Problem Set 3 - Solution Hints

Concave utility functions

Exercises for Chapter 8

Managerial Economics

Master in Industrial Organization and Markets. Spring 2012 Microeconomics III Assignment 1: Uncertainty

CHAPTER 6: RISK AVERSION AND CAPITAL ALLOCATION TO RISKY ASSETS

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals.

So far in the short-run analysis we have ignored the wage and price (we assume they are fixed).

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral.

Total /20 /30 /30 /20 /100. Economics 142 Midterm Exam NAME Vincent Crawford Winter 2008

Midterm 1, Financial Economics February 15, 2010

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

QR43, Introduction to Investments Class Notes, Fall 2003 IV. Portfolio Choice

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Mean-Variance Portfolio Theory

Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Macroeconomics Final Exam Practice Problems: Indifference Curves. Indifference curves are used in both the microeconomics and macroeconomics courses.

Use (solution to) stochastic two-period model to illustrate some basic results and ideas in Consumption research Asset pricing research

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Review of Production Theory: Chapter 2 1

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

The Baumol-Tobin and the Tobin Mean-Variance Models of the Demand

Managerial Economics Uncertainty

PAPER NO.1 : MICROECONOMICS ANALYSIS MODULE NO.6 : INDIFFERENCE CURVES

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

Lecture 2: Fundamentals of meanvariance

Advanced Risk Management

One-Period Valuation Theory

Principes de choix de portefeuille

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

This assignment is due on Tuesday, September 15, at the beginning of class (or sooner).

c U 2 U 1 Econ 310 Practice Questions: Chaps. 4, 7-8 Figure 4.1 Other goods

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Outline. Decision Making Theory and Homeland Security. Readings. AGEC689: Economic Issues and Policy Implications of Homeland Security

Transcription:

1 E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space. A. Overview. c 2 1. With Certainty, objects of choice (c 1, c 2 ) 2. With Uncertainty, objects of choice {E(R), σ(r)} Certainty E(R) Uncertainty preference preference structure structure c 1 σ(r) opportunities locus opportunities locus I. E&G, Chap 10 Preference Structure in {E(R), σ(r)} space. II. Then E&G, Chap 4, 5 Opportunities Locus in {E(R), σ(r)} space. III. Put I. & II. Together. A. Solution. B. Equilibrium. C. Relation between E(R) & σ(r). D. CAPM.

2 B. Indifference Curves in {E(R), σ(r)} space. 1. Assumptions: E(R) a. Happier if E(R). b. Happier if σ(r). i. Risk Averse. c. Dimishing MU. σ(r) E&G, Chap 10 discusses meaning of 1.a.-c. 2. Implications indifference curves. a. Sope upward to right. i. A to B: lower E(R); must have lower σ(r) to remain indifferent. b. Concave upward. i. Give up equal increments of E(R); Must have increasing increments of reduced σ(r). E(R) A B σ(r)

3 E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis: Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space. I. Specifying Preference Functions. A. Simple Example. 1. Evaluating 2 risky assets, A & B: Investment A Investment B. (W i ) P i (W i ) P i. 15 1/3 20 1/3 10 1/3 12 1/3 5 1/3 4 1/3 Define: Expected Value of A = E(A) = Σ P i *W i Variance of A = σ 2 (A) = Σ P i *(W i E(A)) 2 E(A) = 10; σ 2 (A) = 1/3(5) 2 + 1/3(0) 2 + 1/3(-5) 2 = 16.7; σ(a) = 4.08 E(B) = 12; σ 2 (B) = 1/3(8) 2 + 1/3(0) 2 + 1/3(-8) 2 = 42.7; σ(a) = 6.53 Observe: E(A) < E(B) -- bad for A σ(a) < σ(b) -- good for A Risky assets! We will assume investor is risk-averse; demands higher expected value for asset with higher σ.

4 2. How to choose between Assets A & B? Wish to quantify this choice; consider how much you value [E(A), σ(a)] vs [E(B), σ(b)]. Utility function does this by weighing possible outcomes. e.g., Consider following utility function [U(W i )]: Quantifies how much each value of W i is worth to investor. (1) (2) (3) (Wi) Utility Fn Value of Outcome Weight(i) Outcome U(W i ) = (3) = (1)*(2) 20 0.9 18 15 1.0 15 12 1.1 13.2 10 1.2 12 5 1.4 7 4 1.5 6 U(W i ) 20 15 10 5 W i 5 10 15 20 What should U(W i ) depend on? E(W i ) and σ(r i ). Observe: U (W) > 0; More is better; U (W) < 0; Diminishing MU(W).

5 3. Given the utility function, how can we quantify the value or utility of the expected outcomes of A vs B? i.e., how can we rank A & B? Define: Expected Utility = E(U) = Σ P i * U(W i ). E(U) of A E(U) of B = 1/3 U(15) + 1/3 U(10) + 1/3 U(5) = 1/3(15) + 1/3(12) + 1/3(7) = 34/3 = 1/3 U(20) + 1/3 U(12) + 1/3 U(4) = 1/3(18) + 1/3(13.2) + 1/3(6) = 37.2/3 Makes sense If W i = 10 occurs, U(10) = 12; To get Expected Utility, weight U(W i ) by P i and sum. Here investor would choose B, since it offers higher expected utility. Will assume that investors choose among alternatives by maximizing E(U).

6 B. Specifying the functional form of U(W i ). 1. Consider a quadratic utility function: U(W) = aw - bw 2 2. Example; Let a = 4, b =.1; Then: U(W) = 4W -.1W 2 For any possible outcome, Wi, this function quantifies its utility. 3. Given this utility function, consider 3 risky investments with different expected returns & variances; Choose the one that maximizes E(U).

7 II. Economic Properties of Utility Functions. A. Again, consider quadratic utility function: - U(W) = aw - bw 2 - U (W) = MU(W) = a - 2bW - U (W) = -2b First economic property: 1. Marginal Utility of Wealth [U (W) = MU(W)]. a. If U (W) > 0, MU(W) > 0; more is better. b. Therefore require (a-2bw) > 0; or a > 2bW. Second economic property: 2. Attitude Toward Risk [U (W)]. a. Three possibilities: i. risk averse [U (W) < 0]; ii. risk neutral [U (W) = 0]; iii. risk loving [U (W) > 0]. b. With quadratic utility fn, this depends on b: i. if b > 0; concave down; ii. if b = 0; linear; iii. if b < 0; concave up. c. Case i. - diminishing MU(W); - U (W) < 0; - require b > 0.

8 B. Digression: for intuition, define Fair Gamble. 1. Consider two choices: A. Invest B. Do Not Invest Outcome Probability Outcome Probability $2 ½ $1 1 $0 ½ 2. A is lottery ticket; Write as (W1, W2; p) = ($2, $0; ½). B is riskless asset; ($1; 1). 3. Assume: must pay $1 for A, or keep the $1 (B). 4. Observe: E(A) = E(B) = $1. If you invest in A, may win or lose, But expected outcome equals the cost, $1. 5. Define: Fair Gamble- If expected value = cost of gamble. a. Is lottery Fair Gamble? b. Is Las Vegas a Fair Gamble? c. Is a Fair Game a Fair Gamble?

9 C. Attitude Toward Risk can be defined in terms of a Fair Gamble. 1. If risk averse, reject a Fair Gamble. i.e., pick B over A. $1 with certainty is preferred to gamble; B.($1; 1) A.($2, $0; ½). a. Risk aversion implies U (W) < 0; - diminishing MU(W); - first $ is valued more than second $. Proof: Max. E(U) implies: E(U) of B > E(U) of A; U($1) > ½ U($2) + ½ U($0); Multiply both sides by 2: 2 U($1) > U($2) + U($0); U($1) U($0) > U($2) U($1); b. For risk averse investor, disutility of $1 loss > utility of $1 gain.

10 2. If risk neutral, indifferent between A & B; - between $1 with certainty or Fair Gamble; - B($1; 1) = A($2, $0; ½). a. Risk neutrality implies U (W) = 0; - constant MU(W); - first $ is valued same as second $. - same proof, replace > with =. b. For risk neutral investor, disutility of $1 loss is = utility of $1 gain. 3. If risk loving, prefer a Fair Gamble; - pick A over B; - Fair Gamble is preferred to $1 with certainty; - B.($1; 1) A.($2, $0; ½). a. Risk loving implies U (W) > 0; - increasing MU(W); - first $ is valued less than second $. - same proof, replace > with <. b. For risk loving investor, disutility of $1 loss is < utility of $1 gain.

11 D. Attitude Toward Risk can be shown in terms of Indifference Curves. 1. Graphs of utility functions display preference structure in [W, U(W)] space. However, portfolio choice problem is to Max E(U) subject to available opportunities. To do this, need to consider indifference curves in relation to opportunities locus (constraints); - find point of tangency. 2. Indifference Curves plotted in [E(R), σ(r)] space; Combin. of [E(R), σ(r)] so that E(U) is constant; Show tradeoff between E(R) and σ(r) for which investor is indifferent.

12 3. Example: Consider quadratic utility function again. U(W) = aw bw 2 a. Re-define U in terms of return, R. [analysis holds for both U(W) and U(R)]. U(R) = ar br 2 Thus E[U(R)] = a E(R) b E(R 2 ) b. Totally differentiate: du = d[u(r)] = a dr 2bR dr = (a 2bR) dr [Intuition: Recall, MU(R) = du/dr = a 2bR.] [ Multiply both sides by dr. ] c. Then Expected Utility is f[e(r), σ(r)]. Proof: First, recall definition of σ 2 - σ 2 (R) = E[R E(R)] 2 = E[R E(R)][R E(R)] = E[R 2 2 R*E(R) + E(R) 2 ] = E(R 2 ) 2 E(R)*E(R) + E(R) 2 = E(R 2 ) E(R) 2 Then, consider E(U): E(U) = a E(R) b E(R 2 ) = a E(R) b E(R 2 ) b E(R) 2 + b E(R) 2 = a E(R) b E(R) 2 b [E(R 2 ) E(R) 2 ] = a E(R) b E(R) 2 b σ 2 (R) Thus: E(U) = f[e(r), σ(r)]; If E(R) increases, E(U) increases; For risk averse investor, b > 0, so that, If σ(r) increases, E(U) decreases.

13 d. Given the quadratic utility function, can construct indifference curves in [E(R), σ(r)] space. * Totally differentiate E(U), and hold E(U) constant; gives tradeoff between E(R) & σ(r) holding E(U) constant. We have: E(U) = a E(R) b E(R) 2 b σ 2 (R) Then: d[e(u)] = a [de(r)] 2b E(R) [de(r)] 2b σ(r) [dσ(r)] Set d[e(u)] = 0 (indifferent!); solve for slope of indiff. curve: 0 = (a 2b E(R)) [de(r)] - 2b σ(r) [dσ(r)] (a 2b E(R)) [de(r)] = 2b σ(r) [dσ(r)] e. slope of = [de(r)] =. 2b σ(r). indiff. curve [dσ(r)] a 2b E(R) Recall: i. U (R) = MU(R) = a 2bR > 0 (Denominator > 0). ii. Numerator depends on b (σ(r) > 0). 1) risk averse, b > 0, slope > 0; 2) risk neutral, b = 0, slope = 0; 3) risk loving, b < 0, slope < 0. f. concavity of [d 2 E(R)] =. 2b. indiff. curve [dσ(r) 2 ] a 2b E(R) i. risk averse, b > 0, concave upward; ii. risk neutral, b = 0, straight line; iii. risk loving, b < 0, concave downward. g. σ(r) is also in numerator of slope; Thus, if σ(r) = 0, slope = 0; i.e., when curve hits vertical axis, it is horizontal.

14 E. Other aspects of Attitude Toward Risk. First property: U (W) = MU(W) > 0. Second property: U (W); attitude toward risk. Third, consider how the total $ amount invested in risky assets changes as Wealth increases. Investor may diversify; put some of wealth (X) in risky assets, and the rest (W-X) in the riskfree asset. If Wealth increases, will investor put more or less of the additional wealth into risky assets? i.e., will X increase, stay the same, or decrease? 1. Absolute Risk Aversion (ARA). Given an increase in Wealth: i. if investor increases X, decreasing ARA. ii. if investor keeps X same, constant ARA. iii. if investor decreases X, increasing ARA. If i, as W increases, investor increases X, less averse to risk in absolute terms. Most investors display decreasing ARA; as W increases, invest more $ (X) in risky assets. If investors can identify their feelings toward ARA, then the # of investment options can be reduced. Furthermore, which assumption is imposed will restrict the possible forms of utility functions that could describe their preferences. The Pratt-Arrow measure of ARA is: ARA = -U (W) / U (W). - measures nature of ARA for a given level of W. - examples later.

15 Fourth, consider how the amount invested in risky assets changes as a % of Wealth, as Wealth increases. If Wealth increases, will investor put a greater or smaller % of that additional wealth into risky assets? i.e., will (X/W) increase, stay the same, or decrease? 2. Relative Risk Aversion (RRA). Given an increase in Wealth: i. if investor increases (X/W), decreasing RRA. ii. if investor keeps (X/W) same, constant RRA. iii. if investor decreases (X/W), increasing RRA. If i, then as W increases, investor increases (X/W), less averse to risk relative to total wealth. Typical investor probably displays constant RRA; as W increases, invest same % (X/W) in risky assets. If we multiply the Pratt-Arrow measure of ARA by W, we get the measure of RRA: RRA = -W * [U (W) / U (W)]

16 POINT: Utility Theory is important. Even if the portfolio manager doesn t believe in deriving utility functions, can still learn from utility analysis. This provides background for the theory of making financial decisions under uncertainty; investment theory is based on this! Also, understanding properties of utility functions can give insight into the process of rational choice. This allows investor to eliminate some portfolios from further consideration, and reduces the chance of making a really bad decision.