Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture X: Introduction to Game Theory

Similar documents
Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Game Theory. VK Room: M1.30 Last updated: October 22, 2012.

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

CMPSCI 240: Reasoning about Uncertainty

CMPSCI 240: Reasoning about Uncertainty

Introduction to Game Theory

Economics and Computation

Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory

Economics 171: Final Exam

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming

Now we return to simultaneous-move games. We resolve the issue of non-existence of Nash equilibrium. in pure strategies through intentional mixing.

Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory

Static Games and Cournot. Competition

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

Game Theory. Analyzing Games: From Optimality to Equilibrium. Manar Mohaisen Department of EEC Engineering

The Nash equilibrium of the stage game is (D, R), giving payoffs (0, 0). Consider the trigger strategies:

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

HE+ Economics Nash Equilibrium

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

SI 563 Homework 3 Oct 5, Determine the set of rationalizable strategies for each of the following games. a) X Y X Y Z

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibrium. player 2

Solution to Tutorial 1

Solution to Tutorial /2013 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory

1 Games in Strategic Form

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

Jianfei Shen. School of Economics, The University of New South Wales, Sydney 2052, Australia

Outline for today. Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 13: General-Sum Games. General-sum games. General-sum games. Dominated pure strategies

Noncooperative Oligopoly

preferences of the individual players over these possible outcomes, typically measured by a utility or payoff function.

Strategies and Nash Equilibrium. A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory

Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

January 26,

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma

Notes on Game Theory Debasis Mishra October 29, 2018

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 2. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

Game Theory Week 7, Lecture 7

Thursday, March 3

In reality; some cases of prisoner s dilemma end in cooperation. Game Theory Dr. F. Fatemi Page 219

Preliminary Notions in Game Theory

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two

Université du Maine Théorie des Jeux Yves Zenou Correction de l examen du 16 décembre 2013 (1 heure 30)

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Review Best Response Mixed Strategy NE Summary. Syllabus

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002

Chapter 2 Discrete Static Games

LECTURE NOTES ON GAME THEORY. Player 2 Cooperate Defect Cooperate (10,10) (-1,11) Defect (11,-1) (0,0)

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Rationalizable Strategies

Game Theory - Lecture #8

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

EC 202. Lecture notes 14 Oligopoly I. George Symeonidis

Problem Set 2 - SOLUTIONS

ECO303: Intermediate Microeconomic Theory Benjamin Balak, Spring 2008

Mixed Strategies. Samuel Alizon and Daniel Cownden February 4, 2009

Repeated Games. September 3, Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality. Finitely Repeated Games. Infinitely Repeated Games

2 Game Theory: Basic Concepts

Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam

ECON322 Game Theory Half II

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

CSI 445/660 Part 9 (Introduction to Game Theory)

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Advanced Microeconomics II Game Theory Fall

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Food, stormy 300 D. Constant Expected Consumption Line

Best Reply Behavior. Michael Peters. December 27, 2013

Econ 618 Simultaneous Move Bayesian Games

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 9: Introduction to Game Theory 1

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Solution Problem Set 2

Advanced Microeconomics

Introductory Microeconomics

Warm Up Finitely Repeated Games Infinitely Repeated Games Bayesian Games. Repeated Games

ECO410H: Practice Questions 2 SOLUTIONS

Game Theory Problem Set 4 Solutions

Notes for Section: Week 4

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Games of Incomplete Information

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2

Transcription:

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture X: Introduction to Game Theory Kai Hao Yang 11/14/2017 1 Introduction and Basic Definition of Game So far we have been studying environments where the economic agents decision do not affect each others directly. In the studies of competitive markets, all the consumers and firms are price takers and the optimal consumption/production affects each other only through equilibrium prices. In the studies of a monopoly, only the monopolist is making decisions. In game theory, however, each economic agent s decision affects the others directly. That is, game theory is a study of strategic interactions in which when making decisions, each economic agents will take the others behavior (and thus preference) into account. We begin with a simple example. Suppose that there are two suspects are investigated by a prosecutor. The prosecutor does not have direct evidence to convict them for a serious crime so she is hoping that the suspects will confess themselves. If both of them do not confess, the prosecutor can only convict them with a less serious crime. On the other hand, if both of them confess, both will be convicted. However, if only one of them confesses, the confessor will become a state witness and the other suspect will be sentenced even more seriously. For simplicity, suppose that when both do not confess, both will get a payoff of 3. If both confess, both will get a payoff of 2. If only one of them confesses, the confessor will get a payoff of 4 and the other Department of Economics, University of Chicago; e-mail: khyang@uchicago.edu 1

2 will get a payoff of 1. The payoffs the result from their decisions can be summarized by the following table. Table 1: Prisoner s Dilemma Confess Not Confess Confess (3,3) (1,4) Not Confess (4,1) (2,2) Notice that although both confessing would be the best outcome for them jointly. For each of the suspects, not confessing is the best thing to do irrespective of the other s decision. As a result, the unique prediction of this game is that both will not confess. We now formally define a game. A strategic form game is defined by three elements. Players, Strategies and Payoffs. Formally, N is the set players. For each i N, S i is player i s strategy space. Also, for each i N, u i : S i R i N is player i s payoff function. Notice that the payoff function u i has domain i N S i, which means that each player s payoff depends on the others strategies directly. Together, we say that a strategic form game is defined by (N, (S i ) i N, (u i ) i N ). For example, the example above is a strategic form game. The set of players is {1, 2}. The strategy spaces are S i = {Confess, Not Confess} and payoff functions are given by Table 1. We say that a game if finite if N is a finite set and S i is finite for each i N. 2 Pure Strategy Nash Equilibrium With the formal definition of a game, we can then begin analyzing it. The first step is to define a proper solution concept of a game. There are many well-defined solution concepts in game theory. We start with the most common and widely used one Nash equilibrium. Briefly, Nash equilibrium is a strategy profile (a description of all the players strategy) such that no one will have incentive to deviate unilaterally. That is, a Nash equilibrium is a collective behavior that, given that all the other players in the game are not moving, each

3 player will no incentive to change their strategy. Formally, given a strategic form game (N, (S i ) i N, (u i ) i N ), a strategy profile s = (s i ) i N i N S i is a Nash equilibrium if for all i N, for all s i S i, u i (s) u i (s is i ), where s i = (s j ) j i denotes the strategy profile of all the players except i under s. For example, in the Prisoner s Dilemma above, (Confess, Confess) is the unique Nash equilibrium, since this is the only strategy profile in which each player will not have incentive to deviate given that the other player is choosing to Confess. As another example, consider the following game, sometimes referred as Battle of Sexes. Imagine a situation where a couple, Bob and Alice, has to decide whether they should go to a baseball game or to a movie tonight. Suppose that Bob really wants to see the movie and Alice really wants to watch the game. However, it will be the worst for both of them if they cannot go to either of them together. Suppose that they are separated in the morning because they work in different places and their phones are broken so that they cannot communicate. As such, they cannot see each other s decision when making their owns. We summarize Bob s and Alice s payoff in Table 2. To solve for a Nash equilibrium, the following procedure will be useful. From Bob s perspective, given that Alice chooses to go to the game, his best strategy is to go to the game too (so we put an asterisk on Bob s payoff here); Given that Alice chooses to go to the movie, his best strategy is to go to the movie too. On the other hand, from Alice s perspective, given that Bob goes to the movie, her best strategy is to go to the movie too; Given that Bob goes to the game, her best strategy is to go to the game too. After this procedure, we have identified what are the best strategies as a response to the other s strategies. It is then sufficient to find the scenarios that they are consistent with each other: Bob s strategy is the best given Alice s strategy and Alice s strategy is also the best given Bob s. This is exactly the strategy profiles that gives two asterisks in Table 2, which are exactly the Nash equilibria of this game. The Battle of Sexes gives an example for a game that has more than one Nash equilibria. It is also possible that a game may not have any Nash equilibrium at all. Consider the following example, called Matching Pennies, in which player 1 and 2 are flipping coins and 1 always wants to have the same side as 2 does and 2 always does not. You can verify that

4 Table 2: Battle of Sexes Game Movie Game (2*,1*) (0,0) Movie (0,0) (1*,2*) there are no Nash equilibria in this game, since for any strategy profile, either player 1 or player 2 would want to deviate to the other side. Table 3: Matching Pennies Head Tail Head (1*,0) (0,1*) Tail (0,1*) (1*,0) 3 Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibrium and Best Response Correspondence The previous example indicates an undesirable feature of the Nash equilibrium defined above. After all, for a solution concept to have predictive/explanatory power, it had better be the case that a solution always exists. To address this issue, we can extend the definition of Nash equilibrium and allow randomizations. That is, we can allow the players to randomize among strategies. Formally, let (N, (S i ) i N, (u i ) i N ) be finite a strategic form game. For each i, let M i = {σ i [0, 1] Si σ i (s i ) = 1} s i S i be the set of probability distributions on player i s strategy space and let M = i N M i. Also, for each i let v i : M R be defined as: v i (σ) = s S u i (s) i N σ i (s i )

5 denote the expected payoff of buyer i given that each buyer j N randomizes according to σ j. Together, (N, (M i ) i N, (v i ) i N ) is another strategic form game, which we call the mixed extension of the original game. With a mixed extension, Nash equilibrium can be defined analogously. Specifically, a strategy profile σ = (σ i ) i N M is a Nash equilibrium if for all i, for all σ i M i, v i (σ) v i (σ i, σ i ). We referred this extended Nash equilibrium as mixed strategy equilibrium. At a glance, it seems a lot harder to solve for a mixed strategy equilibrium comparing to what we have done before. However, the following techniques are going to be useful for finding mixed strategy equilibria. First, observe that for each player i, given the opponent s strategy σ i, player i will optimally choose some σ i argmax v i (σ i, σ i ). σ i M i If we let β i (σ i ) be defined as argmax σ i M i v i (σ i, σ i ), then β( ) is a set-valued function (or, a correspondence), that gives the set of optimal choices for player i given that the other players are playing σ i. This is called the best response correspondence for player i. Finding mixed strategy Nash equilibrium is then reduced to finding some strategy profile σ = (σ) i N such that σ (β i (σ i )) i N, which is essentially solving a system of equations. For example, consider the Matching Pennies game defined above. If we allowed players to randomize, each player s strategy is then a probability p i [0, 1] of choosing Head. Figure 1 graphs the best response correspondences for player 1 and 2 together. As we can see in Figure 1, there is an intersection between the two best response correspondences, which gives p 1 = p 2 = 1/2. Therefore, each player randomizing by probabilities 1/2 and 1/2 is the unique mixed strategy Nash equilibrium in this game.

6 p 2 β 2 (p 1 ) 1 2 β 1 (p 2 ) 0 1 2 Figure 1. p 1 In fact, with two-players and two-strategies games, the procedure can be further simplified. Observe that for each i, if σ i β i (σ i ), then for all s i such that σ i (s i ) > 0, v i (s i, σ i ) must be the same. Since if not, if v i (s i, σ i ) < v i (s i, σ i ) for some s i, s i such that σ i (s i ) > 0 and σ i (s i) > 0, i can choose a strategy that removes all the probability weights on s i to s i, which will then strictly improve payoff and therefore σ i can not be in β i (σ i ). Using this observation, we know that in a game with two strategies, in any mixed strategy equilibrium, players must be indifferent between choosing two strategies given the other player s strategy. If there are only two payers, the problem is then simplified to be solving a system of linear equations with two unknowns. For example, in the Matching Pennies game, let p i be the probability that i is choosing Head. For player 1, player 2 s strategy must be such that he is indifferent. That is: p }{{} 2 = (1 p 2 ) }{{}. Expected payoff when choosing Head Expected payoff when choosing Tail Similarly, for player 2 to be indifferent, it must be that p 1 = (1 p 1 ). Combining both of them gives p 1 = p 2 = 1/2.

7 For another example, consider the Battle of Sexes game, for 1 to be indifferent, it has to be that 2p 2 = (1 p 2 ) and for 2 to be indifferent, it has to be that p 1 = 2(1 p 1 ) Solving both equations give p 1 = 2 3, and p 2 = 1 3. As such, in addition to the two pure strategy equilibria (Game, Game) and (Movie, Movie), player 1 randomizes with probability 2/3 and 1/3 while player 2 randomizes with probability 1/3 and 2/3 is also an equilibrium.