Choice under Uncertainty

Similar documents
CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

Characterization of the Optimum

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Exercises for Chapter 8

Optimizing Portfolios

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space.

Chapter 1. Utility Theory. 1.1 Introduction

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

3.1 The Marschak-Machina triangle and risk aversion

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral.

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers. Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel)

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

Advanced Microeconomic Theory

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Investment and Portfolio Management. Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

ECON Financial Economics

Managerial Economics

Topic Four Utility optimization and stochastic dominance for investment decisions. 4.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

Problem Set 3 Solutions

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers

Financial Economics Field Exam January 2008

Pricing in markets modeled by general processes with independent increments

Choice Under Uncertainty

3 Arbitrage pricing theory in discrete time.

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Tuesday October 6 Portfolio Allocation Mean-Variance Approach

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Financial Economics. A Concise Introduction to Classical and Behavioral Finance Chapter 2. Thorsten Hens and Marc Oliver Rieger

Topic 3 Utility theory and utility maximization for portfolio choices. 3.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

SAC 304: Financial Mathematics II

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Measuring Risk Preferences. Professor: Pamela Jakiela

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion.

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

MS-E2114 Investment Science Lecture 5: Mean-variance portfolio theory

Part 4: Market Failure II - Asymmetric Information - Uncertainty

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

AMS Portfolio Theory and Capital Markets

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Attitudes Towards Risk

Microeconomics 3200/4200:

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

Behavioral Finance Driven Investment Strategies

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

Lecture 11 - Risk Aversion, Expected Utility Theory and Insurance

2.1 Mean-variance Analysis: Single-period Model

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d

Midterm 1, Financial Economics February 15, 2010

1 Preferences. Completeness: x, y X, either x y or y x. Transitivity: x, y, z X, if x y and y z, then x z.

Prevention and risk perception : theory and experiments

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Optimizing S-shaped utility and risk management

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Analytical Problem Set

University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno. Economics 103: Economics of uncertainty and information PRACTICE PROBLEMS

Managerial Economics Uncertainty

Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Mean-Variance Portfolio Theory

Consumption and Asset Pricing

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

1 Dynamic programming

Utility Indifference Pricing and Dynamic Programming Algorithm

ECON 6022B Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions Fall 2011

Transcription:

Chapter 7 Choice under Uncertainty 1. Expected Utility Theory. 2. Risk Aversion. 3. Applications: demand for insurance, portfolio choice 4. Violations of Expected Utility Theory. 7.1 Expected Utility Theory Formally a lottery involves a probability distribution over a set of prizes. Let X be the set of prizes, with typical elements x, y. We assume that the set is finite, so that there must be a best prize (call it b), and a worst prize (call it w). Lotteries will be denoted by the symbols f, g, and h. Consider lottery f that yields one of two prizes: either x 1 with probability p or x 2 with probability (1 p). We use the following notation to describe lottery f as: p x 1 (1 p) x2 We denote a lottery that give prize x for sure as δ x. An individuals has preferences over lotteries. To model choice under uncertainty, we assume that these preferences have some structure: that 1

is, they satisfy some axioms. A1. Rationality: Completeness and transitivity. A2. Independence: Consider 3 lotteries f, g, h and suppose f g. Then α f (1 α) h α g (1 α) h A3. Continuity: For all x there exists some number (call it α x ) such that δ x α x δ b (1 αx ) δ w Let us call this α x = u(x). Notice that u(b) = 1, u(w) = 0. A4. Monotonicity: p δ b (1 p) δw q δ b (1 q) δw if and only if p > q. The Representation Theorem (informal) Given the four axioms, and given the manner in which we have constructed u( ), one lottery f is a good as another g if, and only if, EU of lottery f EU of lottery g. Proof: Suppose lottery f yields one of two prizes: either x 1 with probability f 1, or x 2 with probability f 2. Likewise, suppose g yields y 1 with probability g 1, or y 2 with probability g 2. Step 1: f is defined as f 1 x 1 f2 x 2, which is the same as f 1 δ x1 f2 δ x2. (7.1) Then, by continuity, we can find some number u(x 1 ) such that δ x1 u(x 1 ) δ b (1 u(x1 )) δ w. (7.2) Likewise, δ x2 u(x 2 ) δ b (1 u(x2 )) δ w. (7.3) 2

Relations (7.1), (7.2) and (7.3) when combined repeatedly with the independence axiom, imply f [ [ f 1 u(x 1 ) + f 2 u(x 2 ) δ b f 1 (1 u(x 1 )) + f 2 (1 u(x 2 )) δ w. Repeating Step 1 for lottery g, we get, g [ [ g 1 u(y 1 ) + g 2 u(y 2 ) δ b g 1 (1 u(y 1 )) + g 2 (1 u(y 2 )) δ w. Step 2. Notice that (7.4) amounts to and (7.5) amounts to f [ EU( f ) δ b (1 EU( f )) δw g [ EU(g) δ b (1 EU(g)) δw. Step 3. The result follows from the monotonicity axiom. Acceptable transformation of utility functions. (7.4) (7.5) If u( ) is a valid utility function, so is au( ) + c, where a and c are constants and a > 0. 7.2 Risk Aversion We now specialize the above analysis to the case where the prize is money. Then, for any lottery we can define its expected value. If an individual prefers [getting the expected value of the gamble to the [gamble, the individual is said to be risk averse. If the preference holds the other way around, the individual is said to be risk-loving. If the individual is indifferent between a gamble and its expected value, she is said to be risk-neutral. Risk-averse preferences imply that the utility function u(w) is concave. 3

Measures of Risk Aversion Consider a utility function u(w), where w denotes wealth. Assume that u is twice-differentiable. How can we measure the risk aversion associated wit the utility function? (a) Concavity of the utility function. Problem: the measure is not invariant to scale changes. (b) Arrow-Pratt measure of absolute risk-aversion. a(w) = u (w) u (w). (c) Arrow-Pratt measure of relative risk-aversion. r(w) = wu (w) u (w). Some commonly-used utility functions 1. Consider the utility function u(w) = aw + b. This is linear in wealth, and captures risk-neutral preferences. Note that u = 0. 2. Consider u(w) = e ρw. Note that u (w) = ρe ρw, and u (w) = ρ 2 e ρw, so that a(w) = u (w) u (w) = e ρw ρ2 ρe ρw = ρ. This utility function displays constant absolute risk aversion, with ρ as the coefficient of absolute risk aversion. Hence the above utility functions is called the Constant Absolute Risk Aversion (CARA) utility function. 4

3. Consider, next, Here and u(w) = w1 λ 1 1 λ. u (w) = w λ, u (w) = λw λ 1, so that r(w) = wu (w) u (w) = λw λ w λ = λ. This utility function displays constant relative risk aversion, with λ as the coefficient of relative risk aversion. The above utility function is called the Constant Relative Risk Aversion Utility (CRRA) utility function 4. Consider, next the utility function Here and so that u(w) = ln w. u (w) = 1 w u (w) = 1 w 2, r(w) = wu (w) u (w) = 1. This is the special case where the constant coefficient of relative risk aversion equals 1. In fact, we can show that this is a special limiting case of the CRRA function above. Consider w 1 λ 1 lim λ 1 1 λ. 5

We can use L Hôpital s rule to find an expression for this limiting case. L Hôpital s rule: Consider the limit of a fractions f (x)/g(x) as x q. If f (q) = g(q) = 0, the fraction f (x)/g(x) is not defined at x = q. L ôpital s rule says that, if f (x) and g(x) are differentiable, the limit of the ratio is given by the ratio of the derivatives. Hence, in the expression lim x q f (x) g(x) = f (q) g (q). w 1 λ 1 lim λ 1 1 λ, we differentiate the expressions in the numerator and the denominator with respect to λ. d[w 1 λ 1 dλ = w 1 λ ln w. d[1 λ = 1. dλ Evaluating the ratio of these derivatives at λ = 1 yields ln w. 7.3 Applications of Expected Utility Theory 7.3.1 Example: Demand for Insurance Consider a risk averse individual with net worth w. With probability p > 0 she faces a risk ( a hurricane ) that would reduce her wealth to w L. Suppose she can insure herself against this risk by paying premium π for every unit of insurance she buys. How much insurance will she buy if insurance markets are competitive? Suppose she buys x units of cover: this means she must pay πx as premium but will be repaid x in the even of loss. Thus 6

if no hurricane, her wealth is w πx; if hurricane causes loss, her wealth is w L πx + x. She must choose x to maximize her expected utility EU(x) = pu(w πx L + x) + (1 p)u(w πx), with first-order condition or p(1 π)u (w πx L + x ) (1 p)πu (w πx ) = 0, u (w πx L + x ) u (w πx ) = (1 p) p π (1 π) The second order condition is guaranteed by the assumed risk aversion, which implies that u is concave. If the insurance markets are competitive, so that π, the price of insurance is driven down to its actuarially fair value p, we must have π = p. If so, the first-order condition amounts to u (w πx L + x ) = u (w πx ). Suppose u is strictly concave. If so, the slope of the function u decreases continuously. It follows that Given the strict concavity of u( ), the last relation suggests w πx L + x = w πx or that x = L. In words, if insurance was available at actuarially fair rates, a strictly riskaverse individual would like to buy complete insurance. 7

7.3.2 Example: Demand for risky financial assets Suppose an investor must allocate her initial wealth w 0 across two financial assets. The first asset is a safe asset that returns R f units for every unit invested. The second asset is risky, and its returns is given by a random variable z with distribution function F(z). The investor is strictly risk averse with utility function u(w) where w is the final wealth. Suppose she invests an amount α in the risky asset and the rest w α in the safe asset. The uncertain payoff to this portfolio is αz + (w α)r f. What are the possible values of α that the investor can choose? If her initial investment in the risky asset is constrained by her initial wealth, we have α w 0. If she can borrow, say at rate R f, to invest in the risky asset, this upper bound can be exceeded? Can α take negative values? If we allow short-selling, negative values of α are permissible. However, to keep things simple let us constrain α [0, w 0. What is the optimal choice of α in this interval? The answer depends on the distribution function F(z) and on the utility function. The individual chooses α to maximizes u(r f w + α(z R f ))df(z). The first-order condition for an interior maximum, α, is (z R f )u (R f w + α (z R f ))df(z) = 0. 7.4 Violations of Expected Utility Theory: Allais Paradox Suppose we are offered the choice between the following lottery tickets. Ticket A gives a 11% chance of winning 1m. Ticket B gives us a slightly lower probability, 10%, of winning but the prize is 5m. Which of these two opportunities would you prefer? 8

Ticket C gives us 1 million for sure (it isn t a lottery ticket, but a cheque), and lottery D gives us a an 89% of winning 1m, 1% chance of getting nothing, and 10% chance of getting 5m. Which would you prefer? E 1 (10%) E 2 (1%) E 3 (89%) A 1m 1m 0m B 5m 0m 0m C 1m 1m 1m D 5m 0m 1m Experimental evidence points to a marked preference for B over A, and of C over D in two separate pair-wise comparisons. This pattern of preference seems systematic; it can be replicated experimentally. This evidence is said to constitute a violation of the independence axiom in the following manner. Compare lotteries A and B they yield identical prizes in event E 3. If we believe in the Independence axiom, preferences between A and B should depend on only those events in which the prizes under A and B differ, namely E 1 and E 2. Likewise, preferences between C and D cannot depend on what happens under E 3, and once again, should depend only on E 1 and E 2. And, (here lies the crux), if the choice between A and B depends on E 1 and E 2, and if the choice between C and D also depends on E 1 and E 2, we should expect that somebody who prefers A to B should also prefer C to D. 9

Exercises 1. Consider a risk-averse investor with wealth w 0 must who must allocate her wealth between two assets. The safe asset returns R for every unit invested while the risky asset returns H > R with probability p and L < R with probability 1 p. Suppose her utility function is given by a differentiable utility function u(.). (a) Suppose first that ph + (1 p)l < R. What is the optimal portfolio choice? Why? (b) Suppose now that ph + (1 p)l > R and u(w) = ln w. What is the optimal portfolio choice for this investor? (c) Suppose next that ph + (1 p)l > R and u(w) = e aw What is the optimal portfolio choice for this investor? 2. Suppose an investors final-period wealth is distributed normally with mean µ and variance σ 2. Let the utility function be given by u(w) = e rw. Show that the utility if such an individual can be described by the mean and variance alone (i.e., this is a case of mean-variance utility). 10

Solutions 1. If the investor invests α in the risky asset and the rest w 0 α in the riskless asset, her final wealth is { αh + (w w = 0 α)r w high, if the payoff to risky asset is high; αl + (w 0 α)r w low, if the payoff is low. with expected utility pu(w high ) + (1 p)u(w low ). The choice problem is to choose α to maximise expected utility. The first order condition for an interior maximum is pu (w high ) w high α In this case it reduces to + (1 p)u (w low ) w low α = 0. p(h R)u [αh + (w 0 α)r + (1 p)(l R)u [αl + (w 0 α)r = 0. We consider the three cases in the question. (a) If ph + (1 p)l < R, the optimal investment is zero. The expected return to the risky asset is less than that to the safe asset. (b) Suppose ph + (1 p)l > R and u(w) = ln w. In this case, u (x) = 1/x. The first order condition writes as p(h R) αh + (w 0 α)r On simplification this reduces to α = ( R[pH + (1 p)l R (H R)(R L) = (1 p)(r L) αl + (w 0 α)r. ) w 0 φw 0, say. Note that the investor holds a constant fraction φ of her initial wealth w 0 in the risky asset. 11

(c) Suppose now that ph + (1 p)l > R and u(w) = e aw. In this case, u (x) = ae aw. The first order condition for an interior maximum is or that p(h R)ae aw high + (1 p)(l R)ae aw low = 0, e a(w high w low ) = p(h R) (1 p)(r L) = k, say. Taking logs on both sides (and noting that the restriction ph + (1 p)l > R implies k > 1 so ln k > 0, or a(w high w low ) = ln k [αh + (w 0 α)r [αl + (w 0 α)r = α(h L) = 1 ln k, a or that α = [ 1 a(h L) ln k = 1 a(h L) ln p(h R) (1 p)(r L) Note that the investment in the risky asset is independent of initial wealth w 0. 2. As w is distributed normally, its density function is f (w) = 1 [ σ 2π exp (w µ)2 2σ 2. If u(w) = exp( rw), then expected utility is u(w) f (w)dw = = 1 exp( rw) [ σ 2π exp (w µ)2 2σ 2 1 [ rw σ 2π exp (w µ)2 2σ 2 dw dw 12

Consider the expression in the square brackets rw (w µ)2 2σ 2 = 1 2σ 2 (2rσ2 w + w 2 2µw + µ 2 ) = 1 2σ 2 [w2 + 2(rσ 2 µ)w + µ 2 Adding and subtracting (rσ 2 µ) 2 to complete the square inside the square brackets rw (w µ)2 2σ 2 = 1 2σ 2 [w2 + 2(rσ 2 µ)w + (rσ 2 µ) 2 (rσ 2 µ) 2 µ 2 + µ 2 = 1 2σ 2 [(w + (rσ2 µ)) 2 (rσ 2 µ) 2 + µ 2 = 1 2σ 2 [(w + (rσ2 µ)) 2 r 2 σ 4 + 2µrσ 2 = ( 1 2 r2 σ 2 µr) 1 2σ 2 [w (µ rσ2 ) 2 Using this 1 u(w) f (w)dw = [ rw σ 2π exp (w µ)2 2σ 2 dw = exp( 1 2 r2 σ 2 µr) = exp( r(µ 1 2 rσ2 )). 1 σ 2π exp [ [w (µ rσ2 ) 2 as the value of the integral, being the integral of a normal distribution with mean (µ rσ 2 ) and variance σ 2, equals 1. Recall that a monotonically increasing transformation of a utility function is a valid utility function, and note that exp( rx) is a monotonically increasing transformation of x: to say that the utility of the risky payoff depends on exp( rx) is the same as saying it depends on x. Thus, for this case, utility depends on µ 1 2 rσ2. 13 2σ 2 dw

Higher mean increases utility, while higher variance decreases it at the rate 1 2 r. 14