Counterparty Risk in the Over-the-Counter Derivatives Market: Heterogeneous Insurers with Non-commitment

Similar documents
Counterparty Risk in the Over-the-Counter Derivatives Market: Heterogeneous Insurers with Non-commitment

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing

Counterparty risk externality: Centralized versus over-the-counter markets. Presentation at Stanford Macro, April 2011

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

LI Reunión Anual. Noviembre de Managing Strategic Buyers: Should a Seller Ban Resale? Beccuti, Juan Coleff, Joaquin

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

A Simple Model of Bank Employee Compensation

Rent Shifting and the Order of Negotiations

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Interest on Reserves, Interbank Lending, and Monetary Policy: Work in Progress

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion

Moral Hazard. Economics Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior. Instructor: Songzi Du

On the use of leverage caps in bank regulation

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011

Introduction to Game Theory

(1 p)(1 ε)+pε p(1 ε)+(1 p)ε. ε ((1 p)(1 ε) + pε). This is indeed the case since 1 ε > ε (in turn, since ε < 1/2). QED

ADVERSE SELECTION PAPER 8: CREDIT AND MICROFINANCE. 1. Introduction

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

Bargaining Order and Delays in Multilateral Bargaining with Asymmetric Sellers

Moral Hazard. Economics Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior. Shih En Lu. Simon Fraser University (with thanks to Anke Kessler)

Class Notes on Chaney (2008)

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

Clearing, Counterparty Risk and Aggregate Risk

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Where do securities come from

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment

John Geanakoplos: The Leverage Cycle

University of Konstanz Department of Economics. Maria Breitwieser.

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

Information and Evidence in Bargaining

Robust Trading Mechanisms with Budget Surplus and Partial Trade

Development Microeconomics Tutorial SS 2006 Johannes Metzler Credit Ray Ch.14

Answers to June 11, 2012 Microeconomics Prelim

A Tale of Fire-Sales and Liquidity Hoarding

Partial privatization as a source of trade gains

Scarce Collateral, the Term Premium, and Quantitative Easing

Bank Leverage and Social Welfare

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Monopoly Power with a Short Selling Constraint

Bank Asset Choice and Liability Design. June 27, 2015

Discussion of Calomiris Kahn. Economics 542 Spring 2012

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Loss-leader pricing and upgrades

ECO 463. SequentialGames

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Group-lending with sequential financing, contingent renewal and social capital. Prabal Roy Chowdhury

Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

Zhiling Guo and Dan Ma

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

A Back-up Quarterback View of Mezzanine Finance

New product launch: herd seeking or herd. preventing?

Dynamic Lending under Adverse Selection and Limited Borrower Commitment: Can it Outperform Group Lending?

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership

Practice Problems 2: Asymmetric Information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Game Theory Fall 2003

Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

A Theory of the Size and Investment Duration of Venture Capital Funds

1 Rational Expectations Equilibrium

Evaluating Strategic Forecasters. Rahul Deb with Mallesh Pai (Rice) and Maher Said (NYU Stern) Becker Friedman Theory Conference III July 22, 2017

Antino Kim Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington Bloomington, IN 47405, U.S.A.

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

A Baseline Model: Diamond and Dybvig (1983)

Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction. By: Stephen P. Holland

Lecture 7: Bayesian approach to MAB - Gittins index

Expensive than Deposits? Preliminary draft

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Dynamic Bilateral Trading in Networks

Leverage and Liquidity Dry-ups: A Framework and Policy Implications

Optimal margins and equilibrium prices

Unemployment equilibria in a Monetary Economy

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

Liquidity and the Threat of Fraudulent Assets

Optimal selling rules for repeated transactions.

Adverse Selection and Moral Hazard with Multidimensional Types

Notes for Section: Week 4

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

Transcription:

Counterparty Risk in the Over-the-Counter Derivatives Market: Heterogeneous Insurers with Non-commitment Hao Sun November 16, 2017 Abstract I study risk-taking and optimal contracting in the over-the-counter (OTC) derivatives market. Hedgers in derivative markets can see their counterparty risk increase because of subsequent trades by their counterparties. Foreseeing this, the hedgers would contract with insurers in a way that accounts for such subsequent insurer trading. In equilibrium, the hedgers optimal trades feature endogenous counterparty default risk management. The risk management involves trade size and counterparty selection. The hedgers optimal trades may or may not entail counterparty risk. Central clearing can improve the hedgers welfare through loss-sharing. JEL Classification: G21, G22, G28, D86 Keywords: Bilateral Contracting, Counterparty Risk, Heterogeneous Beliefs, Non-commitment, Central Clearing Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University, Email: hao.sun@northwestern.edu. I am extremely grateful to my advisor, Michael Fishman. I would like to thank Robert McDonald, Konstantin Milbradt, and Ehud Kalai for their insightful comments. I would also like to thank all participants of the seminars at Kellogg for their valuable inputs. All errors are mine. 1

1 Introduction Central to any OTC derivative market is the bilateral nature of the trades that involves counterparty risk, which is the risk that trading counterparties default on their obligations. Counterparty risk entered the spotlight when major players in the OTC derivative market, e.g. Lehman Brothers and AIG, either declared bankruptcy or were bailed out by the government during the recent financial crisis. The financial crisis raised the important question of whether the OTC derivative market participants can adequately manage counterparty risk themselves, without regulations such as the mandated central clearing of OTC derivatives. How do market participants manage counterparty risk? Empirically, market participants have been shown to manage counterparty risk through counterparty selection (Du et al. (2016)) and hedging (Gündüz (2016)). However, in the growing theory literature on counterparty risk, there has been little focus on counterparty risk management strategies besides margins. In particular, good insurers and bad insurers do not coexist in existing models. 1 Thus, in these models, market participants seeking to buy insurance have no choice but to contract with bad insurers. The contribution of this paper is to study a novel setting in which market participants have the necessary tools to manage counterparty risk, i.e. coexistence of good and bad insurers. Though good and bad insurers coexist in this model, the roles are determined endogenously. I model OTC derivative contract as insurance. The model features a risk-averse hedger who seeks insurance against her future risky endowment that realizes in two periods. The hedger can buy insurance from two insurers. One insurer is more optimistic about the insurance buyer s endowment than the other insurer. I shall refer to the more optimistic insurer as the optimist and the more pessimistic insurer as the pessimist. Since the insurers are heterogeneous in belief, they may wish to bet with each other after selling insurance to the hedger. They cannot commit to not betting when selling insurance to the hedger. This is the source of counterparty risk, as the insurers bet with each other may devalue the hedger s claim. Suppose at least one insurer has enough money to insure the hedger. Because the insurers bet with each other, after the bets are paid, one insurer, i.e. the good insurer, is bound to have enough money to insure the hedger. However, which insurer is good may very well depend on which insurer has sold insurance to the hedger. For example, when the hedger buys insurance from the optimist, the optimist wants to sell the same insurance to the 1 Papers studying counterparty risk, e.g. Biais et al. (2016), Stephens and Thompson (2014), typically model derivative contracts as insurance and study one-sided risk-taking of sellers or insurers. So does this paper. Bad insurers are insurers who take on risks that generate negative externality on others, respectively. Good insurers hedge their positions. In Biais et al. (2016), insurers who sell insurance are homogeneous. Thus, insurers are either all bad or all good. In Stephens and Thompson (2014), insurers are all bad but take on varying amount of risks that harm others. 2

pessimist and devalue the hedger s insurance. Here the pessimist is good. However, when the hedger buys insurance from the pessimist, the optimist wants to buy insurance from the pessimist as well to devalue the hedger s insurance. Here the optimist is good. Because of this non-commitment problem, the good insurer who does not devalue the hedger s insurance may prove to be ever elusive. The model builds on two important characteristics of the OTC derivatives market. First, agents may be heterogeneous. The heterogeneous beliefs can be a stand-in for heterogeneity in agents asset positions. For example, agents may have offsetting exposures so they can insure each other. However, if the agents were to sell insurance to a hedger, the agents may change the insurance they sell to each other depending on the insurance the hedger has bought. Second, there is non-commitment. Agents can always trade with other agents between the time they sign a contract and the maturity of that contract. For example, the typical maturity of a CDS is five years. So in these five years, a CDS seller may have the incentive to engage in activities that devalue the CDS she has sold. Imagine a firm buying a five-year CDS contract from AIG before the financial crisis. There is no way 2 for the firm to prevent AIG from selling CDS contracts to the point of near-bankruptcy. A key insight to my analysis is that when there is a bad insurer who devalues her existing contracts, there is always a good insurer who hedges her existing contracts. Suppose an insurer can hide her money with the other insurer to default on her contract with the hedger. It is obvious that the insurers cannot both hide their money since someone has to have all the money. Thus, if the optimist hides her money with the pessimist and defaults on her contract with the hedger, the pessimist would not be able to do the same. Moreover, the pessimist has the optimist s money as well. So, the pessimist can now fully insure the hedger even if the pessimist s own endowment were not enough. In this case, the optimist is the bad insurer while the pessimist is the good insurer. The intuition is the same in my model, but the identities of the good and bad insurers may depend on the insurers contracts with the hedger. Since the good and bad insurers coexist, the hedger is not limited to buying insurance from only the bad insurer. In the worst case, the hedger can always buy insurance from both insurers to ensure delivery of payment on at least one of the contracts. Under some conditions, the hedger can do better and only buy insurance from one insurer. In equilibrium, the hedger can manage counterparty risk by choosing either trade size or counterparty. When the hedger chooses to contract with both insurers, exactly one insurer defaults. Nevertheless, the hedger pays the full price for both contracts in order to ensure the contracts are incentive compatible. When the hedger chooses to contract with only one 2 assuming the firm cannot require 100% initial margin and the variation margin is subject to valuation disputes 3

insurer, she buys either cheap partial insurance from the optimist or more expensive full insurance from the pessimist. In either case, the prices of the insurance contracts do not reflect the counterparty default risk. Recent regulations mandate central clearing of OTC derivatives in an effort to reduce counterparty risk. Central clearing is an important change to the OTC derivative market. I study the effect of central clearing in this setting. I focus on the loss-sharing ability of central clearing as opposed to the ability of central clearing to enforce margin requirement. The agents in the model do not have any cash upfront so margin requirements do not apply. I find the central clearing improves the hedger s welfare beyond what the hedger can achieve by trying to manage counterparty risk without central clearing. The key difference is that central clearing can costlessly reduce the betting between the insurers while the hedger cannot. At most, the hedger can only change the direction of the bet with a cost. The hedger cannot obtain the first-best contract even with central clearing since the threat of betting makes the hedger compete in price. In this case, even if participation is voluntary, the hedger can always compensate the insurers enough to ensure their participation. The rest of the paper is organized as the following. In section 2, I review the related literature. In section 3, I define the baseline model when hedging is infeasible and present the first-best benchmark. In section 4, I analyze the equilibrium under different parameters. In section 5, I examine hedging and hedging costs. In section 6, I analyze effect of central clearing. In section 7, I discuss assumptions of the model. Finally, in section 8, I conclude. 2 Related Literature This paper is a study of sequential trading under non-commitment. It is closely related to Coase (1972), Bizer and DeMarzo (1992), Bisin and Rampini (2006) and subsequent papers. Nevertheless, the mechanism of non-commitment in our paper differs from that of the others. In Coase (1972) (Bizer and DeMarzo (1992), Bisin and Rampini (2006)) the seller (borrower) cannot commit to not selling to (borrowing from) other buyers (lenders) in subsequent periods, respectively. In this paper, however, sellers cannot commit to not trading with other sellers in the subsequent period. Thus, in this model, sellers with bad incentives coexist with sellers with good incentives. Moreover, the natural insurance providers are exactly the sellers with bad incentives. Though buyers can overcome the non-commitment problem of sellers by trading through sellers with good incentives, the first-best allocation cannot be achieved. Moreover, the allocation in equilibrium is sensitive to the wealth of both types of sellers. This paper is also closely related to the theory literature on counterparty risk, e.g. 4

Thompson (2010), Stephens and Thompson (2014), Biais et al. (2016). In the literature on counterparty risk, this paper is closest to Stephens and Thompson (2014) and Biais et al. (2016). Stephens and Thompson (2014) study the case when insurance buyers have varying degrees of aversion to default, modeled with heterogeneous non-pecuniary costs. While this paper and Stephens and Thompson (2014) study the trade-off between price and risk, the focuses are different. While Stephens and Thompson (2014) focus on insurance buyer s incentive to avoid bad insurance seller, I take the insurance buyer s incentive as given and study how the insurance buyer manages counterparty risk. Biais et al. (2016) consider hedging incentives of insurance sellers to be distorted by bad news, moral hazard, and limited liability. The insurance sellers who trade with insurance buyers in their model are homogeneous while insurers in this paper are heterogeneous. The heterogeneity of the insurers in this paper allows the hedger more flexibility in terms of counterparty choice. As a result, the hedger s optimal contract in this paper features interesting counterparty risk management strategies. In the literature on financial intermediation, this paper is closest to Babus and Hu (2017). In both Babus and Hu (2017) and this paper, financial intermediation arises endogenously due to non-commitment. Agents in Babus and Hu (2017) solve the non-commitment problem using information network and repeated games. The properties of the resulting intermediation chain depends on the structure of the information network. Agents in this model differ in that the insurance buyer only trade through intermediary under some conditions. Under other conditions, the insurance buyer manages counterparty risk through rationing quantity of insurance purchased or by hedging her insurance contract. This paper is also related to the theory literature on central clearing, e.g. Pirrong (2011), Duffie and Zhu (2011), Acharya and Bisin (2014), Stephens and Thompson (2014). Pirrong (2011) provides an extensive overview of central clearing. Duffie and Zhu (2011) discuss benefit of single central counterparty. Acharya and Bisin (2014) discuss the ability of central clearing to increase market transparency. Stephens and Thompson (2014) focus on losssharing ability of central clearing as I do. However, while Stephens and Thompson (2014) focus on ex-ante contribution by insurers to cover potential loss of the central counterparty, we focus on ex-post loss-sharing. This paper complements the search theory literature on OTC market, e.g. Duffie et al. (2007), Lagos et al. (2011). This paper s focus is the strategic risk-taking and counterparty risk. While matching in search models are typically random, the hedger in this paper chooses her counterparties to manage counterparty risk. Thus, this paper also complements Chang and Zhang (2015), which studies endogenous network formation. While Chang and Zhang (2015) focuses on network formation with exogenous risk, this paper focuses on endogenous 5

risk in a network in which all agents are connected to each other. This paper is also related to the empirical literature on counterparty risk in OTC derivative market, e.g. Arora et al. (2012), Du et al. (2016), Gündüz (2016). My results match the price implication in Arora et al. (2012), counterparty selection in Du et al. (2016), and hedging of OTC derivative contract in Gündüz (2016). 3 Model I model OTC derivatives as insurance contracts. There are three dates, t = 0, 1, 2, one hedger, and two insurers with heterogeneous beliefs. The hedger wishes to purchase insurance from insurers. At t = 0, hedger makes take-it-or-leave-it offers to insurers and insurers can choose to accept the offers. At t = 1, insurers trade with each other. At t = 0, 1, contracts are agreed upon but money does not change hands. At t = 2, money changes hands as payments are made. 3.1 Agents and Beliefs Hedger H is risk-averse with twice-differentiable strictly concave utility function u, and is endowed with one unit of risky asset with random payoff R in t = 2. For simplicity, I normalize R {0, 1}. I refer to the state in which R = s as state s at t = 2. H has the belief that state 1 (0) happens with probability π (1 π), respectively. I assume H has all the bargaining power when trading with insurers. This assumption is not essential. As long as H has some bargaining power, the same intuition applies. The two insurers are risk-neutral. One insurer is more optimistic about R with the belief that state 1 happens with probability π > π. I shall refer to this insurer as (optimist) O. The other insurer, a.k.a. (pessimist) P, shares H s belief that state 1 happens with probability π. It is central to our model that O is more optimistic about R than P. As we shall see, this assumption gives us the non-commitment friction that is at the heart of our model. The belief of H relative to beliefs of insurers is of no consequence. I choose P having the same belief as H to ensure H is willing to purchase insurance from O. I shall discuss the implications of different assumptions about beliefs in section 7.1. Both insurers are endowed with constant endowment, or cash, at t = 2. O is endowed with w O while P is endowed w P. I make the following assumption to ensure O has enough wealth to insure H. Assumption 1 w O π 1 π. 6

When O trades with P at t = 1, I assume O has all the bargaining power. Again, this is modeling convenience. I shall discuss the implications of different assumption about bargaining power in section 7.1. Since all endowments arrive at t = 2, all agents maximize expected utility of consumption at t = 2. Moreover, all endowments and beliefs are common knowledge. At t = 1, everything, including contracts and decisions at t = 0, are common knowledge. Since many objects defined in this paper are functions of realization of R, I refer to x(0) (x(1)) as the value x takes in state 0 (1) for any object x, respectively. 3.2 Contracts and Trading At t = 0, H makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer to insurer i {O, P } with contract τ H,i (τ i (0), τ i (1)) R + [ 1, 0]. (1) Contract term τ H,i (0) (τ H,i (1)) specifies transfer from i to H in state 0 (1), respectively. Positive value represents transfer from i to H while negative value represents transfer from H to i. I restrict our attention to τ i R + [ 1, 0], since H can only credibly promise payment in state 1 and H would never consider a contract τ i R [ 1, 0]. At t=1, O makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer to P with contract τ O,P (τ O,P (0), τ O,P (1)) R R (2) The terms are defined similarly. Positive value represents transfer from P to O while negative value represents from O to P. For now, there are no restrictions on τ O,P as there is on τ H,i. In section 3.3.3, I assume P is wealthy enough so that O always wants to sell insurance to P, i.e. τ O,P R R +. Later, I will relax the assumption and study the problem without restrict the direction of O s contract with P. I assume τ O,P is senior to τ H,O and τ H,P in the sense that O and P s claims in τ O,P are paid out before H s claim is paid out from τ H,O and τ H,P. Moreover, since everything is common knowledge, O and P can only credibly promise each other their wealth plus any transfer from H. Thus, O and P have commitment with each other. The seniority assumption and insurers commitment to each other resemble the use of collateral. I discuss our model in relation to collateral in section 7.2. For easy comparison between contracts, I define the price of any contract in t = 0, 1 as q(τ i,j ) τ i,j (1) τ i,j (0). (3) 7

This price represents the amount contract buyer (sell) pays (receives) in state 1 per unit of wealth she receives (pays) in state 0, respectively. Moreover, I denote the standardized contract with price q as τ q (1, q). (4) This helps simplify notation. 3.3 Insurers Now I am ready to introduce the insurer s problems. First, I state the insurers problems. Then, I state assumptions that help simplify the problems. 3.3.1 Insurers Problems First, I state P s value function. Then, I state O s problem. Given contracts τ H,P and τ O,P, P s value function is U P (τ O,P, τ H,P ) E P [ (wp τ O,P τ H,P ) +] Whenever P is indifferent between accepting or not accepting any contract, I assume P accepts the contract. Given (1), H only buys insurance. Moreover, there is commitment between O and P. Thus, P s time 2 wealth, i.e. w P τ O,P τ H,P, can only be negative in state 0. This is useful. For example, suppose P s time 2 wealth in state 0 is positive. Then, I can remove the () + operator from P s value function. Now I define O s problem. Given contract τ H,O, O solves at t = 1 U O (τ H,O, τ H,P ) max τ O,P Û O (τ O,P τ H,O, τ H,P ) E O [ (wo + τ O,P τ H,O ) +] (5) subject to P s individual rationality constraint U P (τ O,P, τ H,P ) U P ((0, 0), τ H,P ) (IR-P) and budget constraints for both insurers τ O,P w O (τ H,O ), τ O,P w P (τ H,P ). (BC-O) (BC-P) Given common knowledge, O can credibly promise to P as much as O s wealth as well as promises from H to O, i.e. (τ H,O ). This is represented by O s budget constraint. This is where I assume O has commitment to P. Moreover, O can default on τ H,O and only the 8

promises from H to O (P ) enter into (BC-O) ( (BC-P)). Thus, the budget constraints are also where I make the seniority assumption. 3.3.2 Tie-breaking Since, O may default on τ O,P, O may be indifferent between several contracts that O can offer to P. I make the following assumption. Assumption 2 (Tie-breaking) Given τ H,O and τ H,P, suppose there are 2 contracts τ 1 and τ 2 such that both contracts satisfy (IR-P), (BC-P), (BC-O), and ÛO(τ 1 ) = ÛO(τ 2 ). O prefers τ i such that U P (α P, 1 τ i, τ H,P ) U P (α P, 1 τ j, τ H,P ) for i j {1, 2}. The above assumption states that when O is indifferent between offering two contracts, O would choose the one that gives P less expected utility. At first, it may seem this assumption contradicts Pareto Optimality. However, when O is in such an situation, O must be able to either find a contract that s preferred to both or O must be defaulting on τ H,O by offering at least one of the two contracts. In the first case, neither contract is optimal for O. Thus, O would not pick either contract in equilibrium anyways and Assumption 2 has trivial consequences. In the second case, when O increases P s expected utility, O is simultaneously decreasing H s expect utility. Thus, Assumption 2 does not violate Pareto Optimality. Moreover, Assumption 2 actually helps H by making O choose the contract that favors paying H over P whenever O is indifferent. Lemma 1 is an immediate consequence of Assumption 2. Lemma 1 Given Assumption 2, O would never choose τ O,P s.t. (IR-P) is slack. By Lemma 1, I can restrict our attention to τ O,P such that (IR-P) binds with equality. I shall refer to the equality version of (IR-P) as (IR -P). Lemma 1 means P will always accept O s offer and reduces P s value function to Û P (τ H,P ) U P (τ O,P (τ H,P ), τ H,P ) = E P [(w P τ H,P ) + ]. (6) At t = 2, P s wealth, including the trades, is still (w P τ O,P τ H,P ) +. This may be different from (w P τ H,P ) +. However, ex-ante at t = 1, P can be sure that O will offer τ O,P such that expected value of the 2 objects are the same. Thus, at t = 0, P is only concerned about [ E P (wp τ H,P ) +]. This decouples P s decision of accepting H s offer from other contracts. This simplifies H s problem. 9

3.3.3 O selling insurance to P In section 3.2, I make no restriction on τ O,P. Now, I put some structure on τ O,P for our baseline result. As defined in (1), there are two possibilities, τ O,P R + R and τ O,P R R. The first possibility corresponds to O buying insurance from P whereas the second possibility corresponds to O selling insurance to P. Given τ H,O = τ H,P = (0, 0), O would always choose to sell insurance to P since O is more optimistic about state 1 and O has all the bargaining power. When τ H,O and τ H,P are both non-zero, O may choose to buy insurance from P so that P would default on τ H,P. In that case, O would compare the expected revenue from buying insurance and selling insurance to P and choose the better option. The only benefit for O to buy insurance from P is that O can get min(τ H,P (0), w P ) for free, since H already paid the price. The cost of doing so is that O is trading against her own interest as O values state 1 more. It s helpful to first study the result when I restrict τ O,P R R. Thus, for now, I impose an assumption on w P to rule out τ O,P R + R. Later, I will relax the assumption. Assumption 3 w P > 1 h 1 (π) h 1 (π ) > h(π). where h(π) π 1 π 1/h 1 (π) is the hazard rate. Intuitively, as w P s wealth increases compared to H s 1, the cost of O buying insurance from P increases since O gives up more of her precious state 1 wealth for state 0 wealth. Given τ H,P, the benefit O receives from buying insurance from P is constant with respect to w P. Thus, as w P increases above the threshold in Assumption 3, the cost of O buying insurance from P outweighs the benefit. Thus, in this case, the incentive for O to sell insurance to P is strong enough that it is impossible for H to hedge. Immediately, we have Lemma 2 Given Assumption 3, O would only consider τ O,P R R +. This is very useful as we only need to consider O selling insurance to P. Thus, Lemma 2 states that O always have non-commitment problem. Whether the problem affects H depends on relative wealth between O and P. This would allow us to derive the baseline results which will help us solve the more general case when I relax Assumption 3. Assumption 3 also has a second implication. The second inequality in Assumption 3 follows from the definition of h( ). It implies that P always have enough wealth to insure H, as well. With Assumption 1 and Assumption 3, I am essentially studying the case when both O and P are wealthier relative to H. Together with P s value function in (6), Assumption 3 also implies P would not accept any offer from H with τ H,P (0) > w P, unless τ H,P (1) = w P h 1 (π) > 1 which H cannot afford. Thus, H can never offer a contract in which 10

H asks P to pay more that P s wealth under Assumption 3. Thus, I can further reduce P s value function to Ū P (τ H,P ) E P [w P τ H,P ]. 3.4 Hedger s Problem Since I will relax Assumption 3 later, I will state H s problem in general. Then, I discuss how Assumption 3 simplifies H s problem. At t = 0, H solves [ max U H (τ H,O, τ H,P ) = E H u(r + τ H,O + τ H,P ) ] τ H,O,τ H,P subject to individual rationality constraints U O (τ H,O, τ H,P ) U O ((0, 0), τ H,P ), E P [(w p τ H,P ) + ] E P [w p ], (IR-HO) (IR-HP) and budget constraints for insurers τ H,O = min ( τ H,O, w O + τ O,P [τ H,O, τ H,P ] ), τ H,P = min ( τ H,P, w P τ O,P [τ H,O, τ H,P ] τ H,P ), (BC-HO) (BC-HP) where τ O,P [τ H,O, τ H,P ] arg max τ E O [ (wo + τ O,P τ H,O ) +] is the solution to O s problem given contracts H offers to O and P. Note that τo,p may not be unique. In that case, I assume H can force O to pick the one that s better for H. Such selection is also Pareto Optimal. The right-hand-side of (IR-HO) doesn t have () + is because of (BC-HO). I shall refer to τ H,O and τ H,P as recovery contracts of the corresponding contracts. One may wonder whether H can choose risk-free τ H,O and τ H,P directly rather than choosing risky τ H,O and τ H,P, which may be defaulted upon. In general, H may not be able to choose τ H,O or τ H,P directly since τ O,P [τ H,O, τ H,P ] may differ from τ O,P [τ H,O, τ H,P ] and τ O,P [τ H,O, τ H,P ]. However, by Assumption 3 and Lemma 2, we know τ H,P < w P < w P τ O,P [τ H,O, τ H,P ] if (IR-HP) binds. Thus, (BC-HP) becomes redundant and τ H,P is always risk-free. We shall see this formally in section 4.1. First, let us study a useful benchmark that gives us the highest utility H can attain. 11

3.5 First-best: w P = 0 In this case, τ O,P = (0, 0) and H would choose τ H,P = (0, 0). This provides a useful benchmark since O does not have commitment problem. O s value function becomes E O [(w O τ H,O ) + ]. In words, O chooses whether to accept τ O. With w O being common knowledge, H would only offer contract τ H,O w O. This reduces O s objective function to E O [w O τ H,O ]. Thus, O would only accept the contract if E O [w O τ H,O ] E O [w O ] or E O [τ H,O ] 0. In other words, O only accepts contract τ O if it makes O at least break even with respect to O s own belief. Knowing this, H maximizes E H [u(r + τ H,O )] subject to O s budget constraint, τ H,O w O, and individual rationality constraint, E O [τ H,O ] 0. Proposition 3 There is a unique solution τh,o F B s.t. τ H,O F B τ h 1 (π ). Given Assumption 1, τ F B H,O F B F B is either interior or τh,o (1) = 1. In either case, τh,o w O. Since H has all the bargaining power, H would extract all the surplus from O. Thus, the price of the contract is h 1 (π ). This provides a useful benchmark since we now know that given price h 1 (π ), H would choose to purchase τh,o F B (0) units of contract. Since H is risk-averse, if the price is higher (lower), H would purchase less (more) of the contract, respectively. I define counterparty risk as the difference between H s equilibrium contract and τ F B When the equilibrium contract is τh,o F B, I say there is no counterparty risk. H,O. 4 Equilibrium Equilibrium is defined as Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium with contracts {τ H,O, τ H,P, τ O,P } such that they solve H and O s problems and both O and P accept contracts τ H,O and τ H,P. 4.1 Preliminary Analysis As discussed previously, given Assumption 3, (IR-HP) can be reduced to E P [w p τ H,P ] E P [w p ]. (IR -HP) as P has enough wealth to insure H. So then, (IR -HP) implies τ H,P (1, h 1 (π)). In other words, H can only trade with P at price of h 1 (π). By Lemma 2, w p τ H,P (0) > 0 implies 12

w p τ O,P (0) τ H,P (0) > 0. This implies (BC-HP) can be removed and I can replace τ H,P with τ H,P. In other words, P never defaults on H and so I can replace the recovery contract τ H,P in H s objective function with the actual contract τ H,P. Moreover, since w p τ O,P (0) τ H,P (0) > 0, P s value function reduces to E P [w P τ O,P τ H,P ]. Thus, O s (IR -P) simplifies further to a break-even condition for P E P [τ O,P ] = 0. (IR -P) which implies O can sell insurance to P for price of h 1 (π). (IR -P) was the only condition that dependents on both τ H,P (0) and τ H,P (1). With (IR -P) replaced by (IR -P), O s problem only depends on τ H,P (1) with (BC-HP). By Lemma 2, (BC-O) is modified to τ O,P w O. (BC -O) Since τ O,P is in the same direction as τ H,O, O pays out to P exactly when H asks O for payment. Thus, contract τ H,O does not increase O s budget constraint anymore. Given Lemma 2 and the above, we have the following Proposition. Proposition 4 Given any τ H,P (1), there is a unique solution τo,p [τ H,P (1)] ( 1, h 1 (π)) to O s problem. τo,p is independent of τ H,O and τ H,P (0). Moreover, τo,p is a corner solution determined by either (BC -O) and (BC-P). τo,p is only dependent on τ H,P (1) when (BC-P) binds. Since O can sell insurance to P for price of h 1 (π) and O is willing to sell insurance for a price of at least h 1 (π ), O is willing to sell insurance to P until either O runs out of money or P runs out of money. This leads to non-commitment problem as O is willing to sell insurance to P to the limit regardless of contract O as accepted from H. Given Proposition 4, as long as the recovery contract τ H,O breaks even for O, O will happily accept τ H,O. Given independence of τo,p from τ H,O, I can replace τ H,O in H s problem with τ H,O and modify (IR-HO) and (BC-HO) to E O [τ H,O ] 0, τ H,O w O + τ O,P [τ H,P (1)]. (IR -HO) (BC -HO) Thus, H can offer contract with price as low as h 1 (π ), which makes O break even. H can do this as long as she knows O has enough resources to pay her. Moreover, the independence statements in Proposition 4 imply 13

Proposition 5 Either τh,o = (0, 0) or τ H,P = (0, 0). In equilibrium, H would only consider trading with O or P. There are two cases. First, H would only trade with O when P runs out of wealth first when trading with O, i.e. (BC-P) binds. Intuitively, when H trades with both P, P would take promises from H and use it to trade with O. This diverts state 0 wealth of O away from H s contract with O. Thus, H is essentially competing against herself for O s state 0 wealth. Second, H would only trade with P when O runs out of wealth first in O s trade with P. In that case, O gives all of her state 0 wealth to P. Thus, H cannot expect O to pay her anything. Thus, H would only trade with P in that case. I shall divide the parameter space into 2 scenarios to highlight effect of the non-commitment problem. In the first scenario, O has more wealth relative to H and R. In that case, the non-commitment problem has no effect on H as P s budget constraint binds before O can sell enough insurance to default on H s contract. In the second scenario, O s wealth is relatively lower compared to case 1. In this case, the non-commitment problem is worse for H as O s wealth decreases. 4.2 Scenario 1: Wealthy O, No Counterparty Risk I first study the case when O is wealthy enough to not have commitment problem. I assume Assumption 4 w O τ F B O (0) + h(π)w P. This assumptions states that O has enough wealth to trade with both P and H without default. The first term τo F B (0) is the optimal amount of insurance H purchases when faced with a price of h(π ). Recall O can sell insurance to P for a price of h 1 (π). Thus, the second term h(π)w P represent how much wealth O needs to sell risk-free insurance to P when P purchases enough insurance to exhaust her entire endowment. Assumption 4 only restricts O s wealth relative to H and P s wealth. It does not post any condition on relative wealth between H and P. Thus, Assumption 4 does not conflict with any earlier assumptions. Given this condition, we have the following Proposition 6 Given Assumption 4, there is a unique equilibrium with τ (0) H,O = τ F B H,O, τ (0) H,P = (0, 0), and τ (0) O,P = w p ( h(π), 1). Since H can purchase insurance from O for cheaper, H strictly prefers to do so. In this case, the first-best contract is available and so H has no appetite for more insurance from P, especially since P only accepts offers at a higher price. 14

Thus, when O is wealthy relative to H and P, O does not default on contract signed with H. However, O only fulfill promises to H because P s endowment constraints P from buying more insurance. Thus, the non-commitment problem of O does not affect H. In this case, I say there is no counterparty risk. 4.3 Scenario 2: Less Wealthy O, with Counterparty Risk In this case, I study the equilibrium when O has less wealth than before. Assumption 5 w O < τ F B O (0) + h(π)w P. The first inequality states that O has enough wealth to trade with P so that P runs out of wealth first. The second inequality states that now when O trades to the limit with P, the first best contract between H and O is no longer feasible. In such case, one may expect H to trade with both O and P. However, as we shall see, H trades with either O or P but never both. Proposition 7 There is a unique equilibrium. There are 3 cases depending on w O. 1. τ (1) H,O = w O + τ (1) O,P (0) (1, h 1 (π )), τ (1) H,P = (0, 0), and τ (1) O,P = w p ( h(π), 1) 2. τ (2) (2) H,O = (0, 0), τ H,P (1, h 1 (π)), and τ (2) O,P = (w p τ(2) H,P (1)) ( h(π), 1), 3. τ (2) (2) H,O = (0, 0), τ H,P (1, h 1 (π)), and τ (3) O,P = w O ( 1, h 1 (π)), where τ (2) H,P (0) is the optimal amount of insurance H purchases given price h(π). Equilibrium is in case 2 and 3 when U H (τ (2) H,O, τ (2) H,P ) U H(τ (1) H,O, τ (1) H,P ). There exists are unique w O h(π)w P and wo in the interval in Assumption 5, such that case 1 is the equilibrium for w O > wo, case 2 is the equilibrium for w O < w O wo, and case 3 is the equilibrium otherwise. When w O is in the interval defined in Assumption 5, there are 3 possible cases. When O s wealth is high, H only buys insurance from O. Though H purchase the insurance at a low price of h 1 (π ), the quantity H can purchase is constrained by O s non-commitment problem. In such case, H can only purchase partial insurance. H can also simultaneously buy insurance from P but H chooses not to since buying insurance from P increases O s non-commitment problem. This devalues H s existing contract with O. When H buys insurance from both P and O, H is essentially competing against herself for O s wealth. Thus, there is equilibrium rationing in case 1. H only buy cheap partial insurance from O. In this case, there is pricing effect of non-commitment problem, i.e. counterparty risk, since H deals with the problem 15

by decreasing quantity purchased. This implies that when we do not see counterparty risk being priced in the data, it doesn t mean counterparty risk has no effect. The effect may just not be in the price. H s welfare can still very much be improved as we shall see later. In case 2 and 3, H is better off buying full insurance at higher price than buying cheaper partial insurance. When H buys more expensive insurance from P, part of the insurance may be sold by O through P. Even though by Assumption 3 that P has enough wealth to insure H, each unit of insurance H buys induces O to sell one more unit of insurance to P. This happens in case 2 until O runs out of wealth and the equilibrium moves to case 3. This result is fairly consistent with Du et al. (2016), who documents that CDS market participants are less likely to trade with counterparties who have credit risk correlated with the underlying. In our model, O has risk correlated with the underlying R since O has incentive to bet on R. When the non-commitment problem become severer as w O decreases, H chooses to switch to buying insurance from P, whose risk is inversely correlated with R. Notice H offers the same contracts in cases 2 and 3, regardless of contract between O and P. This is because by Assumption 3, P has enough to insure H. If that were not the case, H would be worse off in case 2, only able to buy partial insurance at high price. In case 3, O gives her entire endowment to P in state 0. Since O can fully insure H even at the lower price, by Assumption 1, P can fully insure H with O s endowment even when P has very little endowment herself. In all 3 cases, H cannot offer the first-best contract in equilibrium. In case 1, price is same as in first-best but quantity is less. In case 2 and 3, price is lower than the price in first-best. 5 Hedging In this section, I relax Assumption 3 and allow O to have the option to purchase insurance from P. In this case, the incentive for O and P to bet in either direction may not be as strong. Thus, H may have to hedge by trading with both O and P. I will show that H has the option to hedge his contracts by trading with both O and P and I provide lower bound and upper bound on the cost of hedging. Recall τ O,P can be either R R or R + R. I can rule out τ O,P R R and τ O,P R + R ++ right off the bat. Contracts in the first space means non-negative transfers from O to P in both states while contracts in the second one means non-negative transfers from P to O in both states. O would prefer offering (0, 0) to offering any contract τ O,P R R. P would never accept any contract τ O,P R + R ++ since P is better off with (0, 0). Thus, I only need to consider contracts τ O,P that in either R R + or R + R. In other words, 16

I only need to consider O buying insurance from P or selling insurance to P. First, let us define useful notations. I shall denote τ O,P,+ τ O,P R + R and τ O,P, τ O,P R R + (7) In words, τ O,P,+ represents O buying insurance from P while τ O,P, represents O selling insurance to P. Moreover, I define U O (τ H,O, τ H,P, i) max τ O,P,i Û O (τ O,P,i τ H,O, τ H,P ) (8) τ O,P,i arg max τ O,P,i Û O (τ O,P,i τ H,O, τ H,P ) (9) for i {+, }. U O (τ H,O, τ H,P, +) is O s problem with the restriction that O can only buy insurance for P. U O (τ H,O, τ H,P, ) is defined analogously. We have the following Lemma. Lemma 8 Given τ H,P and τ H,O, τ O,P,+ is either (0, 0) or (w P, (w P τ H,P (0)) + h 1 (π). τ O,P, is 1. w O ( τ h 1 (π)) (0, (τ H,P (0) w P ) + h 1 (π)), if (w O (τ H,P (0) w P ) + )h 1 (π) w P τ H,P (1), 2. h(π)(w P τ H,P (1))( τ h 1 (π)) ((τ H,P (0) w P ) +, 0), if (w O (τ H,P (0) w P ) + )h 1 (π) > w P τ H,P (1), 3. (0, 0) if 1 and 2 gives lower expected utility. Thus, given τ H,P and τ H,O, I only need to compare τo,p,+ and τ O,P, to find out whether O prefers to buy insurance from or to sell insurance to P. Now I can define the incentive compatibility constraints of O, i.e. Û O (τ O,P,+ τ H,O, τ H,P ) ÛO(τ O,P, τ H,O, τ H,P ). Û O (τ O,P,+ τ H,O, τ H,P ) ÛO(τ O,P, τ H,O, τ H,P ). (IC-O-B) (IC-O-S) The first IC constraint states O prefers buying insurance from P. The second IC constraint states O prefers selling insurance to P. I augment H s problem with the incentive compatibility constraints. Whether H prefers O to buy insurance from P or otherwise, it must be incentive compatible for O to do so. For H s problem, (IR-HO) requires comparison between ÛO(τ O,P τ H,O, τ H,P ) and ÛO(τ O,P (0, 0), τ H,P ) to determine the price of the contract. To aid the comparison in (IR-HO), we have the following Lemma. 17

Lemma 9 Given τ H,P and τ H,O, ÛO(τ O,P,+ τ H,O, τ H,P ) ÛO(τ O,P, τ H,O, τ H,P ) only if Û O (τ O,P,+ (0, 0), τ H,P ) ÛO(τ O,P, (0, 0), τ H,P ) for all τ O,P,+ and τ O,P,. In words, if O prefers to buy insurance from P given τ H,O and τ H,P, O also prefers to buy insurance from P when O rejects contract τ H,O from H. Intuitively, τ H,O increases O s expected utility more when O sells insurance to P since O can default on τ H,O. Thus, if O doesn t want to buy insurance from P even when O rejects contract τ H,O, O would not want to buy insurance from P no matter what τ H,O O accepts. Thus, the decision of O to buy insurance from P relies heavily on τ H,P. Moreover, Lemma 9 simplifies H s problem since if H wants O to buy insurance from P in equilibrium, and chooses τ H,P so it happens. H can solve for τ H,O using (IR-HO) knowing (IC-O-B) holds for τ H,O = (0, 0). Thus, we have the following Lemma. Proposition 10 For τ H,P such that (IC-O-B) holds for τ H,O = (0, 0), there is a unique τ (4) H,O [τ H,P ] that maximizes H s objective function given τ H,P. τ (4) H,O τ h 1 (π ). Either τ H,O = τ (4) H,O and τ H,P = (0, τ H,P (1)) or τ H,O = (w O (w P τ H,P (1))h 1 (π)) + and τ H,P = τ H,P. Above I characterize the solutions to H s problem given τ H,P that induces O to sell insurance to P when O does not trade with H. Given τ H,P, H either chooses to insure τ H,O by giving money to P for free or to insure τ H,P by offering O a contract which O will default on. Thus, in general, it s possible for H to hedge her position by inducing O to buy insurance from P. When P defaults on τ H,P, τ H,P (1) is the cost of hedging τ H,O. When O defaults on τ H,O, τ H,O (1) τ H,O (0)h 1 (π ) is the cost of hedging τ H,O. The hedging is going to be very expensive for τ H,O. Below I provide upper bound and lower bound on cost of hedging. Proposition 11 Hedging cost for τ H,O has a lower bound of min [ (w O + w P ) ( h 1 (π) h 1 (π ) ), h 1 (π) ( 1 + h 1 (π) ) (h(π ) h(π)) w P, h 1 (π)w P ] and an upper bound of h 1 (π)w P. Hedging cost for τ H,P has a lower bound of 0 and an upper bound of [min (w O, h(π)w P ) (h 1 (π) h 1 (π )) h 1 (π )w P ] +. Hedging cost of τ H,O increases with w P. When w P increases, so does counterparty risk. Thus, hedging cost co-moves with counterparty risk. Depending on w O, w P, π and π, hedging τ H,O may be expensive. Hedging τ H,P is not as expensive since H can always pick τ H,P so that no hedging is needed, i.e. both (IC-O-B) and (IC-O-S) binds with equality at τ H,O = (0, 0). Hedging is cheaper when the gains from O betting with P is small, i.e. h 1 (π) h 1 (π ) is small. When cost of hedging is small enough, H may choose to hedge in equilibrium. 18

6 Central Clearing After the recent financial crisis, both U.S. and Euro-zone has pushed for central clearing of OTC derivatives to reduce counterparty risk. Central clearing is done through use of central counterparty (CCP), who stands between trades and guarantees payment. The process is called novation. The CCP takes a contract agreed upon by two parties and replace the contract with two new contracts. The two new contracts is equivalent to the old contract. However, the parties now both trade with the CCP. This way, the CCP can guarantee trades while implementing tools to reduce counterparty risk. Two main tools CCP uses are collateral requirement and loss sharing. Since our agents do not have money in t = 0, 1, collateral does not apply here. I shall focus on the loss sharing. I examine the effect of applying CCP loss sharing to our problem. 6.1 Loss sharing A CCP does not have endowment. Thus, whenever one agent trading with the CCP defaults, the CCP spread the loss across all the other agents trading with the CCP. Agents trading directly with the CCP are called clearing members. Agents trading with the clearing members are called clients. When an clearing member defaults on a client s trade, CCP spread the loss to all other clearing members by withholding their payments until the client s obligations are paid in full. In our setting, when trying to maximize H s welfare, I designate H as the client and the insurers as the clearing members. While I can model CCP literally by creating 2 new contracts for each existing contract, it is not necessary to do so. For the purpose of modeling loss sharing, I can simply deduct any defaulted amount from all non-defaulting clearing members. Given, Lemma 2, I only need consider when O defaults on τ H,O. Recall τ H,O as defined in the hedger s problem. Suppose τ H,O > τ H,O, i.e. O defaults on contract with H. I deduct the difference τ H,O τ H,O from O s contract with P, i.e. τ O,P. The effective contract P receives from O is thus τ O,P = τ O,P (τ H,O τ H,O) with the restriction that τ O,P 0. I need to rewrite O s problem in terms of τ O,P. For simplicity, I assume τ H,O w O. This simplifies the notation. At t = 1, O now solves max E O [w O + τ τ O,P O,P τ H,O ] 19

subject to P s individual rationality constraint E P [τ O,P ] = 0, (IR-P-CCP) and budget constraints, or loss sharing constraints τ O,P w O τ H,O, τ O,P w P τ H,P. (BC-O-CCP) (BC-P-CCP) With loss sharing, O cannot credibly promise τ O,P to P, O can only promise τ O,P. Recall I assumed commitment between O and P. It is not different here. Only now, loss sharing means H can be assured to receive τ H,O. Given this problem, we have the following Proposition. Proposition 12 There is a unique equilibrium with τh,o CCP, which weakly improves H s welfare compared with corresponds cases in section 4.3. In some cases, the price of τh,o CCP is between h 1 (π) and h 1 (π ). τ CCP H,O is not first-best. With loss sharing, H can be guaranteed payment if O accepts H s contract. However, since O can reject contract from H and sell insurance to P, H competes with P in price. Thus, first-best cannot be reached. Nevertheless, loss sharing weakly improves H s welfare. Moreover, H may purchase blocks of insurance from O for different price. For example, in case 1 from 4.3, H can purchase partial insurance at price h 1 (π ) without CCP. With CCP, H no longer has to compete against herself when purchasing more insurance at high price h 1 (π). Thus, H may wish to purchase more insurance at higher price from O. The average price of all the insurance H buys from O may be between the high price and low price. 6.2 Voluntary Central Clearing In this case, both O and P are indifferent to entering central clearing if entry is voluntary. Even in cases when P has some bargaining power, H can always compensate O and P enough so that both O and P would be willing to enter central clearing. Moreover, H can still do better after compensating O and P than H could have done without central clearing. 7 Discussions 7.1 Different Beliefs, Bargaining Power As long as there is an insurer more optimistic than the other insurer, our results goes through. 20

If both insurers are more optimistic than the hedger, we have the same results. If pessimist is more pessimistic than the hedger, the hedger may prefer to not purchase insurance from the pessimist if the pessimist s belief is below the hedger s certainty equivalent. Similarly, if both insurers are more pessimistic than the hedger, the hedger may choose not to purchase insurance when both insurers beliefs are below the hedger s certainty equivalent. In the model, I gave all the bargaining power to O. I can give all the bargaining power to P and the same results would go through. When P has all the bargaining power relative to O, P can extract all the surplus when trading with O. However, P will still only accept contract from H with price no lower that h 1 (π). Thus, in cases similar to the ones in section 4.3, H may still prefer to purchase partial insurance from O at price of h 1 (π ) < h 1 (π). When both O and P have some bargaining power, similar intuition applies. When H doesn t have all the bargaining power, similar intuition applies. In that case, O and P still cannot commit to not betting with each other at t = 1. 7.2 Collateral Our seniority assumption is reminiscent of setting with collateral. Imagine O and P have endowment at t = 0 and H can ask for collateral. However, suppose O and P have expertise in manage collateral costlessly while H can only manage collateral with a cost. In the case when the cost H incurs to manage collateral is too high, H would prefer the equilibrium with no collateral. In that case, O and P can still post collateral costlessly to each other and thus have seniority in each other s claim. This case is exactly equivalent to our model. 8 Conclusion I study how hedger manages counterparty risk when insurers with heterogeneous beliefs cannot commit to not betting with each other. When the insurers are wealthy relative to the hedger, the hedger cannot change the direction of the insurers bet. In that case, the hedger chooses between cheaper partial insurance and more expensive full insurance. The hedger does not trade with both insurers since her contract with one insurer devalues her contract with the other insurer. When the hedger chooses cheaper partial insurance, the hedger manages counterparty risk through rationing of quantity purchased. Thus, the price of insurance does not reflect counterparty risk. This is consistent with the empirical findings (e.g. Arora et al. (2012), Du et al. (2016)) that effect of countparty risk on price of OTC derivative contracts is small. When the hedger chooses the more expensive full insurance, the hedger chooses to trade with pessimist whose credit risk is less correlated with the 21

underlying. This is consistent with findings in Du et al. (2016). I provide upper and lower bound on cost of H hedging her insurance contract. When gains from betting for O and P is small, hedging may become cheaper. When hedging is cheap enough, H may choose hedging by trading with both counterparties. I also examine the effect of central clearing on hedger s welfare in our setting. We focus on the ability of central counterparty to share losses across its members. In this case, central clearing increases hedger s welfare. However, since the hedger has to compete with pessimist in price, the first-best cannot be reached. In our paper, both insurers are indifferent between participating in central clearing or not. Thus, even if participation is voluntary, the hedger can induce both insurers to participate. This result is contrary to similar papers that study the loss-sharing ability of central counterparty. 22