Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Similar documents
Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

PhD Qualifier Examination

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Answers Econ 8712

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

(a) Ben s affordable bundle if there is no insurance market is his endowment: (c F, c NF ) = (50,000, 500,000).

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Problem Set. Solutions to the problems appear at the end of this document.

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Lecture 8: Asset pricing

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Financial Mathematics III Theory summary

Lecture 2: Stochastic Discount Factor

Master in Industrial Organization and Markets. Spring 2012 Microeconomics III Assignment 1: Uncertainty

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Advanced Microeconomic Theory

PhD Qualifier Examination

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2009 examination. 2008/2009 syllabus

Homework 3: Asset Pricing

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

GE in production economies

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Question 1: (60 points)

Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

Arbitrage Pricing. What is an Equivalent Martingale Measure, and why should a bookie care? Department of Mathematics University of Texas at Austin

( 0) ,...,S N ,S 2 ( 0)... S N S 2. N and a portfolio is created that way, the value of the portfolio at time 0 is: (0) N S N ( 1, ) +...

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Midterm #2 EconS 527 [November 7 th, 2016]

ECON 581. Introduction to Arrow-Debreu Pricing and Complete Markets. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

PAPER NO.1 : MICROECONOMICS ANALYSIS MODULE NO.6 : INDIFFERENCE CURVES

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

General Equilibrium under Uncertainty

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Lecture 18 - Information, Adverse Selection, and Insurance Markets

5. Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior

Golden rule. The golden rule allocation is the stationary, feasible allocation that maximizes the utility of the future generations.

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral.

Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Answers Econ 8712

This assignment is due on Tuesday, September 15, at the beginning of class (or sooner).

Microeconomics II. CIDE, Spring 2011 List of Problems

Finance: A Quantitative Introduction Chapter 7 - part 2 Option Pricing Foundations

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Microeconomic Theory II Spring 2016 Final Exam Solutions

u (x) < 0. and if you believe in diminishing return of the wealth, then you would require

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

1. Introduction of another instrument of savings, namely, capital

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

Choice under Uncertainty

Answers to June 11, 2012 Microeconomics Prelim

Chapter 2 Equilibrium and Efficiency

Limits to Arbitrage. George Pennacchi. Finance 591 Asset Pricing Theory

Economics 602 Macroeconomic Theory and Policy Problem Set 3 Suggested Solutions Professor Sanjay Chugh Spring 2012

First Welfare Theorem in Production Economies

University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno. Economics 103: Economics of uncertainty and information PRACTICE PROBLEMS

Supplement to the lecture on the Diamond-Dybvig model

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Choice Under Uncertainty (Chapter 12)

John Geanakoplos: The Leverage Cycle

Chapter 31: Exchange

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Solutions to Problem Set 1

Microeconomics 3200/4200:

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 8: Insurance Markets

Game Theory. Important Instructions

Assignment 5 Advanced Microeconomics

ECONOMICS 723. Models with Overlapping Generations

Problem Set VI: Edgeworth Box

Interest Rates and Currency Prices in a Two-Country World. Robert E. Lucas, Jr. 1982

Slides III - Complete Markets

Transcription:

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 9, 2015

Review of Last Week Consumer choice problem General equilibrium Contingent claims Risk aversion

The optimal choice, x = (X, Y ), is where the indifference curve is tangent to the budget line. The slope of the indifference curve (= MRS) is equal to the slope of the budget line (= the price ratio). Another way to state this is U = λ(p x, P y ) T : the gradient of the utility function is a scalar multiple of the price vector Suppose the consumer has an initial endowment of goods ω = (X ω, Y ω ). Then this is equivalent to having an income of I = P x X ω + P y Y ω.

An allocation on the Edgeworth box is a Walrasian equilibrium if neither agent has any incentive to trade. This occurs when the indifference curves of both agents are tangent to each other.

The price vector is then the slope of the indifference curves at the equilibrium allocation point. You can think of this as two consumer choice problems being solved simultaneously, using the same prices.

Contingent Claims We can extend consumer choice framework to handle time and risk by expanding our definition of what a good is. We can add the time of availability to the definition of a good. For example: instead of two goods apple and orange, we can define the good 1 apple today and 1 orange, one week from now. We can also define a good to be contingent on a random event. Examples: umbrella when it is raining vs. umbrella when it is not raining 1 unit of grain when the harvest is good vs. 1 unit of grain when the harvest is bad income when there is a recession vs. income when there is an expansion These are called contingent claims.

Two-Period Model At t = 0, there is complete uncertainty: the only information agents have is that all states of the world are possible. At t = 1, uncertainty is resolved: all agents know exactly which state of the world has occurred.

Let E(x) = π low x low + π high x high, the expected value of x. A risk-averse consumer gets higher expected utility from the lottery (E(x), E(x)) than from (x low, x high ).

Finance Economy A finance economy combines the GE model with risk averse utility functions. Suppose there is only one consumption good, call it money, income or wealth. A financial asset is a security that entitles its holder to a specified payout for each possible state of the world. Suppose that asset j is specified by: r j = (r j 1,..., r j S )T Whoever holds 1 unit of asset j will receive r j s at t = 1, if the state of the world happens to be s. r j s is called a state-contingent payoff.

The car insurance in last lecture s example could be thought of as having two state-contingent payoffs: in the crash state, pays 1 in the ok state, pays 0 An asset is called risky if it gives a different payoff in different states. An asset is called riskless or risk-free if it gives the same payoff in every state. A storage asset (e.g. cash) would be (1,..., 1) T. A riskless bond with nominal yield 1 + r would be (1 + r,..., 1 + r) T.

Finance Economy In the real world, stocks or equities are a claim of ownership over a fraction of a firm. This entitles the stockholder to a fraction of the profits of the firm. A bond is a loan, which may or may not be repaid. In the model, stocks and non-government bonds are modeled as risky assets, that is, their payouts will be different in different states of the world.

Finance Economy For example, if the possible states of the world are recession and expansion, then a stock could give a high payout in the expansion state and a low payout in the recession state. For bonds, the states of the world might be success or bankrupt. The bond gives the promised payout in the success state, and gives a zero payout in the bankrupt state. A riskless bond is a special kind of bond, that gives the same payout in all states. Obviously nothing is completely riskless in real life, but for our purposes we can treat the sovereign debt of rich nations with no history of default as riskless.

We can write down the state-contingent payoffs of a particular asset in a vector.

Suppose there are J assets. We can write all their state-contingent payoffs in a matrix.

Suppose we have a square n n matrix M. A row (or column) of M is called linearly independent if it cannot be written as a linear combination of the other rows (or columns). A basic fact from linear algebra is that if M has n linearly independent rows (or columns), then any n-dimensional vector can be written as a linear combination of these rows (or columns). We can apply this fact to the matrix of state-contingent payoffs: if there are S states, and S linearly independent assets, then any asset can be replicated by some combination of the S assets. If this holds, we say that the markets are complete. In an economy with complete markets, any possible risk can be insured against. In the real world, markets are incomplete, but as new types of securities and derivatives are invented, the markets are moving closer to completeness.

Arrow securities The simplest asset is one that pays 1 unit in exactly one state of the world s, and zero in all other states. e s = (0, 0,..., 1,...0) T This is called the Arrow security for state s. Any financial asset can be represented as a linear combination of Arrow securities. If we assume the law of one price, that is, any asset with the same state-contingent payoffs should have the same price... Then we should be able to find the price of any asset as a combination of prices of Arrow securities.

Two-Period Economy By convention, we will say that t = 0 is state s = 0, and the states at t = 1 are s = 1, 2,..., S. Let y s denote the amount of consumption in state s. Assume agents have a utility function v(y 0 ) + δe [v(y)] = v(y 0 ) + δ π s v(y s ) π s is the probability that state s occurs. v( ) is a vnm utility function. δ (0, 1) is the discount factor. This type of utility function is time-separable, i.e. additive in the utility for t = 0 and t = 1. S s=1

Efficient Risk-Sharing Suppose there are two agents, S = {1, 2}, and agents are risk-averse: v i ( ) is strictly concave. Agents are endowed with some amount of securities that pay off at t = 1. Assume there is no aggregate risk: the sum of endowments for each state s is constant. There may be idiosyncratic risk: the endowment for an individual agent may differ across states. The mutuality principle states that an efficient allocation in this situation will diversify away idiosyncratic risk. Agents will consume the same amount in both states; they will only bear aggregate risk.

Assume each agent s utility is: u i (y i (0), y i (1), y i (2)) = v(y i (0)) + δ π s v(y i (s)) y i (s) is the amount consumed in state s by agent i. S s=1 Assume the same aggregate income in both states: y 1 (1) + y 2 (1) = y 1 (2) + y 2 (2) = W At equilibrium, both agents MRS are equal to each other and the price ratio. u 1 y 1 (1) u 1 y 1 (2) = u 2 y 2 (1) u 2 y 2 (2) π 1 v 1 (y 1 (1)) π 2 v 1 (y 1 (2)) = π 1v 2 (W y 1 (1)) π 2 v 2 (W y 1 (2)) v 1 (y 1 (1)) v 2 (W y 1 (1)) = v 1 (y 1 (2)) v 2 (W y 1 (2))

u 1 y 1 (1) u 1 y 1 (2) = u 2 y 2 (1) u 2 y 2 (2) π 1 v 1 (y 1 (1)) π 2 v 1 (y 1 (2)) = π 1v 2 (W y 1 (1)) π 2 v 2 (W y 1 (2)) v 1 (y 1 (1)) v 2 (W y 1 (1)) = v 1 (y 1 (2)) v 2 (W y 1 (2)) By assumption, v 1, v 2 are strictly concave, therefore v 1, v 2 are strictly decreasing. v 1 (x) The function f (x) = is strictly decreasing, so if two values v 2 (W x) x, x give f (x) = f (x ), then x = x. Therefore, y 1 (1) = y 1 (2) and both agents consume the same amount in each state.

Example 5.3(a) Suppose there are two states of the world, with probabilities π, 1 π respectively. There are two agents with utility function of income ln(x). Agents do not care about current consumption (in time t = 0), only consumption at t = 1. Therefore, we can write their utility function as U(y(1), y(2)) = π ln(y(1)) + (1 π) ln(y(2)) where y(1), y(2) are consumption in state 1 and state 2, respectively. Suppose each agent s initial endowment is: w 1 = [ 1 3 ], w 2 = [ 3 1 ]

We want to find the equilibrium prices and allocations. Note that there is no aggregate uncertainty: combined endowment is the same in state 1 and state 2. Therefore, we know that in equilibrium, both agents will achieve perfect insurance (that is, consume the same amount in each state). This is the 45-degree line on the Edgeworth box. Suppose π = 1/2, and let p 1, p 2 be the prices of the Arrow securities for state 1 and 2, respectively. The optimality condition MRS 1 = MRS 2 = p1 p 2 becomes: πy 1 (2) (1 π)y 1 (1) = πy 2 (2) (1 π)y 2 (1) = p 1 p 2 y 1 (2) y 1 (1) = y 2 (2) y 2 (1) = p 1 p 2 Since y 1 (2) = y 1 (1), then p 1 = p 2. Let s choose p 1 = p 2 = 1.

What is the optimal consumption of agents 1 and 2, given prices p 1 = p 2 = 1? At these prices, agent 1 s wealth is 1 1 + 1 3 = 4; agent 2 s wealth is 1 3 + 1 1 = 4. The optimal consumption for both agents is y 1 = 2, y 2 = 2. This also satisfies the market clearing condition, since the total amount of y 1 consumed by both agents is equal to the total initial endowment (and the same holds for y 2 ). Therefore, the Walrasian equilibrium is the combination of price and allocation: prices: any p1, p 2 that satisfies p 1 = p 2 allocation: agent 1 s consumption is (2, 2), agent 2 s consumption is (2, 2) The two conditions for a Walrasian equilibrium are satisfied: Both agents are choosing the utility maximizing choice, given prices p 1, p 2 Market clearing is satisfied: for each of the goods y(1), y(2), total consumption is equal to total endowment

Note that both agents are perfectly insured (that is, consume the same amount in each state). The agents are insuring each other. This is only possible because the good state for agent 1 is the bad state for agent 2, and vice versa. This is an example of mutual insurance: a group of consumers pool their resources to insure each other, instead of going to an outside party like an insurance company.

Mutuality Principle Lengwiler Box 5.1 (Mutuality Principle): An efficient allocation of risk requires that only aggregate risk be borne by agents. All idiosyncratic risk is diversified away by mutual insurance among agents. The marginal aggregate risk borne by an agent equals the ratio of his absolute risk tolerance to the average risk tolerance of the population. The mutuality principle can fail if: Beliefs are heterogeneous (different agents have different subjective probabilities of states) if market frictions (e.g. trading costs, short sale constraints) impede Pareto efficiency if markets are incomplete

Mutuality Principle This principle has many applications in different fields of economics. In international macro, many papers try to test efficient risk sharing among different countries, and explain if/why it does not occur In labor, test efficient risk sharing among workers, retirees, health insurance consumers, etc Many of the models we have seen in this course want to explain banks as a way to implement some sort of risk-sharing. However, risk-sharing is not the only motivation for financial transactions.

What happens if agent 1 is risk-averse, but agent 2 is risk-neutral? For example, suppose agent 1 and agent 2 have utility functions (where v is a concave function):. U 1 (y 1 (1), y 1 (2)) = πv(y 1 (1)) + (1 π)v(y 1 (2)) U 2 (y 2 (1), y 2 (2)) = πy 2 (1) + (1 π)y 2 (2) Agent 2 s indifference curves will be linear. The condition MRS 1 = MRS 2 will become: πv (y 1 (1)) (1 π)v (y 1 (2)) = π 1 π

πv (y 1 (1)) (1 π)v (y 1 (2)) = π 1 π By the same argument as before, agent 1 will fully insure: y 1 (1) = y 1 (2). Note that we are no longer assuming that there is no aggregate uncertainty: the total endowment of each good may be different in different states. This means that in equilibrium, the risk-neutral agent is assuming all the risk, and the risk-averse agent has shifted all of his risk away.

Next Week Homework 1 is due next week. Next week, we will start a brief introduction to game theory. Please read Chapter 2.1-2.8 in Osborne.