Signaling Games. Farhad Ghassemi

Similar documents
ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

HW Consider the following game:

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

Auctions. Michal Jakob Agent Technology Center, Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering, FEE, Czech Technical University

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Game Theory. Important Instructions

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

Answers to Problem Set 4

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: Explanation and Step-by-step examples

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 ANSWER KEY

Games with incomplete information about players. be symmetric or asymmetric.

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński

Name. FINAL EXAM, Econ 171, March, 2015

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions and Nash Paths

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Games of Incomplete Information

Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Auctions. Michal Jakob Agent Technology Center, Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering, FEE, Czech Technical University

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Repeated, Stochastic and Bayesian Games

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Econ 618 Simultaneous Move Bayesian Games

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Topics in Informational Economics 2 Games with Private Information and Selling Mechanisms

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization

CHAPTER 14: REPEATED PRISONER S DILEMMA

National Security Strategy: Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Finding Equilibria in Games of No Chance

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

MKTG 555: Marketing Models

Economics 502 April 3, 2008

Introductory Microeconomics

Lecture Notes on Adverse Selection and Signaling

Rationalizable Strategies

Extensive form games - contd

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game.

Dynamic games with incomplete information

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Information and Evidence in Bargaining

When does strategic information disclosure lead to perfect consumer information?

Microeconomic Theory II Spring 2016 Final Exam Solutions

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions.

Microeconomic Theory III Final Exam March 18, 2010 (80 Minutes)

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

Economics 171: Final Exam

SUCCESSIVE INFORMATION REVELATION IN 3-PLAYER INFINITELY REPEATED GAMES WITH INCOMPLETE INFORMATION ON ONE SIDE

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Chapter 3. Dynamic discrete games and auctions: an introduction

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Incentive Compatibility: Everywhere vs. Almost Everywhere

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Out of equilibrium beliefs and Refinements of PBE

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty

Problem Set 5 Answers

Optimal stopping problems for a Brownian motion with a disorder on a finite interval

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions

Jianfei Shen. School of Economics, The University of New South Wales, Sydney 2052, Australia

Advanced Micro 1 Lecture 14: Dynamic Games Equilibrium Concepts

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants

Simon Fraser University Fall Econ 302 D200 Final Exam Solution Instructor: Songzi Du Wednesday December 16, 2015, 8:30 11:30 AM

Notes for Section: Week 7

1 x i c i if x 1 +x 2 > 0 u i (x 1,x 2 ) = 0 if x 1 +x 2 = 0

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 2. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Beliefs and Sequential Rationality

SI 563 Homework 3 Oct 5, Determine the set of rationalizable strategies for each of the following games. a) X Y X Y Z

Chapter 2 Strategic Dominance

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

October 9. The problem of ties (i.e., = ) will not matter here because it will occur with probability

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture X: Introduction to Game Theory

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

1 R. 2 l r 1 1 l2 r 2

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Random Search Techniques for Optimal Bidding in Auction Markets

Transcription:

Signaling Games Farhad Ghassemi Abstract - We give an overview of signaling games and their relevant solution concept, perfect Bayesian equilibrium. We introduce an example of signaling games and analyze it. 1 Introduction In the general framework of incomplete information or Bayesian games, it is usually assumed that information is equally distributed among players; i.e. there exists a commonly known probability distribution of the unknown parameter(s) of the game. However, very often in the real life, we are confronted with games in which players have asymmetric information about the unknown parameter of the game; i.e. they have different probability distributions of the unknown parameter. As an example, consider a game in which the unknown parameter of the game can be measured by the players but with different degrees of accuracy. Those players that have access to more accurate methods of measurement are definitely in an advantageous position. In extreme cases of asymmetric information games, one player has complete information about the unknown parameter of the game while others only know it by a probability distribution. In these games, the information is completely one-sided. The informed player, for instance, may be the only player in the game who can have different types and while he knows his type, other do not (e.g. a prospect job applicant knows if he has high or low skills for a job but the employer does not) or the informed player may know something about the state of the world that others do not (e.g. a car dealer knows the quality of the cars he sells but buyers do not). Because of such a total asymmetry of information in one-sided information games, one naturally expects that in many circumstances, the uninformed player may not be even willing to participate in the game. It is therefore common that the informed player sends a signal to the uniformed player to help him decide his action (e.g the job applicant sends a college certificate with a high or low level of credibility to the employer, the car dealer announces different warranty plans for his cars). This signal can be considered as the action of the informed player and because actions speaks louder than words, the uninformed player now has something to base his action on. This is the general structure of signaling games. It should be noted that even after receiving the signal from the informed 1

player, the uninformed player still has many good reasons not to believe in full credibility of such signals. In fact, the whole study of signaling games evolves around the idea of what signals should be sent and how optimally one should react to these signals. It is in this context that deception can be formally defined. Deception strategies are those ones which lead an opponent into a disadvantageous position by a deliberate misrepresentation of the truth. In Section 2, we define a signaling game and an appropriate solution concept called perfect Bayesian equilibrium. The formal presentation of signaling games in this section is mainly adopted from Chapter 8 of [1]. An interested reader can also refer to Chapter 8 of our textbook [2] or Chapter 24 of [3] for some insightful discussions. In Section 3, we introduce an example of signaling games and analyze it. The game introduced in this section is taken from [4]. However, we generalize some of the results given there and study the game as a signaling game whereas in the original paper, only Nash equilibria are found. Finally, in Section 4, we give some concluding remarks and directions for future research. It should be also pointed out that in this brief introduction, we only focus on single-stage signaling games where players only act once. Although the literature is somewhat scattered, multi-stage, repeated and stochastic signaling and onesided information games have also been studied. Of special notes are [5] and [6]. 2 Definition and Solution Concept Figure 1 illustrates the structure of a one-stage signaling game. Player 1 has private information about his type θ in Θ and chooses action (signal) s in S. Player 2 observes s and chooses b in B. Before the game begins, it is common knowledge that player 2 has prior beliefs p( ) about player 1 s type. After observing s, player 2 updates his beliefs about θ according to Bayes rule and base his choice of b on the posterior distribution µ( s) over Θ. A strategy for player 1 prescribes a probability distribution σ 1 ( θ) over actions s for each type θ. A strategy for player 2 prescribes a probability distribution σ 2 ( s) over actions b for each action s. The expected payoff for player 1 with type θ and strategy σ 1 ( θ) when player 2 plays σ 2 ( s) is u 1 (σ 1,σ 2,θ) = σ 1 (s θ)σ 1 (b s)u 1 (s,b,θ), (1) s b and the expected payoff for player 2 conditional on s when he uses strategy σ 2 ( s) and posterior belief µ( s) can be computed as follows u 2 (s,σ 2,µ) = θ = θ µ(θ s)u 2 (s,σ 2 ( s),θ) µ(θ s)σ 2 (b s)u 2 (s,b,θ). b (2) Figure 1 and the discussion above show that a signaling game can be modeled as an imperfect information extensive form game with Bayesian inference. It is 2

Nature Player 1 θ 1 θ 2 θ n Player 2 s m s m s 1 s 2 s 1 s 2 s 2 b m b m b 1 b 2 b 1 b 2 b 2 u 1 (s 1,b 1,θ 1 ) b 1 s 1 b m s m Figure 1: Model of a one-stage signaling game. therefore natural to expect a solution concept for this game combines the ideas of subgame perfection, Bayes-Nash equilibrium and Bayesian inference. Definition 1. A perfect Bayesian equilibrium of a signaling game is a strategy profile σ = (σ 1,σ 2) and posterior beliefs µ( s) such that θ, σ1 argmax u 1 (σ 1,σ2,θ), (3) σ 1 s,σ2 argmax µ(θ s)u 2 (s,σ 2,θ) (4) σ 2 µ(θ s) = p(θ)σ 1(s θ) θ p(θ )σ 1 (s θ ) θ In Definition 1, equation (4) ensures that σ 2 is the Bayes-Nash equilibrium of the subgames of player 2. Equation (3) ensures that σ is the Nash equilibrium of the subgames of each type of player 1. Equation (5) determines how posterior beliefs are obtained. There is one subtlety here and that is we have assumed θ p(θ )σ 1(a 1 θ ) > 0. This assumption holds if player 1 plays actions consistent with his equilibrium. If player 1 plays any action that is not in the support of σ 1, it is a common practice to assign an arbitrary posterior distribution for player 2 s beliefs of player 1 s type. A signaling game may have different perfect Bayesian equilibria. In a separating equilibrium, player 1 sends different signals for each of his types. In other words, he completely reveals his type to player 2. In a pooling equilibrium, player 1 sends the same signal for all his types. In this case he does not reveal any new information to player 2 by sending his signals. There can also be hybrid or semi-separating equilibria in which player 1 randomizes between pooling and separating. It is the structure of the game that determines what types of equilibria exist. In strictly competitive settings, the informed player may want to confuse the uninformed player as much as he can so he may play a pooling strategy. In a less competitive setting, the informed player may want to (5) 3

convey as much information as he can to the uninformed player and therefore he plays a separating strategy. 3 An Example of a Signaling Game Consider the following game. There are n items and two boxes. Let assume n is an odd number. Player 1 places x number of items in box number 1 and the rest of the items in box number 2. Player 2 picks one box and the items inside it become his. Player 1 takes the items in the other box. The appreciation of players for the number of items they own, f(i), is a strictly increasing function but not necessarily linear. What are the optimal strategies for each player? Without loss of generality, we can scale f(i) such that f(0) = 0 and f(n) = 1. Let denote the action of player 1 by θ i where i is between 0 and n and reflects the number of items, player 1 puts in box 1. Let denote the action of player 2 by b j where j is 1 or 2 and indicates the box player 2 picks. The matrix of this game can then be shown as θ 0 θ 1 θ n 1 θ n b 1 1 f(n 1) f(1) 0 b 2 0 f(1) f(n 1) 1 The matrix cells represent the payoff of player 1. We note that this is a constantsum game and therefore the payoff of player 1 is 1 minus the payoff player 2 at each entry. It is obvious that the game does not have any Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. In fact, by any counter clock-wise move, one player can increase his payoff as shown in the game matrix. However, since the game is constantsum, the minmax theorem tells us that the game should have a unique value and any strategy that obtains this value is a Nash equilibrium in mixed strategies. The special structure of the game matrix allows us to quickly find this value. We plot each column expected payoff of player 1 when player 2 randomizes between b 1 and b 2 with probability q assigned to b 1. For each pair of columns i and n + 1 i, the minimum value of player 1 s best response occurs at q = 1/2. Therefore the global minimum also occurs at this point and the optimal strategy for player 2 as a minimizer is (1/2,1/2). Player 1 must select a pair of column actions that maximizes his payoff at q = 1/2. Hence he must randomize between columns i and n + 1 i for which f(i ) + f(n + 1 i ) > f(i) + f(n + 1 i) for all i s. This strategy means if, for instance, the items are a collection of stamps and player 1 truly prefers to have all or none of them, then he should only randomize between these two choices. We now extend this game to a signaling game. In the new game, player 1 still places a certain number of items in box 1 and the rest in box 2. However, he also requires to partially open both boxes and show the content of the boxes to player 2. We assume that the number of items that are revealed to player 2 is always less than half of n. Otherwise the selection is easy for player 2. We also assume if the box is not empty, at least one item is revealed and always unequal 4

numbers of items are revealed. We ask again what the optimal strategies are player 1 and player 2. To keep it tractable, we assume n = 3. In the terminology of Section 2, the types in this game are θ 1 = (0,3),θ 2 = (1,2), θ 3 = (2,1), and θ 4 = (3,0), where the first digit indicates the number of items in box 1 and the second digit indicates the number of items in box 2. Signals are s 1 = (0,1) and s 2 = (1,0), where the first digit indicates the number of items which are revealed in box 1 and the second digit indicates the number of items that are revealed in box 2. We assume the prior beliefs of player 2 for types of player 1 is (1/4,1/4,1/4,1/4). Finding an equilibrium for this game then involves finding the following probabilities: σ 1(s 1 θ 1 ) = 1 = p 1 σ 1(s 2 θ 1 ) = 0 = 1 p 1 σ 1(s 1 θ 2 ) = p 2 σ 1(s 2 θ 2 ) = 1 p 2 σ 1(s 1 θ 3 ) = p 3 σ 1(s 2 θ 3 ) = 1 p 3 σ 1(s 1 θ 4 ) = 0 = p 4 σ 1(s 2 θ 4 ) = 1 = 1 p 4 σ2(b 1 s 1 ) = q 1 σ2(b 2 s 1 ) = 1 q 1 σ2(b 1 s 2 ) = q 2 σ2(b 2 s 2 ) = 1 q 2. We note that when type is θ 1 or θ 4, it is not possible to randomize between signals, therefore there remain 4 parameters (p 2,p 3,q 1,q 2 ) that must be assigned to have an equilibrium. We next note that the belief update equations are as follows µ(θ 1 s 1 ) = 0 µ 1 1(θ 1 s 2 ) = 3 p 2 p 3 p 2 µ(θ 2 s 1 ) = µ(θ 2 s 2 ) = 1 p 2 1 + p 2 + p 3 3 p 2 p 3 p 3 µ(θ 3 s 1 ) = µ(θ 3 s 2 ) = 1 p 3 1 + p 2 + p 3 3 p 2 p 3 1 µ(θ 4 s 1 ) = µ 1 + p 2 + p 1(θ 1 s 2 ) = 0. 3 We next note that the immediate payoff for both players does not rely on the signals sent. In other words, u 1 (s i,b 1,θ k ) = f(n + 1 k) and u 1 (s i,b 2,θ k ) = f(k 1). Therefore player 1 s expected payoff does not directly rely on how he personally randomizes his signals. Two reasonable choices, however, are to pick p 2 = p 3 = 1 or p 2 = p 3 = 0. These choices give maximum uncertainty on one side of posterior beliefs of player 2. For instance with the first choice, the posterior beliefs of player 2 are µ( s 1 ) = (0,1/3,1/3,1/3) and µ( s 2 ) = (1,0,0,0). As for player 2 s optimal strategy, he has to maximize his payoff with respect to q 1 and q 2 for each signal and given values of p 2 and p 3. We outline the steps for signal s 1 and p 2 = p 3 = 1. Player 2 s expected payoff in this case is 5

u 2 (s 1,σ 2,µ) = = = µ(θ j s 1 )[q 1 u 2 (s 1,b 1,θ j ) + (1 q 1 )u 2 (s 1,b 2,θ j ) µ(θ j s 1 )[q 1 f(j 1) + (1 q 1 )f(n j + 1) µ(θ j s 1 )q 1 (f(j 1) f(n j + 1)) + µ(θ j s 1 )f(n j + 1). The last line of equation (6) indicates that maximization with respect to q 1 only concerns with the first sum. If this sum is positive, then q 1 = 1, if it is negative, q 1 = 0 and if it is zero, q 1 can be chosen arbitrarily. We therefore expand the first sum (6) p 2 µ(θ j s 1 )q 1 (f(j 1) f(n j + 1)) = [f(1) f(2)] 1 + p 2 + p 3 p 3 + [f(2) f(1)] 1 + p 2 + p 3 1 + [1 0]. 1 + p 2 + p 3 (7) And since p 2 = p 3 = 1, the above sum is equal to 1/3 > 0. As a result, q 1 should be one. This means if player 2 sees an item in box 1, he must select that box and otherwise box 2. 4 Conclusion We provided a brief overview of signaling games. We also investigated the set of strategy solutions for one type of signaling games. In general, because of a cycle, it is harder to find the equilibria of incomplete information extensive form games than the equilibria of complete information extensive form games. One cannot anymore just apply backward induction because the beliefs are updated with the strategies and the strategies are optimal given the beliefs. The example game provided here can be further investigated in several different directions. The whole set of equilibria can be found and the meaning of each one is explored. The game can be further made complicated by considering other non-uniform priors or assigning a charge to player 2 for partially observing the boxes. References [1] D. Fudenberg and J. Tirole, Game Theory. MIT Press, 1991. 6

[2] Y. Shoham and K. Leyton-Brown, Multi Agent Systems. Draft Edition, 2005. [3] P. K. Dutta, Strategies and Games: Theory and Practice. MIT Press, 1999. [4] J. P. Hespanha, Y. Ateskan, and H. Kizilocak, Deception in non-cooperative games with partial information, in Proc. of the 2nd DARPA-JFACC Symp. on Advances in Enterprise Control, 2000. [5] R. J. Aumann and M. Maschler, Repeated Games with Incomplete Information. MIT Press, 1995. [6] S. Sorin, A First Course on Zero-Sum Repeated Games. Springer-Verlag, 2002. 7