Handout on Rationalizability and IDSDS 1

Similar documents
EconS Games with Incomplete Information II and Auction Theory

EconS Signalling Games II

EconS Micro Theory I 1 Recitation #7 - Competitive Markets

Cheap Talk Games with three types

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

EconS Micro Theory I 1 Recitation #9 - Monopoly

Strategic Pre-Commitment

Game Theory Tutorial 3 Answers

Test 1. ECON3161, Game Theory. Tuesday, September 25 th

Dynamic games with incomplete information

A Systematic Presentation of Equilibrium Bidding Strategies to Undergradudate Students

Auction Theory for Undergrads

Rationalizable Strategies

Auction Theory - An Introduction

Some Notes on Timing in Games

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Problem Set 2 Answers

MIDTERM 1 SOLUTIONS 10/16/2008

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Expectations & Randomization Normal Form Games Dominance Iterated Dominance. Normal Form Games & Dominance

Francesco Nava Microeconomic Principles II EC202 Lent Term 2010

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

SI 563 Homework 3 Oct 5, Determine the set of rationalizable strategies for each of the following games. a) X Y X Y Z

1 R. 2 l r 1 1 l2 r 2

These notes essentially correspond to chapter 13 of the text.

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

(a) (5 points) Suppose p = 1. Calculate all the Nash Equilibria of the game. Do/es the equilibrium/a that you have found maximize social utility?

EconS Oligopoly - Part 3

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1

Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts. Game in strategic form has following elements. Player set N. (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i.

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Social Choice

Answers to Problem Set 4

Problem Set 5 Answers

Economics 171: Final Exam

Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part 1

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2009 examination. 2008/2009 syllabus

MS&E 246: Lecture 2 The basics. Ramesh Johari January 16, 2007

Noncooperative Oligopoly

Macroeconomics 4 Notes on Diamond-Dygvig Model and Jacklin

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

CHAPTER 9 Nash Equilibrium 1-1

1 Intro to game theory

Rationalizing Time Inconsistent Behavior: The Case of Late Payments

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

ECON Micro Foundations

Econ 277A: Economic Development I. Final Exam (06 May 2012)

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Comprehensive Exam

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

Microeconomics 3. Economics Programme, University of Copenhagen. Spring semester Lars Peter Østerdal. Week 17

Answer for Homework 2: Modern Macroeconomics I

ECON Financial Economics

January 26,

Introduction to Game Theory

The role of asymmetric information

1. If the consumer has income y then the budget constraint is. x + F (q) y. where is a variable taking the values 0 or 1, representing the cases not

Advanced Microeconomics

Simon Fraser University Spring 2014

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Simon Fraser University Fall Econ 302 D200 Final Exam Solution Instructor: Songzi Du Wednesday December 16, 2015, 8:30 11:30 AM

Some Problems. 3. Consider the Cournot model with inverse demand p(y) = 9 y and marginal cost equal to 0.

Collusion in a One-Period Insurance Market with Adverse Selection

2 Maximizing pro ts when marginal costs are increasing

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2011 Examination. 2010/2011 Syllabus ONLY

EconS Consumer Theory: Additional Topics

For on-line Publication Only ON-LINE APPENDIX FOR. Corporate Strategy, Conformism, and the Stock Market. June 2017

Equilibrium Asset Returns

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Lecture 6 Applications of Static Games of Incomplete Information

Exercises on chapter 4

Practice Questions Chapters 9 to 11

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HOMEWORK #7 ANSWER KEY

Fiscal policy and minimum wage for redistribution: an equivalence result. Abstract

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Spring 2017 Final Exam

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Notes for Section: Week 7

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 2. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

ECO 5341 (Section 2) Spring 2016 Midterm March 24th 2016 Total Points: 100

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

On social and market sanctions in deterring non compliance in pollution standards

EconS Supply and Demand

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Advanced Microeconomics Final Exam Winter 2011/2012

Cooperative Ph.D. Program in Agricultural and Resource Economics, Economics, and Finance QUALIFYING EXAMINATION IN MICROECONOMICS

(a) Describe the game in plain english and find its equivalent strategic form.

Money in OLG Models. Econ602, Spring The central question of monetary economics: Why and when is money valued in equilibrium?

Games of Incomplete Information

Technical Appendix to Long-Term Contracts under the Threat of Supplier Default

An introduction on game theory for wireless networking [1]

1 Modern Macroeconomics

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

Yao s Minimax Principle

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies

Econ 323 Microeconomic Theory. Practice Exam 2 with Solutions

Transcription:

EconS 424 - Strategy and Game Theory Handout on Rationalizability and ISS 1 1 Introduction In this handout, we will discuss an extension of best response functions: Rationalizability. Best response: As we have already covered, we know that we can de ne s i to be a best response of player i to a pro le of strategies s i played by his opponents, s i (s 1 ; s 2 ; :::; s I ), if it yields a larger utility than any other of his available strategies s 0 i 2 S i, that is v i (s i ; s i ) v i (s 0 i; s i ) for all s 0 i 2 S i Rationalizability: A rationalizable strategy is a strategy that is a best response for a player, given some beliefs about other players s behavior. We can de ne a belief as some probability, p, that a player plays a particular strategy. Formally, a strategy is rationalizable if s i 2 Best Response function conditioned on beliefs z } { BR i (p) which says that strategy s i 2 S i is a best response function given beliefs p. We will apply rationalizability in order to eliminate strategies that are never a best response (i.e., that are not rationalizable as best responses for any beliefs that player i might sustain about his opponent s behavior). Strictly dominant strategies: A strictly dominant strategy s i 2 S i for player i yields a strictly larger payo than all of his available strategies s 0 i 2 S i, and does so for all possible strategies played by his opponents. Formally, v i (s i ; s i ) > v i (s 0 i; s i ) for all s 0 i 2 S i, and for all s i 2 S i, s 0 i 6= s i When this happens, we can assign a zero probability to our beliefs that this strategy will be a best response for player i, and it will therefore not be rationalizable. E ectively, we can delete a strictly dominated strategy from a normal form game, as it will never be played by a rational player. Recall that eliminating all strictly dominated strategies for all players is referred to as ISS. In the next examples, we explore settings in which applying ISS provides the same set of equilibrium predictions as applying rationalizability (as in the rst example), and in which settings 1 Felix unoz-garcia, School of Economic Sciences, Washington State niversity, Pullman, WA 99164-6210. E- mail: fmunoz@wsu.edu. 1

the two equilibrium concepts di er (i.e., and analyze which one o ers more precise equilibrium predictions); as illustrated in the second example. 2 Examples First example. We will rst nd equilibrium predictions applying ISS, and then repeat the process, but this time applying rationalizability (i.e., eliminating those strategies that are not best responses). R 2, 0 2, 0 3, 1 2, 1 2, 1 ISS. As can be seen in the gure, strategy R is never chosen by player 2: it yields a payo of -1 regardless of the strategy (row) selected by player 1, while selecting either L or C yields payo s larger than -1. Hence, no matter what strategy player 1 plays, picking either strategy L or C strictly dominates strategy R. Hence, we say that strategy R is strictly dominated and can be thus deleted from this game (since a rational player 2 would never play it). Our new reduced form game is shown in the next gure. 2, 0 2, 0 We now examine whether player 1 has strictly dominated strategies we could delete from the reduced-form matrix. nfortunately, we cannot nd any strictly dominated strategies for player 1. Hence, the application of ISS would leave us with the above reduced-form matrix, with six di erent strategy pro les, as the most precise equilibrium prediction we can provide, i.e., f(; L); (; C); (; L); (; C); (; L); (; C)g 2

Rationalizability. What about rationalizability? oes it provide any more precise equilibrium predictions? We can start by investigating whether there are any conditions in which picking strategy is the best response for player 1, that is, we need to determine if strategy is rationalizable. Recall that a rationalizable strategy is a strategy that is the best response for a player, given some beliefs about the other players. In our game, let s de ne p as the probability (belief) that player 2 is going to play strategy L. This would imply that the probability that player 2 plays strategy C will be 1 p (since probabilities add up to 1). Putting these value into our game, we obtain in the next gure p 1 p 2, 0 2, 0 If player 2 is playing each of his strategies, L and C, with a probabilities p and 1 then player 1 can calculate his expected utility for each of his own strategies. p, respectively, This is done by multiplying each outcome for player 1 s strategy by the probability it occurs, then adding it up. s expected utilities are then Expected utility of player 1 when he plays z } { E 1 () = plays L plays C z} { z} { 2 p + 2 (1 p) = 2 E 1 () = 3 p + 0 (1 p) = 3p E 1 () = 0 p + 3 (1 p) = 3 3p We can graph all of these expected utilities, as shown in the next gure. 3

E 1 3 E 1 ( ) = 3p 2 E 1 ( ) = 2 0 ⅓ ⅔ 1 E 1 ( ) = 3 3p p For strategy to be rationalizable, we must be able to nd at least one value for p such that the expected utility of playing strategy is at least as good as the expected utilities of playing both strategies and. Formally, we need E 1 () E 1 () and E 1 () E 1 () at the same time for at least one value of p. Solving for these inequalities, we obtain E 1 () E 1 () 2 3p () p 2 3 E 1 () E 1 () 2 3 3p () p 1 3 Hence, any belief p that satis es 1 3 p 2 3 will make player 1 s best response to choose strategy (We can also see this on our graph where the line depicting E 1 () is above both of the other lines). For example, if player 1 believed player 2 would play strategy L 50% of the time (p = 0:5), then his expected utilities would be E 1 () = 2 E 1 () = 3 (0:5) = 1:5 E 1 () = 3 3 (0:5) = 1:5 which clearly shows that choosing strategy is player 1 s best response when p = 0:5. Hence, since there exist beliefs for player 1 where strategy is his best response, we say that strategy is rationalizable. We can also represent player 1 s best response function as a function of his beliefs: 8 >< if 1 3 p 2 3 BR 1 (p) = if p >: 2 3 if p 2 3 4

This means that all strategies for player 1 are rationalizable, and the set of rationalizable strategies is the same in this problem as given by ISS, meaning our equilibrium prediction cannot be re ned any further. Second example. Let s look at one more example. Consider the game depicted in the following gure. p 1 p 2, 0 2, 0 5, 1 5, 1 ISS. First, note that the application of ISS doesn t have a bite, yielding the six possible outcomes f(; L); (; C); (; L); (; C); (; L); (; C)g Rationalizability. However, the application of rationalizability has more predictive power (more bite ) than ISS. Let us determine if strategy is rationalizable. This time, however, player 1 s payo from strategies and is much higher. As before, we assign probability p to player 2 playing strategy L and calculate player 1 s expected utilities. E 1 () = 2 p + 2 (1 p) = 2 E 1 () = 5 p + 0 (1 p) = 5p E 1 () = 0 p + 5 (1 p) = 5 5p Graphing these values, 5

E 1 5 E 1 ( ) = 5p 2 E 1 ( ) = 2 0 1 E 1 ( ) = 5 5p p Like before, we need to nd values p for which E 1 () E 1 () and E 1 () E 1 (). Solving for these inequalities, yields E 1 () E 1 () 2 5p () p 2 5 E 1 () E 1 () 2 5 5p () p 3 5 In this case, there does not exist a value for p that is both less than 2 5 and greater than 3 5 at the same time (As we can see on our graph, there is no point in which the line for E 1 () is above the other two lines). Hence, there are no beliefs for player 1 in which strategy is the best response and thus strategy is not rationalizable. In this situation, player 1 will never choose strategy under any circumstances and we can delete it from our game, providing the following reduced form matrix as shown in the next gure. 5, 1 5, 1 At this point, we cannot delete any other strategies for player 1 or 2 (as never being best responses). In particular, for player 1, is a best response to L, while is a best response to C. Similarly, for player 2 L is a best response to, and C is a best response to. While we cannot eliminate any further strategies, in this case, rationalizability gives a more precise equilibrium 6

prediction than ISS, namely f(; L); (; C); (; L); (; C)g 7