Lecture 8: Asset pricing

Similar documents
Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

1 No-arbitrage pricing

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models

3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

Pricing theory of financial derivatives

Lecture 2: Stochastic Discount Factor

ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B. Lecture 7

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

No-arbitrage Pricing Approach and Fundamental Theorem of Asset Pricing

1 Asset Pricing: Replicating portfolios

General Equilibrium under Uncertainty

Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Fundamental Theorems of Asset Pricing. 3.1 Arbitrage and risk neutral probability measures

Problem set 5. Asset pricing. Markus Roth. Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz. Juli 5, 2010

ECON 815. Uncertainty and Asset Prices

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

1 Dynamic programming

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

LECTURE NOTES 3 ARIEL M. VIALE

( 0) ,...,S N ,S 2 ( 0)... S N S 2. N and a portfolio is created that way, the value of the portfolio at time 0 is: (0) N S N ( 1, ) +...

1 The empirical relationship and its demise (?)

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Basics of Asset Pricing. Ali Nejadmalayeri

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Introduction to Game Theory Evolution Games Theory: Replicator Dynamics

Fin 501: Asset Pricing Fin 501:

Economics 8106 Macroeconomic Theory Recitation 2

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

PhD Qualifier Examination

Problem Set 3. Thomas Philippon. April 19, Human Wealth, Financial Wealth and Consumption

Exam Quantitative Finance (35V5A1)

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Homework 3: Asset Pricing

Slides III - Complete Markets

Economia Financiera Avanzada

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Optimizing Portfolios

Finance: Lecture 4 - No Arbitrage Pricing Chapters of DD Chapter 1 of Ross (2005)

UNIVERSITY OF OSLO. Faculty of Mathematics and Natural Sciences

Financial Economics: Risk Sharing and Asset Pricing in General Equilibrium c

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Macroeconomics Sequence, Block I. Introduction to Consumption Asset Pricing

Graduate Macro Theory II: Two Period Consumption-Saving Models

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

ECON 581. Introduction to Arrow-Debreu Pricing and Complete Markets. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Spring, 2016

Mathematics in Finance

Asset Pricing and Equity Premium Puzzle. E. Young Lecture Notes Chapter 13

GMM Estimation. 1 Introduction. 2 Consumption-CAPM

LECTURE NOTES 10 ARIEL M. VIALE

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

A No-Arbitrage Theorem for Uncertain Stock Model

CHAPTER 2 Concepts of Financial Economics and Asset Price Dynamics

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Homework # 8 - [Due on Wednesday November 1st, 2017]

MATH3075/3975 FINANCIAL MATHEMATICS TUTORIAL PROBLEMS

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Yao s Minimax Principle

Microeconomics III Final Exam SOLUTIONS 3/17/11. Muhamet Yildiz

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

Financial Mathematics III Theory summary

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

One-Period Valuation Theory

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

Dynamic Macroeconomics: Problem Set 2

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d

Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

A model for a large investor trading at market indifference prices

An Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing Model

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

ON INTEREST RATE POLICY AND EQUILIBRIUM STABILITY UNDER INCREASING RETURNS: A NOTE

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Finance: A Quantitative Introduction Chapter 7 - part 2 Option Pricing Foundations

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

WITH SKETCH ANSWERS. Postgraduate Certificate in Finance Postgraduate Certificate in Economics and Finance

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Macroeconomics and finance

Chapter 8: CAPM. 1. Single Index Model. 2. Adding a Riskless Asset. 3. The Capital Market Line 4. CAPM. 5. The One-Fund Theorem

Period State of the world: n/a A B n/a A B Endowment ( income, output ) Y 0 Y1 A Y1 B Y0 Y1 A Y1. p A 1+r. 1 0 p B.

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

Dynamic Asset Pricing Model

Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics. Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle

Real Business Cycles (Solution)

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Transcription:

BURNABY SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY BRITISH COLUMBIA Paul Klein Office: WMC 3635 Phone: (778) 782-9391 Email: paul klein 2@sfu.ca URL: http://paulklein.ca/newsite/teaching/483.php Economics 483 Advanced Topics in Macroeconomics Spring 2014 Lecture 8: Asset pricing 1 Facts According to Aiyagari (1993), the average annual real rate of return on 3-month U.S. Treasury bills in the post-war period has been about 1 percent. On stocks, this rate of return has been about 6 percent (4 percent in the last 200 years). Thus the equity premium was about 5 percentage points. According to Jagannathan et al. (2000), the equity premium was about 7 percentage points 1926-70, but only 0.7 of a percentage point 1970-99. See also http://pages.stern.nyu.edu/ adamodar. This set of lecture notes will develop the consumption-based capital asset pricing model (C- CAPM) which is based on the concept of competitive equilibrium. A subsequent set of lecture notes will investigate if it can account for the above facts. It can t unless we focus on the last 30 years only. 2 Prequel to C-CAPM: no-arbitrage pricing How far can we get in determining the correct price of assets by just assuming that there are no arbitrage opportunities? Notice that this is a weaker assumption than (competitive) equilibrium. Surprisingly far, as it turns out. In particular, we can work out how to price derivatives claims that are defined in terms of other securities, e.g. options. 1

2.1 A two period model Let t = 0, 1 (today and tomorrow). There are N securities. The price of security n at time t is denoted by St n. We write S t = St 1 St 2. S N t. S 0 is deterministic, but S 1 is stochastic. We write S1(ω) 1 S S 1 (ω) = 1(ω) 2. S1 N (ω) where ω Ω = {ω 1, ω 2,..., ω M }. Now define the matrix D via S1(ω 1 1 ) S1(ω 1 2 )... S1(ω 1 M ) D = S 2. 1(ω 1 )...... N M........ S N 1 (ω 1 )...... S N 1 (ω M ) [ = d 1 d 2... d M ]. Definition. A portfolio is a vector h R N. Interpretation: h n is the number of securities of type n purchased at t = 0. Remark: Fractional holdings as well as short positions (h n < 0) are allowed. The value of a portfolio h at time t is given by N V t (h) = h n St n = h T S t. Definition. A vector h R N is called an arbitrage portfolio if V 0 (h) < 0 2 n=1

and V 1 (h) 0 for all ω Ω. Remark. We can weaken the condition for all ω Ω to with probability one if we want but in this context that wouldn t add much. Theorem. Let securities prices S be as above. Then there exists no arbitrage portfolio iff there exists a z R M + such that S 0 = Dz. Remark. This means that today s (period 0 s) price vector has to lie in the convex cone spanned by tomorrow s (period 1 s) possible prices vectors. (A convex cone is a subset C of a vector space X such that for any x, y C and α 0 we have (αx) C and (x + y) C. ) Proof. Absence of arbitrage opportunities means that the following system of inequalities has no solution for h. { h T S 0 < 0 h T d j 0 for each j = 1, 2,..., M. Geometric interpretation: there is no hyperplane that separates S 0 from the columns of D. Such a hyperplane would have an arbitrage portfolio as a normal vector. Now according to Farkas lemma, the non existence of such a normal vector is equivalent to the existence of non negative numbers z 1, z 2,..., z M such that S 0 = M z j d j j=1 or, equivalently, S 0 = Dz where z R M +. A popular interpretation of the result S 0 = Dz is the following (but beware of over interpretation). Define where q i = z i β β = M z i. i=1 3

Then q can be thought of as a probability distribution on Ω and we may conclude the following. Theorem. The market S is arbitrage free iff there is a scalar β > 0 and probabilities (nonnegative numbers that sum to 1) q 1, q 2,..., q m such that S 0 = βe Q [S 1 ] = β[q 1 S 1 (ω 1 ) + q 2 S 1 (ω 2 ) +... + q M S 1 (ω M )] and we call the numbers {q i } martingale probabilities (for reasons that are not immediately obvious in this context). Economically speaking, the q i s are state prices. Relative prices of $1 in state i. Arrow Debreu prices. Yet another approach is to define a so called pricing kernel. For an arbitrage free market S, there exists a (scalar) random variable m : Ω R such that such that S 0 = E[m S 1 ] where the expectation is now taken under the objective measure P. Provided the outcomes ω i all obtain with strictly positive probabilities, we have m(ω i ) = βq({ω i })/P ({ω i }) = βq i /p i. where the p i s are the objective probabilities. So the pricing kernel takes care both of discounting and the change of probability measure. 2.1.1 Pricing contingent claims Definition. A contingent claim is a mapping X : Ω R. We represent it as a vector x R M via the formula x i = X(ω i ). Interpretation: the contract x entitles the owner to $x i in state ω i. Theorem. Let S be an arbitrage free market. Then there exist β, q such that if each contingent claim x is priced according to π 0 [X] = βq T x = βe Q [X] (1) then the market consisting of all contingent claims is arbitrage free. If the market is complete (in this case: for each contingent claim x there exists a portfolio h such that D T h = x), then the β and the Q are unique, and (1) represents the unique way of pricing each contingent claim so as to avoid arbitrage. 4

Notice that we can equivalently write (1) as π 0 [X] = [m X] (2) where m is a non-negative random variable. Under complete markets, this m is unique. 3 Equilibrium asset pricing In this Section I present the consumption-based capital asset pricing model (C-CAPM). 1 We will be trying to account for the equity premium. In so doing, we will discover that volatile or unpredictable returns as such is irrelevant for the equilibrium rate of return: what matters is the covariance of payoffs with consumption. 3.1 The environment People live for two periods. The population is constant, N(t) = N and endowment profiles are constant across individuals and across time, ω h t = [ω 1, ω 2 ]. There are two assets in this economy: private lending, associated with a gross real interest rate of r(t) and land which yields an uncertain crop d(t). There are A units of land available, and the crop behaves as follows: d(t) = d + ε t where { +σ with probability 1/2 ε t = σ with probability 1/2 The random variables ε t are independent. We assume that everyone has the same utility function and that it is separable across time: u h (c h t (t), c h t (t + 1)) = u(c h t (t)) + βu(c h t (t + 1)). We also assume that, in the presence of uncertainty, people maximize expected utility. What does this assumption amount to? Well, von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) showed that, 1 This material is based on lectures notes by David Domeij at the Stockholm School of Economics and Kjetil Storesletten at the University of Oslo. 5

under some very reasonable (but apparently counterfactual see Machina (1987)) assumptions, choice under uncertainty can be represented as maximization of expected utility. A typical individual h born in period t maximizes E [ u(c h t (t)) + βu(c h t (t + 1)) ] subject to c h t (t) ω 1 l h (t) p(t)a h (t) c h t (t + 1) ω 2 + r(t)l h (t) Manipulating the first-order conditions for optimal choice, we get the fundamental asset pricing equations. [ ] 1 u r(t) = βe (c h t (t + 1)) u (c h t (t)) { } u (c h t (t + 1)) p(t) = βe [p(t + 1) + d + ε(t + 1)] u (c h t (t)) (3) (4) Notice that the random variable βu (c h t (t + 1))/u (c h t (t)) works as a pricing kernel here! Since all individuals born in a given period are identical (they have the same preferences and endowments), we must have, in a (symmetric) competitive equilibrium, l h (t) = 0 and a h (t) = A N. What remains to do is to find prices r(t) and p(t) that satisfy our fundamental asset pricing equations and also our market clearing conditions above. Since the environment is stationary, we look for a stationary equilibrium where p(t) = p and r(t) = r. The result is { } 1 u r = βe (ω 2 + [p + d + ε(t + 1)]A/N u (ω 1 pa/n) (5) and { u (ω 2 + [p + d + ε(t + 1)]A/N p = βe u (ω 1 pa/n } [p + d + ε(t + 1)] (6) 6

3.1.1 Imposing further restrictions In order to get sharper results, let s make some more assumptions about preferences, crops and endowments. 3.1.1.1 Risk neutral agents Risk neutral preferences means that the utility function is linear in consumption so that u (c) = α. Then (5) and (6) become and 1 r = β p = β[p + d]. These equations say that the risk free rate r and the average rate of return on land (p + d)/p are the same: 1/β. Alternatively, define the average equity premium via { p + d + ε(t + 1) ˆr = E p In the risk neutral case, this is zero. } r. 3.1.1.2 Risk averse agents A much more interesting case is if u is strictly concave. Specifically, we will assume u(c) = ln c so that u (c) = 1 c. To further simplify matters, assume ω 2 = 0 and that A = N. Then our equilibrium conditions become { } 1 r = βe ω 1 p [p + d + ε(t + 1)] and p = β (ω 1 p). 7

Solving for p from the second condition, we get p = β 1 + β ω 1. Substituting this into the first equilibrium condition, we get r = p + d p σ 2 p(p + d). Notice that if σ = 0 then r = (p+d)/p as in the risk neutral case. Notice also that the expected equity premium is ˆr = (1 + β) 2 ω 1 (βω 1 + (1 + β)d) σ2 which evidently is decreasing in d and increasing in σ. References Aiyagari, S. R. (1993). Explaining financial market facts: The importance of incomplete markets and transactions. Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review 17 (1), 17 31. Jagannathan, R., E. R. McGrattan, and A. Scherbina (2000). The declining U.S. equity premium. Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review 24 (4), 3 19. Machina, M. J. (1987). Choice under uncertainty: Problems solved and unsolved. Journal of Economic Perspectives 1 (1), 121 154. von Neumann, J. and O. Morgenstern (1944). Princeton University Press. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. 8

Appendix : Farkas lemma Proposition (Farkas lemma). If A m n is a real matrix and if b R m, then exactly one of the following statements is true. 1. Ax = b for some x R n + 2. (y T A) R n + and y T b < 0 for some y R m. Proof. In what follows we will sometimes say that x 0 when x is a vector. This means that all the components are non negative. To prove that (1) implies that not (2), suppose that Ax = b for some x 0. Then y T Ax = y T b. But then (2) is not true. If it were, then y T A 0 and hence y T Ax 0. But then y T b 0. Hence (1) implies not (2). Next we show that not (1) implies (2). Let X be the convex cone spanned by the columns a 1, a 2,..., a n of A, i.e. { } n X = a R n : a = λ i a i ; λ i 0, i = 1, 2,..., n. i=1 Suppose there is no x 0 such that Ax = b. Then b / X. Since X is closed and convex, the Separating Hyperplane Theorem says that there is a y R m such that y T a > y T b for all a X. Since 0 X, y T 0 > y T b and consequently y T b < 0. Now suppose (to yield a contradiction) that not y T A 0. Then there is a column in A, say a k, such that y T a k < 0. Since X is a convex cone and a k X, we have (αa k ) X for all α 0. But by the (absurd) supposition, for sufficiently large α, we have y T (αa k ) = α(y T a k ) < y T b, and this contradicts separation so the supposition cannot be true. Thus y T a i 0 for all columns a i of A, i.e. y T A 0. Separating Hyperplane Theorem. Let X R n be closed and convex, and suppose y / X. Then there is an a R and an h R n such that h T x > a > h T y for all x X. Proof. Omitted. 9