(Appendix to: When Promoters Like Scalpers) Global strategic complementarity in a global games setting

Similar documents
Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Answers To Chapter 6. Review Questions

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

ECON/MGMT 115. Industrial Organization

Foundational Preliminaries: Answers to Within-Chapter-Exercises

Income distribution and the allocation of public agricultural investment in developing countries

``Liquidity requirements, liquidity choice and financial stability by Diamond and Kashyap. Discussant: Annette Vissing-Jorgensen, UC Berkeley

Zhiling Guo and Dan Ma

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

(1 p)(1 ε)+pε p(1 ε)+(1 p)ε. ε ((1 p)(1 ε) + pε). This is indeed the case since 1 ε > ε (in turn, since ε < 1/2). QED

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

OPTIMAL BLUFFING FREQUENCIES

Sabotage in Teams. Matthias Kräkel. University of Bonn. Daniel Müller 1. University of Bonn

Correct (and misleading) arguments for using market based pollution control policies

ECON Micro Foundations

$1,000 1 ( ) $2,500 2,500 $2,000 (1 ) (1 + r) 2,000

Haiyang Feng College of Management and Economics, Tianjin University, Tianjin , CHINA

Static Games and Cournot. Competition

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure

Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations

Technical Appendix for: The Effect of Third-Party Funding of Plaintiffs on Settlement. Andrew F. Daughety and Jennifer F. Reinganum.

Information Processing and Limited Liability

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Econometrica Supplementary Material

Self-Fulfilling Credit Market Freezes

not to be republished NCERT Chapter 2 Consumer Behaviour 2.1 THE CONSUMER S BUDGET

Problem Set 1. Debraj Ray Economic Development, Fall 2002

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Dynamic signaling and market breakdown

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010

We will make several assumptions about these preferences:

Corporate Finance - Yossi Spiegel

In this appendix, we examine extensions of the model in Section A and present the proofs for the

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals.

LINES AND SLOPES. Required concepts for the courses : Micro economic analysis, Managerial economy.

Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion?

Bubble and Depression in Dynamic Global Games

Y t )+υ t. +φ ( Y t. Y t ) Y t. α ( r t. + ρ +θ π ( π t. + ρ

Chapter 7 Review questions

Game Theory: Global Games. Christoph Schottmüller

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9

Strategic complementarity of information acquisition in a financial market with discrete demand shocks

Supplementary Material: Strategies for exploration in the domain of losses

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version)

Best Reply Behavior. Michael Peters. December 27, 2013

Global Games and Illiquidity

Auction is a commonly used way of allocating indivisible

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions.

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Math 135: Answers to Practice Problems

Lecture 5. Xavier Gabaix. March 4, 2004

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Moral Hazard Example. 1. The Agent s Problem. contract C = (w, w) that offers the same wage w regardless of the project s outcome.

Credible Threats, Reputation and Private Monitoring.

Chapter 10 THE PARTIAL EQUILIBRIUM COMPETITIVE MODEL. Copyright 2005 by South-Western, a division of Thomson Learning. All rights reserved.

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

The Clock-Proxy Auction: A Practical Combinatorial Auction Design

Background. I Established in US in 1938 THE MINIMUM WAGE

Technical Appendix to Long-Term Contracts under the Threat of Supplier Default

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments

Can Stock Price Manipulation be Prevented by Granting More Freedom to Manipulators

Ilkka Kiema, Research Coordinator, Labour Institute for Economic Research

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

University of Toronto Department of Economics ECO 204 Summer 2013 Ajaz Hussain TEST 1 SOLUTIONS GOOD LUCK!

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011

New product launch: herd seeking or herd. preventing?

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HOMEWORK #7 ANSWER KEY

Development Microeconomics Tutorial SS 2006 Johannes Metzler Credit Ray Ch.14

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

PhD Qualifier Examination

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

Self-Fulfilling Credit Market Freezes

Saving, Investment, and the Financial System

Global Games and Illiquidity

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

University of California, Davis Date: June 24, PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE. Answer four questions (out of five)

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Fall 2013 D. Romer

Microeconomics III Final Exam SOLUTIONS 3/17/11. Muhamet Yildiz

A Model of Safe Asset Determination

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

A non-robustness in the order structure of the equilibrium set in lattice games

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix

Price Theory of Two-Sided Markets

Financial Intermediation, Loanable Funds and The Real Sector

= quantity of ith good bought and consumed. It

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion

Question 1: Productivity, Output and Employment (20 Marks)

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

Lecture Notes on Adverse Selection and Signaling

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium

Transcription:

(Appendix to: When Promoters Like Scalpers) Global strategic complementarity in a global games setting LarryKarpandJeffreyM.Perloff Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics 207 Giannini Hall University of California Berkeley CA 94720 email: karp@are.berkeley.edu perloff@are.berkeley.edu March 4, 2004

Here we describe the relation between our (imperfect information) models with and without scalpers, and the models in two other papers that relax the assumption of global strategic complementarity in a global games setting. In the absence of scalpers, actions are global strategic complements; the advantage of taking a particular action increases with the measure of other agents who take the same action. When scalpers can enter, actions are strategic complements or substitutes depending on the measure of agents who take the action; in other words, actions are not global strategic complements. In Goldstein and Pauzner (2003) s model of bank runs, actions are one-sided strategic complements, a term that is defined below. Karp, Lee, and Mason (2003) study a model in which actions could be either strategic complements or substitutes. The four panels in Figure 1 show for four different games the advantage of taking a particular action, as a function of the measure (α) of agents taking that action, holding fixed the value of a payoff-relevant variable γ and other parameters (such as the first period price in the ticket game, and the first period interest rate in the bank-run game). We denote the advantage of taking the action as. (This function is conditional on α and γ and is therefore distinct from the function A anexpectationoverγ and α used in the text. For example, in the absence of scalpers, = B 0 γp h p 1 ;withscalpers, = B γp h p 1.) Figure 1a graphs (α; γ.p 1 ) (the advantage of waiting) in the ticket game when there are no scalpers, taking as given γ and the firstperiodprice. Thegraphisstrictlyincreasingfor α<1. The dashed line shows the advantage of waiting given a larger value of γ. Figure 1b shows (α; γ.p 1 ) (the advantage of waiting) in the ticket game with scalpers. That function increases for α<ˆα and then drops discontinuously. Provided that γp h >p 1 (as Figure 1b assumes) the agent loses positive surplus by waiting; therefore, < 0 for α>ˆα (where the second period surplus is 0). Again, the dashed line shows that a larger value of γ reduces the advantage of waiting. For all four panels we assume that the value of γ is at a level such that the advantage of taking the action is positive for some range of α and negative for some other range. Now we consider the payoffs in two other games. Figure 1c, adapted from Goldstein and Pauzner (2003), shows the graph of the advantage of running on a bank, i.e. withdrawing funds from a bank early, as a function of α. Hereα is the measure of agents who run on the bank. An increase in the economic fundamental, γ, increases the chance that an investment will succeed in the second period, making it possible for the bank to pay a high return to agents who 1

ˆ Figure 1: The benefit of a particular action as a function of α. (Dashed line shows benefitfor higher γ.) did not withdraw their deposits early. If few agents run on the bank (α is small) the optimal action is to not withdraw funds from the bank ( < 0); if enough agents run on the bank, the bank is certain to default. In that case, > 0. For α sufficiently large the slope of is negative. For large α it remains optimal to withdraw funds, but the advantage of doing so decreases with α. Over this range of α the funds in the bank are insufficient to meet the demands of all the agents who try to withdraw their deposit. The bank s funds are rationed, so an increase in the number who try to withdraw decreases the amount that any individual receives. Therefore is decreasing in α for large α. The fact that is not monotonic means that the assumption of global strategic complements does not hold. 2

However, the graph of has a single crossing, and it remains positive over the range where it decreases. Goldstein and Pauzner (2003) refer to this as one-sided strategic complementarity. The dashed line shows the advantage of running on the bank given a stronger economic fundamental. Figure 1d, adapted from Karp, Lee, and Mason (2003), shows the advantage of going to a bar rather than staying home and reading a book. Agents do not like bars that are nearly empty or very crowded, so (for a range of values of γ, including the value shown in the figure) < 0 for α closeto0orcloseto1. Agents utility of going to the bar also depends on the quality of the band, given by γ. In this setting actions are strategic complements for small α and strategic substitutes for large α. Goldstein and Pauzner (2003) show that there exists a unique equilibrium (a threshold equilibrium) in the bank run game despite the lack of global strategic complementarity. Karp, Lee, and Mason (2003) show that in the bar problem there is no threshold equilibrium in fact no equilibrium that is monotonic in the signal when the degree of strategic substitutability is high and is small. Thus, Figures 1b 1d illustrate three departures from the global complementarity assumption, and three kinds of results: (b) a unique threshold equilibrium but no general uniqueness result, (c) a unique equilibrium, a threshold equilibrium, and (d) no threshold equilibrium. The one-sided strategic complementarity is crucial for Goldstein and Pauzner s proof of uniqueness; since this assumption does not hold for the games illustrated by figures 1b or 1d, the absence of a uniqueness proof in those cases is perhaps not surprising. However, Figures 1b and 1d both have two disjoint intervals over which < 0 (and therefore both violate the single-crossing property), so it may be surprising that there is a unique threshold equilibrium in one case and no threshold equilibrium in the other. In order to explain this difference, we use Goldstein and Pauzner s intuitive explanation of the existence of a (unique) threshold equilibrium. This argument is valid for the games in Figures 1a and 1c. The explanation is also useful for the game in Figure 1b, because it shows that a local condition for existence is satisfied. However, the explanation completely breaks down for the game in Figure 1d. Goldstein and Pauzner s intuitive explanation is therefore useful inhelpingtounderstandwhythegamesinfigures1band1dhavesuchdifferentequilibria, despite the apparent similarities of the two payoff functions. In all four games there exists a unique signal, that we denote as k, such that if an agent believes that all other agents are using the threshold strategy I k (η) defined in Equation (11), 3

Figure 2: The benefit of an action as a function of γ, under a threshold strategy. the agent who observes η = k is indifferent between the two actions. Thus, in each of the four games there is a unique candidate threshold equilibrium. If all agents use this threshold strategy, the function α (γ; I k ) isgivenbyequation(12). No agent takes the action if γ<k and all agents take the action if γ>k+. In order for the candidate to be an equilibrium, it must be the case that the expectation of (conditional on the belief that all agents use the threshold strategy) is 0 conditional on the signal η = k and that the expectation is negative (respectively, positive) for η > k(respectively, η<k). This requirement implies that the graph of the conditional expectation of (as a function of the signal) is decreasing in the neighborhood of k. The four panels of Figure 2 show the graphs of as a function of the state of nature γ, under the assumption that all agents use the threshold strategy I k (η). (The level of the threshold differs in the different games.) In the ticket game without scalpers (Figure 2a), where = γb 0 γp h p 1, all agents wait for sufficiently low γ, and the advantage of waiting declines linearly with γ at the rate B 0 (1) p h.forγ slightly above k, some agents receive asignalabovek and decide to buy, reducing the chance of getting a ticket in the second period for those who wait. Thus, increases in γ lead to a faster reduction in the benefit ofwaiting. (The function becomes concave.) 4

In the ticket game with scalpers, under the threshold strategy we have ( ) γp h p 1 if γ < ˆγ = B 0 (α (γ)). γp h p 1 if γ > ˆγ where ˆγ is defined in Equation (16) and α (γ) isgivenbyequation(12). The function has a discontinuous upward jump at ˆγ (Figure 2b). In the model with bank runs, for very bad states of nature all agents run on the bank. The advantage of running on the bank is constant with respect to the state of nature (Figure 2c). For γ slightly above k, some agents receive a signal that induces them to not run on the bank. By keeping their deposits in the bank they increase the payment to those agents who withdraw their deposits, thereby increasing the advantage of running on the bank. Therefore > 0 γ for γ slightly above k. When the economic fundamental becomes sufficiently strong, the increased probability that the investment will be successful reduces the attraction of making an early withdrawal; over this region < 0,asshown. γ Whenagentsuseathresholdstrategyinthebarproblem,theydecidetogothebarfor sufficiently large γ (e.g., a very good band). If the congestion effect is strong enough and is small enough, there is an interval of γ>k+ over which < 0, as shown in Figure 2d. Over this interval the quality of the band (the value of γ) is not great enough to compensate for the amount of congestion. By construction, the integral of over (k, k + ) is 0 for all four panels of Figure 2 (since agents who observe η = k are indifferent between the two actions). Recall that in all four games, the posterior distribution of γ (conditional on the signal) is uniform over the support [η, η + ]. We are now in a position to describe how the value of this integral changes as the signal changes. For concreteness, consider an agent who observes a signal η 0 slightly larger than k. In Figures 2a - 2c, the integral of over (η 0, η 0 + ) is negative, since, as the signal increases from k to η 0, we take away positive area and add negative area to the integral. Thus, given the signal η 0 >k,the expected value of waiting in the ticket game and the expected value of withdrawing funds in the bank-run game is negative, as required by equilibrium. The converse holds for signals slightly below k. This argument establishes that the expectation of (conditional on the belief that all agents use the threshold strategy) is a decreasing function of the signal in the neighborhood of η = k. (We explained above why this negative slope is a requirement for equilibrium.) In panels (a) and (c) the argument in the previous paragraph holds for all η 0 >k, not only 5

in the neighborhood of k. This argument, together with the observation that there is a unique candidate threshold equilibrium, implies that there is a unique threshold equilibrium for the games described in panels (a) and (c). (Goldstein and Pauzner s argument that there are no other types of equilibria in the bank run game is distinct from the argument summarized here.) The upward discontinuity in panel (b) prevents extending the graphical argument in the ticket game with scalpers away from the neighborhood of η = k. That is, the argument only shows that the slope of the expectation of is negative at η = k a necessary condition for the existence of a threshold equilibrium. The argument cannot be used to show that the expectation of asthesamesignask η. However, the graphical argument is not valid for the game in panel (d), even for signals in the neighborhood of k. When the signal increases from k to η 0, taking expectations of involves both adding and subtracting a negative area to the integral. In this case, there is no reason to think that the expected payoff has the correct monotonicity. Karp, Lee, and Mason (2003) confirm that there is no threshold equilibrium in the bar game when congestion is large and is small. 6

References GOLDSTEIN, I., AND A. PAUZNER (2003): Demand deposit contracts and the probability of bank runs, Eitan Berglas School of Economics. KARP, L.,I.H.LEE, AND R. MASON (2003): A Global Game with Strategic Substitutes and Complements, University of California, Berkeley, Dept. of Ag and Resource Economics; and http://are.berkeley.edu/ karp/. 7