Prospect Theory Applications in Finance. Nicholas Barberis Yale University

Similar documents
Stocks as Lotteries: The Implications of Probability Weighting for Security Prices

Realization Utility. Nicholas Barberis Yale University. Wei Xiong Princeton University

RESEARCH OVERVIEW Nicholas Barberis, Yale University July

What drives the disposition effect? An analysis of a long-standing preference-based explanation

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES THE LOSS AVERSION / NARROW FRAMING APPROACH TO THE EQUITY PREMIUM PUZZLE. Nicholas Barberis Ming Huang

Behavioral Finance. Nicholas Barberis Yale School of Management October 2016

The Effect of Pride and Regret on Investors' Trading Behavior

Econ 219B Psychology and Economics: Applications (Lecture 6)

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES STOCKS AS LOTTERIES: THE IMPLICATIONS OF PROBABILITY WEIGHTING FOR SECURITY PRICES. Nicholas Barberis Ming Huang

BEHAVIORAL FINANCE Asset Prices and Investor Behavior. American Economic Association January Nicholas Barberis Yale University

Preferences with Frames: A New Utility Specification that Allows for the Framing of Risks

LECTURE NOTES 10 ARIEL M. VIALE

Prospect Theory and the Size and Value Premium Puzzles. Enrico De Giorgi, Thorsten Hens and Thierry Post

First Impressions: System 1 Thinking and the Cross-section of Stock Returns

DIVERSIFICATION IN LOTTERY-LIKE FEATURES AND PORTFOLIO PRICING DISCOUNTS

Econ 219A Psychology and Economics: Foundations (Lecture 5)

The Disposition Effect and Expectations as Reference Point

Prospect Theory and Asset Prices

EC989 Behavioural Economics. Sketch solutions for Class 2

Comparison of Disposition Effect Evidence from Karachi and Nepal Stock Exchange

Regret, Pride, and the Disposition Effect

Casino gambling problem under probability weighting

FIN 355 Behavioral Finance

RISK AND RETURN REVISITED *

Salience and Asset Prices

Dynamic Decision Making in Agricultural Futures and Options Markets by Fabio Mattos, Philip Garcia and Joost M. E. Pennings

A Model of Casino Gambling

Local Risk Neutrality Puzzle and Decision Costs

The Effect of Mental Accounting on Sales Decisions of Stockholders in Tehran Stock Exchange

Prospect Theory, Partial Liquidation and the Disposition Effect

Equilibrium Asset Pricing with Epstein-Zin and. Loss-Averse Investors

Prospect Theory and Stock Returns: An Empirical Test

Does Portfolio Rebalancing Help Investors Avoid Common Mistakes?

Prospect Theory and Stock Returns: An Empirical Test

Salience Theory and Stock Prices: Empirical Evidence

Do Investors Buy Lotteries in China s Stock Market?

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Realization Utility: Explaining Volatility and Skewness Preferences

A Behavioral Approach to Asset Pricing

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2

Reference Dependence Lecture 1

A Belief-Based Model of Investor Trading Behavior

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

1 Dynamic programming

BOUNDEDLY RATIONAL EQUILIBRIUM AND RISK PREMIUM

Rolling Mental Accounts. Cary D. Frydman* Samuel M. Hartzmark. David H. Solomon* This Draft: March 13th, 2016

EMPIRICAL STUDY ON STOCK'S CAPITAL RETURNS DISTRIBUTION AND FUTURE PERFORMANCE

Rolling Mental Accounts. Cary D. Frydman* Samuel M. Hartzmark. David H. Solomon* This Draft: August 3rd, 2016

Lottery-Related Anomalies: The Role of Reference-Dependent Preferences *

Lottery-Related Anomalies: The Role of Reference-Dependent Preferences *

ESSAYS ON LOSS AVERSION AND HOUSEHOLD PORTFOLIO CHOICE IN DO HWANG DISSERTATION

Martina Nardon and Paolo Pianca. Prospect theory: An application to European option pricing

Citation for published version (APA): Groot, J. S. D., & Dijkstra, T. K. (1996). Writing covered calls: should it be done? s.n.

Time Diversification under Loss Aversion: A Bootstrap Analysis

Loss Aversion and Asset Prices

Reference price distribution and stock returns: an analysis based on the disposition effect

Master Thesis Finance THE ATTRACTIVENESS OF AN INVESTMENT STRATEGY BASED ON SKEWNESS: SELLING LOTTERY TICKETS IN FINANCIAL MARKETS

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

2010 Faculty of Business and Law Primary Supervisor: Dr. Peiming Wang

Consumption and Portfolio Decisions When Expected Returns A

Have we solved the idiosyncratic volatility puzzle?

People avoid actions that create regret and seek actions that cause

Herding and Contrarianism: A Matter of Preference?

Lottery-Related Anomalies: The Role of Reference-Dependent Preferences

Towards the Design of Better Equity Benchmarks

Risk aversion, Under-diversification, and the Role of Recent Outcomes

for Cliquet-Style Guarantees

Stocks with Extreme Past Returns: Lotteries or Insurance?

Belief in Mean Reversion and the Disposition Effect: An Experimental Test

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Myopic Loss Aversion, Asymmetric Correlations, and the Home Bias

Optimal Financial Education. Avanidhar Subrahmanyam

Context Dependent Preferences

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Asset Location and Allocation with. Multiple Risky Assets

Salience Theory and Stock Prices: Empirical Evidence

Does Yearend Sweep Ameliorate the Disposition Effect of. Mutual Fund Investors?

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Econ 219A Psychology and Economics: Foundations (Lecture 5)

Goal-Based Investing with Cumulative Prospect Theory and Satisficing Behavior

Household Investment Puzzles and Probability Weighting

Models of Reference Dependent Preferences

The Investment Behavior of Small Investors in the Hong Kong Derivatives Markets: A Statistical Analysis

Herding and Contrarianism: A Matter of Preference

Behavioral Finance and Asset Pricing

Diversification in Lottery-Like Features and Portfolio Pricing Discounts *

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011

Heterogeneous Firm, Financial Market Integration and International Risk Sharing

The Trend Is Your (Imaginary) Friend - A Behavioral Perspective on Technical Analysis

Manipulating Individuals' Risk-Taking with Financial Incentives: A Myopic Loss Aversion Experiment

Self Control, Risk Aversion, and the Allais Paradox

Basics of Asset Pricing. Ali Nejadmalayeri

A Prospect-Theoretical Interpretation of Momentum Returns

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

What Can Rational Investors Do About Excessive Volatility and Sentiment Fluctuations?

Credit Risk and Lottery-type Stocks: Evidence from Taiwan

Do Large Losses Loom Larger than Gains? Salience, Holding Periods, and the Disposition Effect

One-Period Valuation Theory

Unifying the CAPM with Prospect Theory behavior: A theoretical and numerical analysis

Transcription:

Prospect Theory Applications in Finance Nicholas Barberis Yale University March 2010 1

Overview in behavioral finance, we work with models in which some agents are less than fully rational rationality is typically taken to mean two things: rational beliefs: update beliefs using Bayes rule rational preferences: make decisions according to EU, with a utility function defined over wealth or consumption 2

Overview, ctd. one source of inspiration on plausible departures from rationality is the psychology literature psychology of beliefs deviations from Bayes rule e.g. overconfidence, representativeness psychology of preferences deviations from EU or a concern for non-consumption utility e.g. prospect theory, narrow framing, ambiguity aversion today, look at implications of prospect theory and narrow framing for asset prices and portfolio choice 3

Prospect Theory almost all models of the stock market assume that investors evaluate risk according to EU however, extensive experimental evidence shows that people systematically violate EU there are now many non-eu models that try to capture the experimental evidence Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979) is the best-known it does the best job capturing the evidence many financial phenomena are hard to explain within the EU framework can we make progress by replacing EU with Prospect Theory? 4

Prospect Theory, ctd. Four key features: the carriers of value are gains and losses, not final wealth levels compare v(x) vs.u(w + x) inferred from experimental evidence also consistent with the way we perceive other attributes v( ) has a kink at the origin captures a greater sensitivity to losses (even small losses) than to gains of the same magnitude loss aversion inferred from aversion to (110, 1 2 ; 100, 1 2 ) v( ) is concave over gains, convex over losses inferred from (500, 1) (1000, 1 ) and ( 500, 1) 2 ( 1000, 1 2 ) 6

Prospect Theory, ctd. transform probabilities with a weighting function π( ) that overweights low probabilities Note: inferred from our simultaneous liking of lotteries and insurance, e.g. (5, 1) (5000, 0.001) and ( 5, 1) ( 5000, 0.001) transformed probabilities should not be thought of as beliefs, but as decision weights 7

Cumulative Prospect Theory proposed by Tversky and Kahneman (1992) applies the probability weighting function to the cumulative distribution function: (x m,p m ;...; x 1,p 1 ; x 0,p 0 ; x 1,p 1 ;...; x n,p n ), where x i <x j for i<jand x 0 = 0, is assigned the value n i= m π iv(x i ) π i = π(p i +...+ p n ) π(p i+1 +...+ p n ) π(p m +...+ p i ) π(p m +...+ p i 1 ) for 0 i n m i< the agent now overweights the tails of a probability distribution this preserves a preference for lottery-like gambles 8

Cumulative Prospect Theory, ctd. Tversky and Kahneman (1992) also suggest functional forms for v( ) and π( ) and calibrate them to experimental evidence: v(x) = x α λ( x) α for x 0 x<0 π(p )= P δ (P δ +(1 P ) δ ) 1/δ with α =0.88,λ=2.25,δ =0.65 9

1 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.6 w(p) 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.1 0 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 P FIGURE 2. THE TVERSKY-KAHNEMAN (1992) PROBABILITY WEIGHTING FUNCTION. Notes: The figure shows the form of the probability weighting function proposed by Tversky and Kahneman (1992), namely w(p )=P δ /(P δ +(1 P ) δ ) 1/δ. The dashed line corresponds to δ =0.65, the dash-dot line to δ =0.4, and the solid line to δ =1. 55

Narrow framing in traditional models, an agent evaluates a new gamble by merging it with his pre-existing risks and checking if the combination is attractive but in experimental settings, people often seem to evaluate a new gamble in isolation (Tversky and Kahneman, 1981) this is narrow framing get utility directly from the outcome of the gamble, not just indirectly from its contribution to total wealth Barberis, Huang, and Thaler (2006) argue that the rejection of (110, 1 2 ; 100, 1 2 ) is not only evidence of loss aversion, but of narrow framing as well an agent with pre-existing risk finds the above gamble attractive, even if loss averse 10

Narrow framing, ctd. how should narrow framing be interpreted? two possibilities: it is related to non-consumption utility, e.g. regret, which is plausibly associated with a narrow frame it stems from an intuitive attempt to maximize consumption utility intuition uses accessible information, and the most accessible information may be about narrow components of wealth (Kahneman, 2003) in what follows, we sometimes define prospect theory s gains and losses as gains and losses in specific components of wealth e.g. gains and losses in stock market wealth e.g. gains and losses in a specific stock this is narrow framing 11

Applications of prospect theory and narrow framing Probability weighting function I. Pricing of skewness Concavity/convexity of value function over gains/losses II. Disposition effect Loss aversion III. Equity premium IV. Stock market non-participation 12

Applications, ctd. In all cases: have to decide on a frame, narrow or broad which asset do the gains and losses refer to? then decide on the precise definition of the gain/loss e.g. what is the reference point? 13

Models and references Probability weighting function Barberis and Huang (2008), Stocks as Lotteries: The Implications of Probability Weighting for Security Prices, American Economic Review. Concavity/convexity of value function over gains/losses Barberis and Xiong (2009), What Drives the Disposition Effect? An Analysis of a Long-Standing Preference-Based Explanation, Journal of Finance. Barberis and Xiong (2010), Realization Utility, Working paper. 14

Models and references, ctd. Loss aversion Barberis, Huang, and Santos (2001a), Prospect Theory and Asset Prices, Quarterly Journal of Economics. Barberis and Huang (2001b), Mental Accounting, Loss Aversion, and Individual Stock Returns, Journal of Finance. Barberis, Huang, and Thaler (2006), Individual Preferences, Monetary Gambles, and Stock Market Participation: A Case for Narrow Framing, American Economic Review. Barberis and Huang (2007), The Loss Aversion / Narrow Framing Approach to the Equity Premium Puzzle, Handbook of the Equity Risk Premium. Barberis and Huang (2009), Preferences with Frames: A New Utility Specification that Allows for the Framing of Risks, Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control. 15

I. Pricing of skewness (PW) Barberis and Huang (2008), Stocks as Lotteries... single period model; a risk-free asset and J Normally distributed risky assets agents have identical expectations about security payoffs agents have identical CPT preferences Then: defined over gains/losses in wealth (i.e. no narrow framing) reference point is initial wealth scaled up by riskless rate, so utility defined over Ŵ = W 1 W 0 R f full specification is: V (Ŵ )= 0 v(w ) dπ(p (W )) 0 v(w ) dπ(1 P (W )) (continuous distribution version of Tversky and Kahneman, 1992) the CAPM holds FOSD holds all investors are on the MVE frontier De Giorgi, Hens, and Levy (2003) 16

I. Pricing of skewness (PW), ctd. now introduce a small, independent, positively skewed security into the economy we obtain a novel prediction: the new security earns a negative excess return skewness itself is priced, in contrast to concave EU model where only coskewness with market matters equilibrium involves heterogeneous holdings (assume short-sale constraints for now) some investors hold a large, undiversified position in the new security others hold no position in it at all heterogeneous holdings arise from non-unique global optima, not from heterogeneous preferences since the new security contributes skewness to the portfolios of some investors, it is valuable, and so earns a low average return 17

8 x 10 3 6 4 2 0 utility 2 4 6 8 10 0 0.02 0.04 0.06 0.08 0.1 0.12 0.14 0.16 x FIGURE 3. A HETEROGENEOUS HOLDINGS EQUILIBRIUM. Notes: The figure shows the utility that an investor with cumulative prospect theory preferences derives from adding a position in a positively skewed security to his current holdings of a Normally distributed market portfolio. The skewed security is highly skewed. The variable x is the fraction of wealth allocated to the skewed security relative to the fraction of wealth allocated to the market portfolio. The two lines correspond to different mean returns on the skewed security. 56

I. Pricing of skewness (PW), ctd. this only works if the new security is highly skewed otherwise, would need too undiversified a position in order to add skewness to the portfolio results hold: even if there are many skewed securities even if short sales are allowed qualitatively, even if EU agents are present 18

0.1 0 utility 0.1 0.2 0 0.05 0.1 0.15 0.2 0.25 x FIGURE 4. A HOMOGENEOUS HOLDINGS EQUILIBRIUM. Notes: The figure shows the utility that an investor with cumulative prospect theory preferences derives from adding a position in a positively skewed security to his current holdings of a Normally distributed market portfolio. The skewed security is only moderately skewed. The variable x is the fraction of wealth allocated to the skewed security relative to the fraction of wealth allocated to the market portfolio. The three lines correspond to different mean returns on the skewed security. 57

20 15 10 expected excess return (percent) 5 0 5 10 15 20 0.06 0.07 0.08 0.09 0.1 0.11 0.12 0.13 0.14 q FIGURE 5. SKEWNESS AND EXPECTED RETURN. Notes: The figure shows the expected return in excess of the risk-free rate earned by a small, independent, positively skewed security in an economy populated by cumulative prospect theory investors, plotted against a parameter of the security s return distribution, q, which determines the security s skewness. A low value of q corresponds to a high degree of skewness. 58

I. Pricing of skewness (PW), ctd. Applications low average return on IPOs IPO returns are highly positively skewed under-diversification Mitton and Vorkink (2007) find that undiversified individuals hold stocks that are more positively skewed than the average stock diversification discount Mitton and Vorkink (2008) low average return of volatile stocks (Ang et al., 2006) other: low average return to private equity low average return on distressed stocks over-pricing of out-of-the-money options 19

I. Pricing of skewness (PW), ctd. a clear prediction of the model is that skewness should be priced in the cross-section of assets some recent papers test this idea, and find support for the prediction Boyer, Mitton, Vorkink (2009) Conrad, Dittmar, Ghysels (2009) Zhang (2005) Green and Hwang (2009) Bali, Cakici, Whitelaw (2010) 20

II. Disposition effect (CC) Odean (1998) studies the trading activity, from 1987-1993, of 10,000 households with accounts at a large discount brokerage firm he finds that, when individual investors sell a stock, they have a greater propensity to sell one that has risen in value since purchase, rather than fallen in value the disposition effect 21

II. Disposition effect (CC) How exactly does Odean (1998) measure this? whenever an investor sells shares of a stock, classify each of the stocks in his portfolio on that day as one of: realized gain, realized loss, paper gain, or paper loss add up total number of realized gains and losses and paper gains and losses over all accounts over the sample, and compute: PGR = PLR = no. of realized gains no. of realized gains + no. of paper gains no. of realized losses no. of realized losses + no. of paper losses (e.g. PGR is proportion of gains realized ) the disposition effect is the finding that PGR > PLR specifically, 0.148 = PGR > PLR = 0.098 22

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. The most obvious potential explanations fail to capture important features of the data e.g. informed trading the subsequent return of winners that people sell is higher than that of losers they hold on to e.g. taxes, rebalancing, transaction costs an important piece of evidence is that the disposition effect is stronger among less sophisticated individual investors (Dhar and Zhu, 2006) 23

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. Two non-standard hypotheses have gained prominence an irrational belief in mean-reversion an explanation based on prospect theory prospect theory, in combination with stock-level narrow framing, does appear, at first sight, to offer an explanation of the disposition effect but it turns out that we need to be careful how we implement prospect theory prospect theory defined over annual stock-level trading profits does not generate a disposition effect Barberis and Xiong (2009), What Drives the Disposition Effect?... 24

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. consider a simple portfolio choice setting T + 1 dates: t =0, 1,...,T a risk-free asset, gross return R f each period a risky asset with an i.i.d binomial distribution across periods: R t,t+1 = R u >R f with probability 1 2 R d <R f with probability 1 2, i.i.d. the investor has prospect theory preferences defined over his gain/loss simplest definition of gain/loss is trading profit between 0 and T, i.e. W T W 0 we use W T W 0 R T f call W 0 R T f the reference wealth level 25

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. The investor therefore solves where max x 0,x 1,...,x T 1 E[v(ΔW T )] = E[v(W T W 0 R T f )] subject to v(x) = x α λ( x) α for x 0 x<0, W t = (W t 1 x t 1 P t 1 )R f + x t 1 P t 1 R t 1,t W T 0 (Note that we ignore probability weighting here) using the Cox-Huang (1989) methodology, can derive an analytical solution for any number of trading periods 26

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. Results the investor usually exhibits the opposite of the disposition effect only when T is high and μ is low does he exhibit a disposition effect for T = 2 and for the Tversky and Kahneman (1992) parameterization, he always exhibits the opposite of the disposition effect 27

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. Why does the disposition effect always fail in the twoperiod case for the TK parameters? (t =0, 1, 2) for the investor to buy the stock at time 0, in spite of his loss aversion, it must have a high expected return this implies that the time 1 gain is larger than the time 1 loss in magnitude it also implies that, after a time 1 gain, the investor gambles to the edge of the concave region (v( ) is only mildly concave over gains) after a time 1 loss, the investor gambles to the edge of the convex region but it takes a larger position to gamble to the edge of the concave region after the time 1 gain than it does to gamble to the edge of the convex region after the time 1 loss the investor takes more risk after a gain than after a loss, contrary to the disposition effect 28

100 Time 1 and time 2 gains/losses plotted on the value function 80 60 B 40 A 20 B utils 0 20 D 40 C 60 D 80 100 100 80 60 40 20 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 gain/loss 45

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. So how can we explain the disposition effect? one idea is to apply prospect theory to realized gains and losses i.e. to assume realization utility (Shefrin and Statman, 1985) e.g. if you buy a stock at $40 and sell it at $60 you get a jolt of positive utility at the moment of sale, based on the size of the realized gain prospect theory applied to realized gains and losses does predict a disposition effect more reliably (Barberis and Xiong, 2009) realization utility may be a consequence of mental accounting people often think about their investing history as a series of investing episodes or stories when an investor sells an asset at a gain, he feels good because he is creating a positive new investing episode 29

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. Weber and Camerer (1995) provide useful experimental support for the realization utility view of the disposition effect in a laboratory setting, they ask subjects to trade six stocks over a number of periods each stock has some probability of going up in each period, ranging from 0.35 to 0.65 subjects are not told which stock is associated with which up-move probability subjects exhibit a disposition effect more interestingly, in one condition, the experimenter liquidates subjects holdings and then allows them to reallocate however they like subjects do not re-establish their positions in prior losers 30

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. Barberis and Xiong (2010), Realization Utility, study linear realization utility, coupled with a positive time discount factor an infinite horizon, continuous-time model with a risk-free asset and many risky stocks at each moment of time, the investor must allocate all of his wealth either to the risk-free asset or to one of the stocks if he sells a stock, he derives utility from the realized gain or loss Solution if the expected return on stocks is too low, the agent invests in the risk-free asset forever if the expected return on stocks is high enough, he buys a stock at time 0 and sells it only if its value rises a certain percentage amount above purchase price he then immediately reinvests in another stock, and so on 31

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. applications: Note: the disposition effect but also: excessive trading the underperformance of individual investors even before transaction costs the greater turnover in bull markets the greater selling propensity above historical highs the negative premium to volatility in the crosssection the fact that overpriced assets are also heavily traded although not a feature of this model, realization utility may also generate momentum in asset prices Grinblatt and Han (2005), Frazzini (2006) 32

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. Summary a model in which the investor derives prospect theory utility from annual trading profits does not deliver a disposition effect very reliably a model in which the investor derives prospect theory utility from realized gains and losses delivers a disposition effect more reliably Note: but the disposition effect follows even from linear realization utility, coupled with a positive time discount factor some authors have argued that we shouldn t give up on the annual trading profit implementation of prospect theory e.g. Meng (2009) considers an alternative reference point assumption 33

II. Disposition effect (CC), ctd. the trading models we have looked at ignore probability weighting in dynamic settings, probability weighting leads to a time inconsistency this may be relevant in some contexts, e.g. casinos Barberis (2010), A Model of Casino Gambling 34

III. Equity premium (LA) a model in which investors are loss averse over annual changes in the value of their stock market holdings predicts a large equity premium Benartzi and Thaler (1995) three elements: loss aversion annual evaluation narrow framing Benartzi and Thaler (1995) emphasize the first two elements myopic loss aversion 35

III.Equitypremium(LA),ctd. to make the argument more rigorous, need to embed it in a dynamic setting e.g. so that preferences include a utility of consumption term alongside the prospect theory term two ways of doing this: Barberis, Huang, and Santos (2001a) Barberis and Huang (2009) Barberis and Huang (2007) reviews both methods 36

III.Equitypremium(LA),ctd. Method I (Barberis, Huang, and Santos, 2001a) intertemporal model; three assets: risk-free (R f,t ), stock market (R S,t+1 ), non-financial asset (R N,t+1 ) representative agent maximizes: E 0 ρ t C1 γ t t=0 1 γ + b 0ρ t+1 C γ t v(g S,t+1 ) G S,t+1 = θ S,t (W t C t )(R S,t+1 1) x v(x) = λx for x 0 x<0, λ>1 frame stock market narrowly v( ) captures only loss aversion for reasonable parameters, get substantial equity premium 37

III.Equitypremium(LA),ctd. three elements in the Benartzi and Thaler (1995) hypothesis loss aversion, annual evaluation, narrow framing the term myopic loss aversion emphasizes the first two ingredients but narrow framing is just as critical loss aversion over total wealth fluctuations doesn t produce as large an equity premium the loss aversion / narrow framing approach? how do we justify the narrow framing? 38

III.Equitypremium(LA),ctd. Method II (Barberis and Huang, 2009) start from standard recursive specification V t = H(C t,μ(v t+1 )) W (C, x) = ((1 β)c ρ + βx ρ ) ρ, 1 0 <β<1, 0 ρ<1 μ(x) =(E(x ζ )) ζ 1 can adjust this to incorporate narrow framing V t = H C t,μ(v t+1 )+b i,0 in 3-asset context from before: i E t(v(g i,t+1 )) V t = H (C t,μ(v t+1 )+b 0 E t (v(g S,t+1 ))) G S,t+1 = θ S,t (W t C t )(R S,t+1 1) x v(x) = λx for x 0 x<0, λ>1 ζ = ρ 39

III.Equitypremium(LA),ctd. this specification is better than Method I it is tractable in partial equilibrium it admits an explicit value function easy to check attitudes to monetary gambles it does not require aggregate consumption scaling C can now show that for parameter values that predict reasonable attitudes to large and small-scale monetary gambles, get substantial equity premium 40

III.Equitypremium(LA),ctd. Barberis, Huang, and Santos (2001a) also build in dynamic aspects of loss aversion house money effect generates high volatility and time-series predictability in addition to a high equity premium but dynamic risk-taking phenomena are still poorly understood e.g. after a prior loss, do we see more or less risktaking? 41

IV. Stock market non-participation (LA) the combination of loss aversion and narrow framing may shed light on other puzzling phenomena in particular, on examples of under-diversification potential applications: stock market non-participation (Barberis, Huang, and Thaler, 2006) low number of stocks held directly home bias narrow framing is crucial in all these applications e.g. loss aversion over total wealth does not predict stock market non-participation even a loss averse agent would want some position in equities since the stock market has a low correlation with other household risks, it offers useful diversification 42

Summary probability weighting pricing of skewness no narrow framing needed concavity/convexity of value function disposition effect (sometimes!) but probably need realization utility loss aversion equity premium, under-diversification need narrow framing Future work? test prospect theory hypotheses for various facts use theoretical analysis to develop new predictions 43