Ambiguity Aversion. Mark Dean. Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University

Similar documents
Subjective Expected Utility Theory

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Expected Utility Theory

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Other Regarding Preferences

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Choice under risk and uncertainty

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

Ambiguity Aversion in Standard and Extended Ellsberg Frameworks: α-maxmin versus Maxmin Preferences

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Contents. Expected utility

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Notes for Session 2, Expected Utility Theory, Summer School 2009 T.Seidenfeld 1

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

MA 1125 Lecture 14 - Expected Values. Wednesday, October 4, Objectives: Introduce expected values.

Choice under Uncertainty

Uncertainty. Contingent consumption Subjective probability. Utility functions. BEE2017 Microeconomics

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market

Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity

Why casino executives fight mathematical gambling systems. Casino Gambling Software: Baccarat, Blackjack, Roulette, Craps, Systems, Basic Strategy

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Expectimax and other Games

CS 188: Artificial Intelligence. Maximum Expected Utility

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Homework 9 (for lectures on 4/2)

Reference Dependence and Loss Aversion in Probabilities: Theory and Experiment of Ambiguity Attitudes

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

Their opponent will play intelligently and wishes to maximize their own payoff.

Behavioral Insurance: An Introduction

Exercises for Chapter 8

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions.

Choice Under Uncertainty

What do Coin Tosses and Decision Making under Uncertainty, have in common?

Notes 10: Risk and Uncertainty

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM

CS 4100 // artificial intelligence

Decision making in the presence of uncertainty

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

10/12/2011. Risk Decision-Making & Risk Behaviour. Decision Theory. under uncertainty. Decision making. under risk

Chapter 15 Trade-offs Involving Time and Risk. Outline. Modeling Time and Risk. The Time Value of Money. Time Preferences. Probability and Risk

Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information

TECHNIQUES FOR DECISION MAKING IN RISKY CONDITIONS

Lecture 12: Introduction to reasoning under uncertainty. Actions and Consequences

Ambiguity Attitudes and Financial Diversification: Can Ambiguity Likelihood Insensitivity Help to Explain Under-Diversification?

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Time Preferences. Mark Dean. Behavioral Economics Spring 2017

Choose between the four lotteries with unknown probabilities on the branches: uncertainty

Mean, Variance, and Expectation. Mean

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

5/2/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 24: Uncertainty and Information 2. Today. The Story So Far. Preferences and Expected Utility

* Financial support was provided by the National Science Foundation (grant number

Finish what s been left... CS286r Fall 08 Finish what s been left... 1

Economic Risk and Decision Analysis for Oil and Gas Industry CE School of Engineering and Technology Asian Institute of Technology

CS 5522: Artificial Intelligence II

Handling Uncertainty. Ender Ozcan given by Peter Blanchfield

Lesson 9: Comparing Estimated Probabilities to Probabilities Predicted by a Model

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Rational Choice and Moral Monotonicity. James C. Cox

MLLunsford 1. Activity: Mathematical Expectation

Self Control, Risk Aversion, and the Allais Paradox

Financial Economics. A Concise Introduction to Classical and Behavioral Finance Chapter 2. Thorsten Hens and Marc Oliver Rieger

On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences *

Insights from Behavioral Economics on Index Insurance

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Chapter 7 Review questions

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli

1. better to stick. 2. better to switch. 3. or does your second choice make no difference?

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Lecture 3: Making Decisions with Multiple Objectives Under Certainty

Decision making under uncertainty

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

Reference Dependence Lecture 1

Epistemic Experiments: Utilities, Beliefs, and Irrational Play

2 Lecture Sophistication and Naivety

An Economist s Roadmap: from the World to formal Theory, and back to (Experimental) Data

Ambiguity, Information Quality and Asset Pricing. Larry G. Epstein and Martin Schneider. Working Paper No. 507 May 2004 UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER

Transcription:

Ambiguity Aversion Mark Dean Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University 1 Subjective Expected Utility So far, we have been considering the roulette wheel world of objective probabilities: our decision maker has been choosing between lotteries, which give a know probability of winning each of the available prizes. We are now going to think about the horse race world of subjective probabilities (which we will also call uncertainty or ambiguity). Remember the key difference: when talking about a roulette wheel all (or at least most) people would agree on the probability of each outcome: if there are 38 slots in the wheel, the probability of each slot is 1 38. We can therefore treat the probabilities of lotteries based on roulette wheels as observable (i.e. we, as the researcher, know what they are). In contrast, we may be much less confident about the probabilities associated with a horse race. Just because there are 3 horses does not mean that each has a 1 3 chance of winning. In fact, reasonable people may assign very different probabilities to outcomes of the same horse race. Therefore we cannot treat these probabilities as externally observable. If they exist anywhere, they exist in the head of the decision maker, in the same way that utilities exist in the head of the decision maker. We therefore need another approach. In order to capture what it is that the decision maker is uncertain about, we will introduce the concept of states of the world. These summarize the possible outcomes that could occur. If we think of the simple case of a race between 3 horses (Archibald, Byron and Cumberbach) then there are 6 possible states of the world, related to the different orders in which the horses can finish (excluding ties) 1

State Ordering Payoff Act f Payoff Act g 1 A, B,C $10 -$10 2 A, C, B $10 -$10 3 B, A, C -$10 -$10 4 B, C, A -$10 -$10 5 C, A, B -$10 $20 6 C, B, A -$10 $20 We then think of a decision maker choosing between acts. An act is defined by the outcome it provides in each state of the world. The following are two examples of acts: Act f: A $10 even money bet that Archibald will win Act g: A $10 bet at odds of 2 to 1 that Cumberbach will win The above table shows what each of these acts will pay in each state of the world. Act f pays $10 if Archibald wins, and -$10 otherwise. Act g pays $20 if Cumberbach wins, and -$10 otherwise? If you had to make a choice between act f and act g, how would you do it? The subjective expected utility model assumes the following procedure 1. Figure out the probability you would associate with each state of the world 2. Figure out the utility you would gain from each prize 3. Figure out the expected utility of each act according to those probabilities and utilities 4. Choose the act with the highest utility So, in the above problem, the DM would choose act f over g if [π(abc) + π(acb)] u(10) + [π(bac) + π(bca)] u( 10) + [π(cba) + π(cab)] u( 10) [π(abc) + π(acb)] u( 10) + [π(bac) + π(bca)] u( 10) + [π(cba) + π(cab)] u(20) If we rearrange this expression and (for the moment) assume that utility is linear, we get [π(abc) + π(acb)] [π(cba) + π(cab)] 3 2 2

In other words, you will choose f over g if you think the probability of Archibald winning is at least 3 2 higher than the probability of Cumberbach winning. We say that a DM s preferences over acts have a Subjective Expected Utility (SEU) representation if we can find some utility function and some probabilities that are consistent with their choices Definition 1 Let X be a set of prizes, Ω be a (finite) set of states of the world and F be the resulting set of acts (i.e. F is the set of all functions f : Ω X). We say that preferences on the set of acts F has a subjective expected utility representation if there exists a utility function u : X R and probability function π : Ω [0, 1] such that ω Ω π(ω) = 1 and f g ω Ω π(ω)u (f(ω)) ω Ω π(ω)u (g(ω)) Some things to note about the subjective utility model: In the case of objective world, we only had to identify one thing from the decision maker s choices - the utility function. Everything else was externally observable. identify two things: their utility function and their beliefs Now we have to As in the case of choice under objective risk, we might be interested in understanding what behavior is consistent with a subjective utility representation and what is not. In other words we would like a set of axioms such that preferences have an SEU representation if and only if they satisfy those axioms. Sadly, doing so is beyond the scope of this course, but you should be aware that this has been done. In fact it has been done twice. First by Savage 1 and later (using a trick to make the process a lot simpler) by Anscombe and Aumann 2 You should be interested in whether the utility numbers and probability assessments from an SEU representation are unique: i.e. can we find multiple sets of utility numbers and probability assessments that match the same preferences. We showed in the last lecture that, for objective risk, utilities were unique up to a strictly positive affi ne transformation (i.e. if 1 Savage, Leonard J. 1954. The Foundations of Statistics. New York, Wiley. 2 Anscombe, F. J.; Aumann, R. J. A Definition of Subjective Probability. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics 34 (1963), no. 1, 199 205. doi:10.1214/aoms/1177704255. 3

some utility function u represented preferences, then v would represent the same preferences if and only if v(x) = au(x) + b for some a > 0 and b R). The same is true here. Helpfully, it turns out that the probability assessments are unique - i.e. there is only one set of probabilities that will explain any preferences. This is good, in the sense that we can think of choices as completely revealing the DM s beliefs. 2 The Ellsberg Paradox Unfortunately, while the SEU model is a simple, neat and intuitively plausible model, it has problems as a predictive model of choice. In the same way that Allais came up with a thought experiment that demonstrated robust violations of Expected Utility theory for choice over objective risk, so Daniel Ellsberg came up with counter examples for choice under uncertainty. One such example we demonstrated in class: Fill a bag with 20 red and 20 black tokens (we will call this the risky bag). Offer your subject the opportunity to place a $10 bet on the color of their choice (i.e., if they choose red, then they receive $10 if a red token is drawn from the bag and $0 otherwise). Then elicit the amount x such that the subject is indifferent between playing the gamble and receiving $x for sure. Repeat the above experiment, but provide the subject with no information about the number of red and black tokens (we will call this the uncertain bag). Then elicit the amount y such that the subject is indifferent between playing the gamble and receiving $y for sure. Typically, in this experiment, we find that x is much higher than y - in other words subjects prefer betting on the risky bag than on the uncertain bag. This seems like a very natural way to behave - after all, we know a lot more about the risky bag than we do about the uncertain bag. However, it is not in line with SEU theory. Why is that? Well let s first think about the risky urn. Here, we know that there is an equal number of red and black tokens, so whichever color you bet on, the probability of winning is 50%. Thus (assuming the utility of $0 is zero), the value of betting on the risky bag is 0.5u($10) 4

What about the uncertain bag? Well in order to apply SEU we need to figure out what are the states of the world. Here we have two relevant states: that the token drawn from the uncertain bag will be red, or that it will be black. We can therefore represent the acts of betting on red (r) and betting on black (b) as follows State r b red 10 0 black 0 10 If our decision maker is an SEU type person, then they act as if they assign a probability π(red) to the token being red, and π(black) = 1 π(red) to it being black. Thus, the value of betting on red is π(red)u($10) and betting on black is (1 π(red)) u($10) Now notice that in the experiment, the decision maker gets to choose which color to bet on. Thus, the value of betting on the bag is max {π(red)u($10). (1 π(red)) u($10)} The key thing here is, whatever the decision maker s beliefs, the value of betting on the uncertain urn cannot be lower than the value of betting on the risky urn. If π(red) 0.5, then π(red)u($10) 0.5u($10). If π(red) 0.5 then (1 π(red)) 0.5 and so π(black)u($10) 0.5u($10). The probability distribution in the risky urn is the worst possible beliefs to have given that you are allowed to pick what color to bet on. Thus, the observation that x is greater than y (sometimes called ambiguity aversion ) cannot be squared with SEU 3 Maxmin Expected Utility There have been many attempts to adjust the SEU model to allow for ambiguity aversion. One of the most popular is the Maxmin Expected Utility model introduced by Gilboa and Schmeidler. 3 3 Gilboa, Itzhak & Schmeidler, David, 1989. "Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior," Journal of Mathematical Economics, Elsevier, vol. 18(2), pages 141-153, April. 5

This model also has a nice interpretation: imagine that you were of a pessimistic frame of mind, and that you thought the world was out to get you: in particular you though that the sneaky experimenter could observe whether you bet on red or black, then alter the number of red and black tokens in the bag in order to screw you over. If they saw you bet on red, they could increase the number of black tokens, and if they saw you bet on black the could increase the number of red tokens. This is basically the Maxmin Expected Utility model. Rather than having a single probability distribution over states of the world, the maxmin expected utility model assumes that the decision maker believes that there are a set of possible probability distributions out there, and that nature will pick the worst of those given the act that they have chosen Definition 2 Let X be a set of prizes, Ω be a (finite) set of states of the world and F be the resulting set of acts (i.e. F is the set of all functions f : Ω X). We say that preferences on the set of acts F has a Maxmin expected utility representation if there exists a utility function u : X R and convex set of probability functions Π and f g min π(ω)f(ω) min π(ω)g(ω) π Π ω Ω π Π ω Ω The maxmin expected utility model can explain Ellsberg paradox type behavior. Say that the decision maker believed that there were a set of possible probabilities Π of a red token being drawn from the uncertain bag between 0.25 and 0.75 (with associated probabilities of a black token being drawn between 0.25 and 0.75). Then the value of betting on red in the uncertain back would be min π(red)u($10) = 0.25u($10) π Π whereas the value of betting on black would be min π(black)u($10) = 0.25u($10) π Π Thus the maximum value of betting on the uncertain bag would be 0.25u($10), less than the 0.5u($10) one would get from betting on the risky urn. 6

4 Ambiguity Aversion and No-Trade Prices Ambiguity aversion has a number of implications for behavior in (for example) finance and insurance. One example, illustrated by Dow and Werlang, 4 is the existence of a no trade region in asset prices. Imagine that there is a financial asset that pays $10 if a company is a success, and $0 otherwise. The price of the asset is p. As an investor, you are can buy 1 unit of this asset, or you can short sell 1 unit of the asset. If you buy the asset you pay p and receive $10 if the company is a success. If you short sell the asset, then you have receive p for sure, but have to pay $10 if the company does well. What would an SEU guy choose to do? Well they would figure out their probability of the company doing well - let s call this π(good). The value of buying the asset is therefore π(good)u(10) u(p) while the utility of short selling the asset is u(p) π(good)u(10) Thus, (assuming that utility is linear, for convenience), the decision maker will buy if p 10π(good), and will short sell if p 10π(good) The key point here, is that, at any price the decision maker will be prepared to trade. For p 10π(good) they would like to buy, while for p 10π(good) they would like to sell (if p = 10π(good) then they would be happy to do either.) Now compare this to the behavior of a maxmin expected utility guy. Remember that such a person has a range of possible probabilities of the firm doing well. Let s say that π (good) is the highest probability they will consider for the firm to be good, and π (good) the lowest probability they will consider. Now, what happens if they buy the asset? In this case, they will assume the worst, and assign probability π (good) to the firm doing well. They will therefore buy the asset if π (good)u(10) u(p) 0 4 Dow, James & Werlang, Sergio Ribeiro da Costa, 1992. "Uncertainty Aversion, Risk Aversion, and the Optimal Choice of Portfolio," Econometrica, Econometric Society, vol. 60(1), pages 197-204, January. 7

If they sell the asset, they will again assume the worst, and assign the probability π (good) to the firm doing well. They are therefore prepared to short sell the asset if u(p) π (good)u(10) 0 Therefore, if π (good) < π (good), then the decision maker will not be prepared to trade at any price. Again, assuming linear utility, if the price p falls in the range 10π (good) > p > 10π (good) Then they will not be prepared to buy or sell. The reason is that their assessment of how well the firm will do depends on whether they have bought or sold the financial asset: if they buy the asset then the will assume the firm will do poorly. If they short the asset they will assume it will do well. for prices in that range, they would prefer to do neither. 8