INTERVAL DISMANTLABLE LATTICES

Similar documents
CATEGORICAL SKEW LATTICES

Modular and Distributive Lattices

Theorem 1.3. Every finite lattice has a congruence-preserving embedding to a finite atomistic lattice.

General Lattice Theory: 1979 Problem Update

INFLATION OF FINITE LATTICES ALONG ALL-OR-NOTHING SETS TRISTAN HOLMES J. B. NATION

PURITY IN IDEAL LATTICES. Abstract.

COLLOQUIA MATHEMATICA SOCIETATIS JANOS BOLYAI SZEGED (HUNGARY), 1980.

COMBINATORICS OF REDUCTIONS BETWEEN EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS

Congruence lattices of finite intransitive group acts

Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA

THE NUMBER OF UNARY CLONES CONTAINING THE PERMUTATIONS ON AN INFINITE SET

Gödel algebras free over finite distributive lattices

Projective Lattices. with applications to isotope maps and databases. Ralph Freese CLA La Rochelle

CARDINALITIES OF RESIDUE FIELDS OF NOETHERIAN INTEGRAL DOMAINS

An orderly algorithm to enumerate finite (semi)modular lattices

Lattices with many congruences are planar

The finite lattice representation problem and intervals in subgroup lattices of finite groups

Introduction to Priestley duality 1 / 24

Notes on the symmetric group

Algebra homework 8 Homomorphisms, isomorphisms

Epimorphisms and Ideals of Distributive Nearlattices

Laurence Boxer and Ismet KARACA

CONGRUENCES AND IDEALS IN A DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICE WITH RESPECT TO A DERIVATION

A Property Equivalent to n-permutability for Infinite Groups

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies

Non replication of options

Fuzzy Join - Semidistributive Lattice

The illustrated zoo of order-preserving functions

Generating all nite modular lattices of a given size

Generating all modular lattices of a given size

Skew lattices of matrices in rings

ON THE LATTICE OF ORTHOMODULAR LOGICS

CONSTRUCTION OF CODES BY LATTICE VALUED FUZZY SETS. 1. Introduction. Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 35, No. 2, 2005,

More On λ κ closed sets in generalized topological spaces

FUZZY PRIME L-FILTERS

LATTICE LAWS FORCING DISTRIBUTIVITY UNDER UNIQUE COMPLEMENTATION

Lattice Laws Forcing Distributivity Under Unique Complementation

Abstract Algebra Solution of Assignment-1

GUESSING MODELS IMPLY THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 25 Mar 2019

ORDERED SEMIGROUPS HAVING THE P -PROPERTY. Niovi Kehayopulu, Michael Tsingelis

LATTICE EFFECT ALGEBRAS DENSELY EMBEDDABLE INTO COMPLETE ONES

Some Remarks on Finitely Quasi-injective Modules

UNIVERSAL QUASIVARIETIES OF ALGEBRAS

CHARACTERIZATION OF CLOSED CONVEX SUBSETS OF R n

Lattices and the Knaster-Tarski Theorem

Translates of (Anti) Fuzzy Submodules

Ordered Semigroups in which the Left Ideals are Intra-Regular Semigroups

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours

Palindromic Permutations and Generalized Smarandache Palindromic Permutations

Forecast Horizons for Production Planning with Stochastic Demand

MITCHELL S THEOREM REVISITED. Contents

Equivalence between Semimartingales and Itô Processes

REMARKS ON K3 SURFACES WITH NON-SYMPLECTIC AUTOMORPHISMS OF ORDER 7

Hierarchical Exchange Rules and the Core in. Indivisible Objects Allocation

ADDING A LOT OF COHEN REALS BY ADDING A FEW II. 1. Introduction

PARTITIONS OF 2 ω AND COMPLETELY ULTRAMETRIZABLE SPACES

New tools of set-theoretic homological algebra and their applications to modules

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

3.2 No-arbitrage theory and risk neutral probability measure

SEMICENTRAL IDEMPOTENTS IN A RING

Lattice Model of Flow

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 24 Feb 2014

Transcendental lattices of complex algebraic surfaces

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

TEST 1 SOLUTIONS MATH 1002

Residuated Lattices of Size 12 extended version

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

Fair semigroups. Valdis Laan. University of Tartu, Estonia. (Joint research with László Márki) 1/19

Fuzzy L-Quotient Ideals

Computing Unsatisfiable k-sat Instances with Few Occurrences per Variable

Interpolation of κ-compactness and PCF

A Combinatorial Proof for the Circular Chromatic Number of Kneser Graphs

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models

Attempt QUESTIONS 1 and 2, and THREE other questions. Do not turn over until you are told to do so by the Invigilator.

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

Cut-free sequent calculi for algebras with adjoint modalities

A Translation of Intersection and Union Types

Applied Mathematics Letters

Generalization by Collapse

PORTFOLIO OPTIMIZATION AND EXPECTED SHORTFALL MINIMIZATION FROM HISTORICAL DATA

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

AN INFINITE CARDINAL-VALUED KRULL DIMENSION FOR RINGS

Fractional Graphs. Figure 1

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 13 Feb 2014

METRIC POSTULATES FOR MODULAR, DISTRIBUTIVE, AND BOOLEAN LATTICES

κ-bounded Exponential-Logarithmic Power Series Fields

Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros

TWIST UNTANGLE AND RELATED KNOT GAMES

An Optimal Odd Unimodular Lattice in Dimension 72

Virtual Demand and Stable Mechanisms

The (λ, κ)-fn and the order theory of bases in boolean algebras

Undecidability and 1-types in Intervals of the Computably Enumerable Degrees

TWO-PERIODIC TERNARY RECURRENCES AND THEIR BINET-FORMULA 1. INTRODUCTION

LATTICE VARIETIES COVERING THE SMALLEST NON-MODULAR VARIETY

ALGORITHMS FOR FINITE, FINITELY PRESENTED AND FREE LATTICES

1 Shapley-Shubik Model

On axiomatisablity questions about monoid acts

1 Directed sets and nets

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 15 Jan 1991

Alain Hertz 1 and Sacha Varone 2. Introduction A NOTE ON TREE REALIZATIONS OF MATRICES. RAIRO Operations Research Will be set by the publisher

Transcription:

INTERVAL DISMANTLABLE LATTICES KIRA ADARICHEVA, JENNIFER HYNDMAN, STEFFEN LEMPP, AND J. B. NATION Abstract. A finite lattice is interval dismantlable if it can be partitioned into an ideal and a filter, each of which can be partitioned into an ideal and a filter, etc., until you reach 1-element lattices. In this note, we find a quasi-equational basis for the pseudoquasivariety of interval dismantlable lattices, and show that there are infinitely many minimal interval non-dismantlable lattices. Define an interval dismantling of a lattice to be a partition of the lattice into two nonempty, complementary sublattices where one is an ideal and the other a filter. A finite lattice is said to be interval dismantlable if it can be reduced to 1-element lattices by successive interval dismantlings. In order to work with these lattices, we note that the following are equivalent for a finite lattice L: (1) L = I F for some disjoint proper ideal I and filter F. (2) L contains a nonzero join prime element. (3) L contains a non-one meet prime element. (4) There is a surjective homomorphism h : L 2. (5) Some generating set X for L can be split into two disjoint nonempty subsets, X = Y Z, such that Y Z. (6) Every generating set X for L can be split into two disjoint nonempty subsets, X = Y Z, such that Y Z. So if a lattice L contains no join prime element, then it is interval nondismantlable. If L contains no join prime element, but every proper sublattice does, then it is minimally interval non-dismantlable. If L contains an interval non-dismantlable sublattice, then L is interval nondismantlable. Note that it follows from (2) and (3) that every finite meet semidistributive or join semidistributive lattice is interval dismantlable. The Date: January 20, 2017. 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 06B05, 08C15. Key words and phrases. lattice, join prime, meet prime, generating set, quasivariety. 1

2 ADARICHEVA, HYNDMAN, LEMPP, AND NATION atoms of a finite meet semidistributive lattice are join prime; dually, the coatoms of a finite join semidistributive lattice are meet prime. In view of conditions (5) and (6) above, let us say that a subset X of a lattice L is divisible if it can be divided into two nonempty subsets Y and Z such that Y Z; else X is indivisible. It is straightforward to see that interval dismantlable lattices form a pseudoquasivariety, i.e., a class of finite algebraic structures closed under taking substructures and finite direct products. The basic theorem on pseudoquasivarieties is due to C. J. Ash [2]; see also Chapter 2 of V. A. Gorbunov [3]. Theorem 1. Let K be a pseudoquasivariety of structures of finite type. Then K is the set of all finite structures in the quasivariety Q = SPU(K), where U denotes the ultraproduct operator. Thus there is a set of quasi-equations that determines the set of finite interval dismantlable lattices. For each n 3, let X n = {x 1,..., x n } be a set of n variables. Consider the quasi-equations (δ n ) & Y Xn Y (Xn \ Y ) x 1 x 2. Any indivisible subset A of a lattice L with A n satisfies the hypothesis of δ n. On the other hand, by symmetry the conclusion could be replaced by x i x j for any i j. Hence the quasi-equation δ n expresses that L contains no indivisible subset of size k for 1 < k n. In particular, δ n implies δ n 1. Theorem 2. A finite lattice is interval dismantlable if and only if it satisfies δ n for all n 3, that is, the lattice contains no indivisible subset of more than one element. Proof. First, assume that L is interval dismantlable. For every n 3 and a L n, we want to show that δ n holds under the substitution x i a i. If a 1 = a 2, then the conclusion of δ n holds. If a 1 a 2, then the sublattice S = Sg(a 1,..., a n ) is nontrivial and interval dismantlable, and hence S has a decomposition S = I F into a proper ideal and filter. Let Y = {a i : a i F } and Z = {a j : a j I}. Then Y F and Z I, whence Y Z, so that the corresponding inclusion in the hypothesis of δ n fails. Thus δ n holds for every substitution. Conversely, let us show that every finite lattice that satisfies all δ n is interval dismantlable. We do so by induction on L. To begin, the 1-element lattice satisfies every δ n and is trivially interval dismantlable. So consider a finite lattice L with L > 1. Choose a generating set X = {a 1, a 2,..., a k } for L with a 1 a 2. Since L satisfies δ k and

INTERVAL DISMANTLABLE LATTICES 3 the conclusion fails, there is a nontrivial splitting X = Y Z with Y Z. This splits L into a proper ideal and filter, L = I F, and each of these is a smaller lattice that satisfies δ n for all n. By induction, both I and F are interval dismantlable, and so L is as well. Any class of finite lattices closed under sublattices can be characterized by the exclusion of its minimal non-members. Examples of minimal interval non-dismantlable lattices include M 3 and the lattices in Figure 1, which fail δ 4. We would like to show that the pseudoquasivariety of finite interval dismantlable lattices is not finitely based, for which we need an infinite sequence of minimal interval non-dismantlable lattices, such that any finite collection of the quasi-equations δ j is satisfied by at least one of them. The next theorem provides this by generalizing the top right example of Figure 1. Figure 1. Three minimal interval non-dismantlable lattices. Theorem 3. There is a sequence of minimal interval non-dismantlable lattices K n (n 4) such that each K n satisfies δ j for 3 j < n, but fails δ n. Proof. For n 4, we construct a lattice K n as follows. The carrier set is n (n 2) = {(i, j) : 0 i < n and 0 j < n 2}, with the order given by (i, j) (k, l) if j l and either 0 k i l j or

4 ADARICHEVA, HYNDMAN, LEMPP, AND NATION n+k i l j, plus a top element T and bottom element B. Thus we are thinking of the first coordinates modulo n, as if wrapped around a cylinder. The covers in the middle portion of the lattice are given by (i, j) < (i, j + 1) and (i, j) < (i + 1 mod n, j + 1) where 0 i < n and 0 j < n 3. The middle portion of the lattice K 5 is illustrated in Figure 2. 2 1 0 0 1 2 3 4 Figure 2. Middle portion of the lattice K 5 ; add top and bottom elements for the whole lattice. For a generating set, we can take X = {(i, 0) : i < n}. This has the property that any pair of distinct elements of X meets to B, while the join of any n 1 is T. Thus K n fails δ n and is interval non-dismantlable. In view of the circular symmetry, we may consider the maximal sublattices not containing the generator (0, 0). These are easily seen to be S 0 = K n \ {(0, j) : j < n 2} and T 0 = K n \ {(j, j) : j < n 2}. Both these are interval dismantlable. For S 0 = (1, 0) (n 1, n 3), with the filter being dually isomorphic to the lattice Co(n 2) of convex subsets of an n 2 element chain, and hence meet semidistributive, and the ideal being isomorphic to Co(n 2) and hence join semidistributive. Likewise T 0 = (n 1, 0) (n 2, n 3), with the filter being meet semidistributive and the ideal being join semidistributive. To see that K n satisfies δ j for 3 j < n, consider an arbitrary generating set X for K n. For each k with 0 k < n, the set S k = K n \{(k, l) : l < n 2} is a proper sublattice of K n. Hence X S k, i.e., X contains an element of the form (k, l) for each k < n. Thus X n. So every subset of K n with fewer than n elements generates a proper sublattice, which is interval dismantlable. Therefore K n satisfies δ j for j < n. Discussion. The original notion of dismantlability is that a finite lattice is dismantlable if it can be reduced to a 1-element lattice by successively removing doubly irreducible elements. These lattices were

INTERVAL DISMANTLABLE LATTICES 5 characterized independently by Ajtai [1] and Kelly and Rival [4], as those lattices not containing an n-crown for n 3. Dismantlable lattices do not form a pseudoquasivariety, as they are not closed under finite direct products. More generally, we can define a sublattice dismantling of a lattice to be a partition of the lattice into two nonempty, complementary sublattices. A finite lattice is said to be sublattice dismantlable if it can be reduced to 1-element lattices by successive sublattice dismantlings. Clearly both the original dismantlable lattices and interval dismantlable lattices are sublattice dismantlable, and this class does form a pseudoquasivariety. It would be interesting to characterize sublattice dismantlable lattices. References [1] M. Ajtai, On a class of finite lattices, Period. Math. Hungar. 4 (1973), 217 220. [2] C.J. Ash, Pseudovarieties, generalized varieties and similarly described classes, J. Algebra 92 (1985), 104 115. [3] V.A. Gorbunov, Algebraic Theory of Quasivarieties, Plenum, New York, 1998. [4] D. Kelly and I. Rival, Crowns, fences and dismantlable lattices, Canad. J. Math. 26 (1974), 1257 1271. Department of Mathematics, Hofstra University, Hempstead, NY 11549, USA E-mail address: kira.adaricheva@hofstra.edu Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Northern British Columbia, Prince George, BC, Canada E-mail address: jennifer.hyndman@unbc.ca Department of Mathematics, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI 53706, USA E-mail address: lempp@math.wisc.edu Department of Mathematics, University of Hawai i, Honolulu, HI 96822, USA E-mail address: jb@math.hawaii.edu