Lecture Note: Monitoring, Measurement and Risk. David H. Autor MIT , Fall 2003 November 13, 2003

Similar documents
INCENTIVE CONTRACTS AND PERFORMANCE MEASUREMENT. George P. Baker. Original Version: January, 1990 This Version: September, 1991

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

Transactions with Hidden Action: Part 1. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Moral Hazard: Dynamic Models. Preliminary Lecture Notes

JEFF MACKIE-MASON. x is a random variable with prior distrib known to both principal and agent, and the distribution depends on agent effort e

Economics 101A (Lecture 25) Stefano DellaVigna

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 7: Moral Hazard. Patrick Legros

Internet Appendix to: Common Ownership, Competition, and Top Management Incentives

Problem set 5. Asset pricing. Markus Roth. Chair for Macroeconomics Johannes Gutenberg Universität Mainz. Juli 5, 2010

Econ 101A Final Exam We May 9, 2012.

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Economics 101A (Lecture 25) Stefano DellaVigna

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

ECON 6022B Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions Fall 2011

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Fall 2013 D. Romer

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Eco504 Spring 2010 C. Sims FINAL EXAM. β t 1 2 φτ2 t subject to (1)

Microeconomic Foundations of Incomplete Price Adjustment

Chapter 7 Moral Hazard: Hidden Actions

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

PROBLEM SET 7 ANSWERS: Answers to Exercises in Jean Tirole s Theory of Industrial Organization

Exercises on the New-Keynesian Model

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

Macroeconomics. Lecture 5: Consumption. Hernán D. Seoane. Spring, 2016 MEDEG, UC3M UC3M

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture II: Production Function and Profit Maximization

Characterization of the Optimum

Macroeconomics Sequence, Block I. Introduction to Consumption Asset Pricing

Practice Problems. w U(w, e) = p w e 2,

Moral Hazard Example. 1. The Agent s Problem. contract C = (w, w) that offers the same wage w regardless of the project s outcome.

1 Asset Pricing: Replicating portfolios

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Microeconomics III Final Exam SOLUTIONS 3/17/11. Muhamet Yildiz

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Problem Set 2: Sketch of Solutions

Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction. By: Stephen P. Holland

Problem set 1 Answers: 0 ( )= [ 0 ( +1 )] = [ ( +1 )]

Financial Mathematics III Theory summary

Where do securities come from

MAIN TYPES OF INFORMATION ASYMMETRY (names from insurance industry jargon)

Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment

Risk Neutral Agent. Class 4

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 5. Property Rights Theory. The key question we are staring from is: What are ownership/property rights?

Information Processing and Limited Liability

Problem Set: Contract Theory

Recap First-Price Revenue Equivalence Optimal Auctions. Auction Theory II. Lecture 19. Auction Theory II Lecture 19, Slide 1

A 2 period dynamic general equilibrium model

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Efficiency Wage. Economics of Information and Contracts Moral Hazard: Applications and Extensions. Financial Contracts. Financial Contracts

Consumption and Portfolio Decisions When Expected Returns A

Practice Problems 2: Asymmetric Information

Capital Constraints, Lending over the Cycle and the Precautionary Motive: A Quantitative Exploration

ECON 4335 The economics of banking Lecture 7, 6/3-2013: Deposit Insurance, Bank Regulation, Solvency Arrangements

Intro to Economic analysis

Definition of Incomplete Contracts

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

(Some theoretical aspects of) Corporate Finance

Homework 3: Asset Pricing

Homework 1: Basic Moral Hazard

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Practice Problems. U(w, e) = p w e 2,

EFFICIENT MARKETS HYPOTHESIS

Lucas s Investment Tax Credit Example

Economics and Finance,

Portfolio Investment

Reuben Gronau s Model of Time Allocation and Home Production

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 9. Demand for Insurance

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński

1. Cash-in-Advance models a. Basic model under certainty b. Extended model in stochastic case. recommended)

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market

Up till now, we ve mostly been analyzing auctions under the following assumptions:

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

Macroeconomics I Chapter 3. Consumption

Portfolio Sharpening

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011

Moral Hazard. Economics Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior. Instructor: Songzi Du

Problems with seniority based pay and possible solutions. Difficulties that arise and how to incentivize firm and worker towards the right incentives

Economics 101A (Lecture 26) Stefano DellaVigna

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3

Bank Leverage and Social Welfare

Eco504 Spring 2010 C. Sims MID-TERM EXAM. (1) (45 minutes) Consider a model in which a representative agent has the objective. B t 1.

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Chapter 7: Portfolio Theory

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

The role of asymmetric information

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Birkbeck MSc/Phd Economics. Advanced Macroeconomics, Spring Lecture 2: The Consumption CAPM and the Equity Premium Puzzle

Dynamic Contracts. Prof. Lutz Hendricks. December 5, Econ720

Economics 430 Handout on Rational Expectations: Part I. Review of Statistics: Notation and Definitions

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Recalling that private values are a special case of the Milgrom-Weber setup, we ve now found that

Consumption- Savings, Portfolio Choice, and Asset Pricing

Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I

Transcription:

Lecture Note: Monitoring, Measurement and Risk David H. Autor MIT 14.661, Fall 2003 November 13, 2003 1

1 Introduction So far, we have toyed with issues of contracting in our discussions of training (both general and specific), holdup and shirking. The goal of this lecture is to make this set of issues more precise. We ll take three cuts at the contracting problem 1. The canonical Principal-Agent problem, which formalizes the trade-off between risk and incentives (review). This model is about uncertainty of outcomes with no uncertainty about appropriate actions. 2. The Principal-Agent problem with uncertainty about appropriate actions and asymmetric information (Baker, 1992). 3. The Principal-Agent problem with uncertainty about appropriate actions and asymmetric information: the choice of input- versus output-based contracts (Prendergast, 2002) 2 Canonical Principal-Agent problem An optimal compensation scheme must accomplish two things: 1. Induce a given worker to put forth the appropriate level of effort (incentive compatible) 2. Induce the right workers to accept the contract (selection, individual rationality)\ Under risk neutrality, the optimal contract is linear. w = α + βq, where w is the wage, q is output, and α, β are chosen contracting parameters. Output depends on effort and luck. Normalize effort e so that one unit of effort produces one unit of output in expectation, q = e + ν, where ν is luck or measurement error. 2

Workers cost of effort is c (e), withc 0 ( ),c 00 ( ) > 0. Worker s labor supply function is max e E [α + β (e + ν) c (e)], with FOC c 0 (e) =β. (1) Firm s problem is therefore max α,β E (q) (α + βe) =maxe (α + βe) subject to Individual Rationality (IR) constraint α,β α + βe > c(e). Substituting IR into firm s maximization problem (assuming holds with equality) gives max α,β e c (e), with FOC β =[1 c0 (e)] e β (and e/ α =0, so the 2 nd condition redundant). =0 (2) Combining (1) with (2) implies that β =1.Thefirm pays the worker the entire residual profit. Given this, the optimal α which is generally negative is chosen to satisfy the IR constraint. Hence, firm rents the worker the job at price α, and pays piece rate 1. However, if the worker is risk averse, then this result must be modified: There is now a trade-off between incentives and risk: A flat rate contract where w = E [α + β (e + ν) c (e)] provides the best insurance and the worst incentives 3

A pure piece rate contract with w = α + q providesthebestincentivesandworst insurance For any concave utility function, we ll therefore have 0 β RA <β RN =1,whereRA and RN stand for Risk Averse and Risk Neutral respectively, where B RA is declining in the agent s risk aversion (and α will therefore be increasing). The only agency problem in this setup is that a firm cannot simultaneously provide efficient incentives and efficient insurance to a risk averse agent. The important comparative static in this model is that, holding agent risk aversion constant, the riskier is the environment (greater σ 2 ν), thelowerisβ RA. Although risk has no effect on the optimal β for a risk neutral party, higher risk makes the contract less attractive to a risk averse agent, and the firmmayhavetocompensatetheagentheavily (though α) tosatisfytheir. Notice that you can think of this trade-off in terms of input versus output monitoring. The extreme case of input monitoring is when you pay the worker if he sits at his desk, regardless of what he produces. The extreme case of output monitoring is that you pay him q, regardless of what he does. The PA model implies that output monitoring is the ideal case for a risk neutral agent. 3 Adding imperfect output monitoring to this model It in its canonical form, the PA model takes the problem of incentives as purely a problem of mitigating the impacts of random noise. This suggests that the problem might be relatively solvable. For example, if the principal knew the agent s cost function c (e) and could monitor effort perfectly, she could write an optimal input contract based on the agent supplying e that solves c (e )=1. So, in this simple form, perhaps it s not such a deep problem. 4

In fact, the only distortion in the equilibrium of the PA model is that incentives might be insufficiently strong for first best output given that agents are risk averse. Could a contract be too strong, in that it generates too much output? In the PA model, theanswerisnosolongasβ 1, which will always be true (and this is a strict inequality of the agent is risk averse). But intuition and many colorful examples suggest that the answer must be yes. See for example the figure from Oyer, 1999, QJE on quarterly sales at competing Tandem and Stratus computer companies. Even though their fiscal years end in different quarters, each has large sales jumps at end of fiscal year. Clearly, this is not business cyclicality. Most likely explanation: gaming by managers. This idea was first formally articulated in a management journal article by Steven Kerr, 1975, On the Folly of Rewarding A, While Hoping for B. At the time of its publication, economists did not have a language for Kerr s idea. Baker s 1992 JPE formalizes Kerr s insight. 3.1 Sketch: There are numerous tasks that the agent could engage in at any time. These tasks, in aggregate affect the thing that the principle wishes to maximize V (e, ). Which activities will have the highest marginal product is unknown ex ante (a random variable, function of ). But these values are observed privately by the agent at the time of production. This would not create an incentive problem except that a contract cannot be written for V (e, ). Instead, a contract must be written for P (e, ), which is observable/verifiable. 5

[Why? We can only reward what we can measure. We cannot measure maximizing shareholder value. We can measure burgers flipper per hour. So, that s what you will paid for.] This disjuncture between V (e, ),P (e, ) gives rise to a set of contracts that can be either too weak or too strong, even with risk neutral agents. [Note that if we assumed there was no private information, this would be equivalent to assuming that the principal could contract directly over V (e, ), sincewouldbeableto specify optimal efforts given the opportunity set.] 3.2 Setup in full P s objective f n V (e, ) is not contractible. It is a f n of e, agent s actions, and, a set of random variables that completely characterize the state of the world ( SOW ). Assume an arbitrary contractible performance measure P (e, ), which is also a f n of e and SOW. Assume risk neutrality complicates without added insight. Key point is that we may get β<1despite risk neutrality. Consider only linear incentive contracts: w = α + βp (e, ) (3) NeitherPnorAknows before signing contract. Information: Agent is asymmetrically well informed about when actions are to be performed, and this affects her optimal action choice. (Seems sensible: Agent directly observes opportunity set at time actions must be taken; Principal is on a lounge chair gazing out at the Caribbean sea.) This setup implies that effort is a random variable, a function of. 6

Non-triviality: At least some elements of affect marginal product of effort on both V ( ),P ( ). Contracts are binding cannot be reneged (otherwise IR constraint also random) The standard deviation of V e (the marginal product of effort) with respect to, defined as σ ve is a measure of the amount of valuable information that the agent possesses. When σ ve low, variations in opportunity set observed by agent are not particularly important for the principal s objectives. And v.v. when σ ve high. Be clear: marginal product of effort could be high or low in either cases, but if σ ve is low, there is little reason to vary effort. Similarly σ pe is a measure of valuable info A has about performance measure P ( ). Consider e as a unidimensional variable, although could be written as vector. Time line: 1. Agent signs binding contact specifying P ( ),α,β. 2. is unknown, but its distribution is known 3. After signing, before choice of e, all elements of revealed to agent. 3.3 Maximization Normalize P ( ) so that the average dollar value of an incremental unit of performance measure is 1. Hence, optimal piece rate is 1 under a first-best contract: E [P e (e, )] = E [V e (e, )]. (4) The expected marginal product of effort on performance measure equal to expected marginal product of effort on value. Standard assumptions on effort cost: c 0 > 0,c 00 > 0. w = α + βp (e, ) c(e). (5) 7

IR constraint with outside opportunity set H : E [α + βp (e, ) c(e)] H, (6) Effort choice βp e (e, )=c 0 (e ). (7) Principal s maximization max α,β E [V (e, ) α βp (e, )], (8) subject to (6) and (7). Substituting the IR constraint into the maxmization gives and differentiating WRT β yields max E [V (e, ) H + βp (e, ) c(e) βp (e, )], β E V e e β E c 0 (e)e β =0, where e β = e / β. Substituting in equation (7) for c 0 (e ) and rearranging yields β, β = E V e e β E. (9) P e e β Notice that if there were no random variables involved that is optimal effort is not a function of thenβ =1, and there is no contracting problem. To get an expression for e β,differentiate (7): β βp e (e, ) c 0 (e ) = P e + βp ee e β c 00 e β (10) e β = P e c 00 βp ee. 8

Now, substitute back into (9) to get β = ³ E hv e ³ E hp e i P e c 00 βp ee i. P e c 00 βp ee Assuming (c 00 βp ee ) is constant ( 2nd order Taylor approximation ) reduces this to β = E [V ep e ] E [P 2 e ]. (11) Assume WLOG that E [P e ]=E [V e ]=1at e and recalling that E [A B] =E [A] E [B]+ cov(a, B), wecanwrite β = 1+cov(V e,p e ). (12) 1+var(P e ) The correlation coefficient between two variables a, b is defined as Using this, we can rewrite as (12) β = µ σvep e σ v e σ p e ρ ab = σ ab σ a σ b (13) σve σ p e +1 1+σ 2 p e = ρσ ve σ p e +1 1+σ 2 p e. (14) This the coefficient from a bivariate regression without an intercept... Key observations 1. If σ ve = σ pe and ρ =1,thenβ =1.That is, if V e,p e are perfectly correlated with identical variances, then we are back in the first-best world. (Measures don t need to be identical for this to be true, just proportional.) 2. Correlation of V e,p e is a key determinant of optimal piece rate. If the marginal product of effort on a performance measure is strongly correlated with the marginal product of effort on value, then the agent, who chooses effort level based on the value of P e, will choose high levels of effort when V e is high and low levels when V e low. 3. The piece rate β serves two functions: Oneistogettheagenttoexerteffort on average 9

Two is to get the agent to use her superior information in choosing her effort level. 4. This means that the piece rate can still be positive even when V e,p e are negatively correlated (so long as the marginal product of effort is positive on average). Example, from Baker: 2 states of world, equally likely. In one state, P e =5,V e =10 andintheotherp e =10,V e =5. So, the measures are perfectly negative correlated. Would you want β<0inthis case? No, because you still want positive effort on average. Marginal products are 7.5 on average, and optimal piece rate is 0.8. Comparison with standard PA model: If A risk neutral, there is no conflict of interest between P and A; first best achievable. Here, a conflict of interest arises even with risk neutrality because the piece rate does not perfectly align A s incentives with P s objectives (unless the correlation is one). So, even risk neutral agent facing a β of 1 could be induced to work too hard if the marginal value of effort for P is lower than the marginal value of effort for V.This would be inefficiently costly for the agent and principal. (Note that if c 00 =0,this would not be true. Convexity of effort function means that marginal cost of effort eventually rises faster than marginal product.) Trade-off: the Principal will reduce effort variation by reducing piece rate reduces incentives for effort but this is efficient. 3.4 Observableeffortcase When effort is observable, Principal could condition the agent s payoff on her effort choice. In the standard PA model, this would be first best efficient. If the Principal exerted first-best effort and this could be verified, pay could be independent of actual output could offer full insurance and full incentives. So, an input contract with monitoring solves incentive and participation constraint perfectly. 10

In the Baker model, that result will not hold. Because of the information asymmetry, the Principal still will not know the optimal level of effort because does not observe realization of. Can still reward e on average if observable, however. Consider this contract w = α + β 1 E [P e]+β s (P E [P e]). (15) This contract pays two separate piece rates: one for expected output conditional on effort, the other for the realization of output. Each piece rate serves a purpose. 1. β 1 causes the principal to exert the right level of effort on average 2. β 2 provides incentives to adjust effort level according to superior information about marginal productivity (due to observation of ). Optimal solutions for these parameters is β 1 = E [V e] E [P e ] =1, β 2 = ρ σ v e = σ v e p e σ pe σ σ σv e = σ v e p e, v e p e σ pe σ 2 v e whicharetheinterceptandslopecoefficients from a regression of V on P and a constant. So, observing effort allows the principal to improve the contract. (This contract would produce shirking if effort was not observable.) How do we know that this contract is more efficient than (14)? In the prior example, we could never have β < 0, if the marginal product of effort was positive on average. That s even true if V e and P e are perfectly negatively correlated. In this example, β 1 provides incentives for average effort and β 2 provides incentives for marginal effort. So, we could easily have a case where β 1 > 0 and β 2 < 0. And if we did, this would dominate the single instrument case where one β must trade off between solving these two problems simultaneously. This is an insightful and important paper (and elegant). 11

4 Prendergast 2002 JPE I will not develop the details of this paper. But it provides another insight into why the PA model is too parsimonious (and also an empirical failure). The contrast here is again between input and output monitoring. Recall from the PA model that input monitoring is preferred where there is high risk to the risk-averse agent and output monitoring when there is low risk. In the Prendergast model, there is again a large dimensional action space and again private information observed by the Agent about marginal products. Another key idea: input monitoring is cheaper than output monitoring. Why would this be true? Seems that the answer will vary with context. Under these assumptions, input monitoring will be preferred by Principal when she has a clear idea of the right actions to take. This reduces monitoring costs at not a great loss in efficiency. Problem: precisely in the riskiest settings where Principal does not have good information about what actions to take (e.g., sending a sales representative to a foreign country to develop a new line of business versus siting a McDonalds on the interstate). In these uncertain cases, the principal may choose output monitoring so as not to constrain agents superior information about actions. But this will shift risk to agents when risk is high opposite of PA model. The details of this model are not especially elegant but the point seems good. If you need references on order statistics, please ask me. 5 Conclusion As this lecture may underscore, the contracting issues we visited in the lectures on training investment and efficiency wage incentives are fairly rudimentary relative to the depth of the subject. As a labor economist, you should understand the fundamentals of incentive and 12

mechanism design, at least at the introductory level here. If you want further depth, I highly recommend the Organizational Economics and Contract Theory classes taught by Bob Gibbons. 13