ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

Similar documents
University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno. Economics 103: Economics of uncertainty and information PRACTICE PROBLEMS

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Economics Honors Exam Review (Micro) Mar Based on Zhaoning Wang s final review packet for Ec 1010a, Fall 2013

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals.

Best Reply Behavior. Michael Peters. December 27, 2013

Managerial Economics

PAPER NO.1 : MICROECONOMICS ANALYSIS MODULE NO.6 : INDIFFERENCE CURVES

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space.

Master in Industrial Organization and Markets. Spring 2012 Microeconomics III Assignment 1: Uncertainty

Exercises for Chapter 8

First Welfare Theorem in Production Economies

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

Characterization of the Optimum

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

MEASURES OF RISK-AVERSION

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Chapter 1 Microeconomics of Consumer Theory

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

E&G, Ch. 1: Theory of Choice; Utility Analysis - Certainty

Choice under risk and uncertainty

(a) Ben s affordable bundle if there is no insurance market is his endowment: (c F, c NF ) = (50,000, 500,000).

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department of Economics Principles of Microeconomics Final Exam Wednesday, October 10th, 2007

Preferences - A Reminder

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

UNIT 1 THEORY OF COSUMER BEHAVIOUR: BASIC THEMES

Choice under Uncertainty

Advanced Microeconomic Theory

ECONOMICS OF UNCERTAINTY AND INFORMATION

If Tom's utility function is given by U(F, S) = FS, graph the indifference curves that correspond to 1, 2, 3, and 4 utils, respectively.

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

Midterm 1 - Solutions

We want to solve for the optimal bundle (a combination of goods) that a rational consumer will purchase.

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

The trade-offs associated with getting an education

Insurance, Adverse Selection and Moral Hazard

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2009 examination. 2008/2009 syllabus

Utility Homework Problems

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July time : 1 hour. Do all 4 questions. All count equally.

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments

ECON Micro Foundations

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

Intro to Economic analysis

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

not to be republished NCERT Chapter 2 Consumer Behaviour 2.1 THE CONSUMER S BUDGET

Midterm 2 (Group A) U (x 1 ;x 2 )=3lnx 1 +3 ln x 2

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

a. Show the budget set containing all of the commodity bundles that the following individuals can afford.

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

ECON 301: General Equilibrium V (Public Goods) 1. Intermediate Microeconomics II, ECON 301. General Equilibrium V: Public Goods

You may not start to read the questions printed on the subsequent pages of this question paper until instructed that you may do so by the Invigilator

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

12.2 Utility Functions and Probabilities

CONSUMPTION THEORY - first part (Varian, chapters 2-7)

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d

AS/ECON AF Answers to Assignment 1 October Q1. Find the equation of the production possibility curve in the following 2 good, 2 input

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Mock Examination 2010

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

UNCERTAINTY AND INFORMATION

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

Corporate Finance - Yossi Spiegel

Symmetric Game. In animal behaviour a typical realization involves two parents balancing their individual investment in the common

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Final Exam Economic 210A, Fall 2009 Answer any 7 questions.

2c Tax Incidence : General Equilibrium

Total /20 /30 /30 /20 /100. Economics 142 Midterm Exam NAME Vincent Crawford Winter 2008

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Theoretical Tools of Public Finance. 131 Undergraduate Public Economics Emmanuel Saez UC Berkeley

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

Economic Development Fall Answers to Problem Set 5

Problem Set 3 Solutions

International Macroeconomics

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Answers To Chapter 7. Review Questions

Chapter Four. Utility Functions. Utility Functions. Utility Functions. Utility

Mean-Variance Portfolio Theory

CHAPTER 6: RISK AVERSION AND CAPITAL ALLOCATION TO RISKY ASSETS

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

I. The Money Market. A. Money Demand (M d ) Handout 9

Foundational Preliminaries: Answers to Within-Chapter-Exercises

Transcription:

University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno Economics 03: Economics of uncertainty and information TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo PROBLEM # : The expected value of the lottery: 8 6 6 6 6 6 is 8 6 8 6 6 6 6 PROBLEM # : The expected value cannot be computed because the prizes or basic outcomes are not numbers. PROBLEM # 3: The decision not to buy insurance is the decision to face the following lottery: with probability 0.9 Shirley s wealth will be $00,000, with probability 0. it will be $5,000. The expected value of this lottery is: 0.9 (00,000) + 0. (5,000) = $9,500. The insurance policy guarantees a wealth of 00,000 7,500 = 9,500. Hence Shirley will buy the insurance policy if she is risk-averse, will be indifferent between buying and not buying if she is risk-neutral and will prefer not to buy if she is risk-loving. PROBLEM # : If Bill refuses to invest his wealth is $,000 for sure. If Bill gives $0,000 to Bob to $, 000 $8, 000 invest then he faces the following lottery: L. The expected value of L is 88% % 88, 000 8, 000 $, 600. If Bill were risk averse he would prefer $,600 for sure to 00 00 the investment (lottery L) and obviously he will prefer $,000 to $,600; thus he would prefer $,000 for sure to the investment; since he decides to go ahead with the investment he is not risk averse. If Bill were risk neutral he would be indifferent between $,600 for sure and the investment (lottery L) and obviously he will prefer $,000 to $,600; thus he would prefer $,000 for sure to the investment; since he decides to go ahead with the investment he is not risk averse. Hence Bill is risk-loving. PROBLEM # 5: (a) First of all note that the initial wealth is W =,600 and the potential loss is x =,600,0 = 576. We write each point as a pair ( h, D ) where h W W is the premium and D W W is the deductible. Thus (0,576) A 600 556, 556 390 (,66), NI, B 600 80, 80 390 (0,90), 600 390 0, 0 A. Page of 8

(b) The expected profit from a contract ( h, D ) is h p( x D). Thus ( NI) 0, ( A) 38, ( B).8 and ( C) 9.8. p 5 (c) All the isoprofit lines are straight lines and all have the same slope given by. p 5 Thus starting at a point W, W, if you reduce W to 0 then the vertical coordinate changes to W W, yielding the vertical intercept. Applying this to point NI we get that by reducing the horizontal coordinate by,0, the vertical coordinate increases by,0 56 to,600 + 56 =,856. Hence the equation of the isoprofit line that goes through point NI (which is the zeroprofit line) is W,856 W. Applying the same procedure we get that Equation of isoprofit line through A Equation of isoprofit line through B Equation of isoprofit line through C W W W,903.5 W,87.5 W,735.5 W PROBLEM # 6: Since Ben prefers B to A, he must prefer D to C. Proof: Let V be a vonneumann-morgenstern utility function that represents Ben's preferences. Let V(,000) = a, V(3,000) = b, V(0) = c. We can safely assume that a > b > c (more money is better). Define the function U as follows: c U(x) = V(x) a c a c. Then U represents the same preferences as V. Hence we can work with U. Now, U(000) = U(0) = V(0) c a c V(000) c a c = a c a c = c c a c = 0. =, U(3000) = V(3000) c a c = b c a c, b c Let q =. Then 0 < q <. Thus a c U(000) =, U(3000) = q (with 0 < q < ) and U(0) = 0. [You could have started directly with this normalized utility function without going through the normalization procedure.] Now (EU stands for Expected Utility), EU(A) = 0.8 U(000) + 0. U(0) = 0.8, EU(B) = U(3000) = q. Since Ben prefers B to A, it must be q > 0.8. Let us now compare C and D: EU(C) = 0. U(000) + 0.8 U(0) = 0., EU(D) = 0.5 U(3000) + 0.75 U(0) = 0.5 q. Since q > 0.8, it follows that 0.5q > (0.5)(0.8) = 0.. Hence EU(D) > EU(C). Page of 8

PROBLEM # 7: Suppose that there is a vonneumann-morgenstern utility function U that represents Jennifer s preferences. We can normalize it so that U(3000)= and U(500)=0. Since Jennifer is indifferent between L and $000, U(000) = 5 6. Since she is indifferent between L and $000, U(000) = 3. Thus EU(L 3 ) = () + 5 6 + 3 + 0 = 5 8 and EU(L ) = 0 () + 5 6 + 3 + 0 (0) = 3. 3 Since > 5 8, Jennifer should prefer L over L 3. Hence she is not rational according to the theory of expected utility. PROBLEM # 8: Normalize her utility function so that U(z ) = and U(z ) = 0. Then, since Rachel is indifferent z z z between and 8, we have that U(z ) = 8. Similarly, since she is indifferent 0 0 0 z z z3 between and, U(z 3 ) = z z z3 z. Then the expected utility of L 3 is 8 8 8 8 z z z3 8 3 0 0.55 while the expected utility of L 3 is 8 8 0 8 8 80 5 5 5 3 8 39 0.78. Hence she prefers L 5 5 0 5 50 to L. PROBLEM # 9: (a) The expected value of L is 30 8 8 8 8. The expected value 0 0 0 0 0 of L is 30 8 5 8 8.. Hence a risk-neutral person would prefer L 0 0 0 to L. (b) The expected utility of L is 5 while the expected utility of L is 0 (c) The graph of ln(m) is as follows: ln ( 30 ) ln 8 0 ( ) ln 0 ( ) ln 8 5 ( ) 5 ln( 8).7 ln ( 30 ) ln 8 5 ( ) ln( 8).73. Thus Paul prefers L to L. Page 3 of 8

.303 3 ln( m) 0 0.303 3 0 3 5 6 7 8 9 0 0. m 0 (d) d ln( m). (e) dm m d ln( m). dm m PROBLEM # 0: (i) u(x) = x ½, u(x) = ½ x ½, u(x) = risk-aversion. (ii) u(x) = ln(x), u(x) = x x 3/ = < 0 hence concave, thus x3, u(x) = x < 0 hence concave, hence risk-aversion. (iii) u(x) = x, u(x) = x, u(x) = > 0 hence convex, hence risk-loving. (iv) u(x) = 5x +, u (x) = 5, u(x) = 0 hence straight line, hence risk-neutral. PROBLEM # : (i) U(x) = x + 0, (ii) V(x) = 6x +6 0, (iii) Since V(x) = a U(x) + b preferences. U(x) = < 0. Risk averse. V(x) = 6 < 0. Risk averse. Thus they have the same attitude to risk. with a = 3 and b =, V(x) and U(x) represent the same (iv) U(x) = x, V(x) = ln(x). The second derivative is negative in both cases, hence both display risk-aversion. On the other hand, it is not possible to find two numbers a > 0 and b such that U(x) = a V(x) + b (for all x) hence they do not represent the same preferences. (v) We already saw that U and V represent the same preferences. This is confirmed by the Arrow-Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion: it is the same for both. In fact, U''(x) U'(x) = V''(x) V'(x) = x. Page of 8

PROBLEM # : 8 6 The expected value of the lottery 3 is 3 8 0(6). 0 6 6 6 6 6 6 (a) The risk premium is 8 = $. (b) Amy is risk-averse since she considers the lottery to be equivalent to a sum of money which is less than the expected value of the lottery (hence she prefers the expected value of the lottery for sure to the lottery). PROBLEM # 3: (a) The expected value of both lotteries is 8, hence Bill considers them to be equivalent (i.e. he is indifferent between the two). (b) Zero. (c) Zero PROBLEM # : (a) The expected value of L is 30 8 8 8 8. 0 0 0 0 0 (b) The expected utility of L is 30 8 8 8.09. 0 0 0 0 0 (c) The risk premium is the value of r that solves the following equation: 8 r.09. Thus r = $.. (d) (g) (h) d m d m. (e) < 0 for every m > 0. (f) Jennifer is risk averse. dm 3 m dm m 3 U( m) RA( m) m 0. U( m) m m RA(900). RA(, 600). (900),800 (, 600) 3, 00 PROBLEM # 5: (a) Obviously, the expected value is still 8. (b) The expected utility of L is (0 30 ) (0 8 ) (0 ) (0 8 ) (0 8 ) 77.88. 0 0 0 0 0 Note that this is equal to 0(.09) (recall that.09 was the expected utility with the function U ( m) m ). (c) The risk premium is the value of r that solves the following equation: 0 8 r 77.88. Thus r = $. (same as with the function U ( m) m ). d 0 (d) (0 m ) 0. dm m m Page 5 of 8

d 5 (e) (0 m ) 0 < 0 for every m > 0. dm 3 3 m m 5 3 V ( m) (f) John is risk averse. (g) RA( m) m 0 (same as before). V ( m) 0 m m (h) RA(900). RA(, 600) (same as before). (900),800 (, 600) 3, 00 Comments: the utility function V ( m) 0 m represents the same preferences as the utility function U ( m) m (in fact V(m) can be obtained from U(m) by multiplying the latter by 0 and subtracting ). Thus anything which is true for Jennifer is also true for John (e.g. risk attitude, ranking of any two lotteries, risk premium, measures of risk aversion, etc.). In an exam, if you are given the utility function V ( m) 0 m you can simplify your life by transforming it to the equivalent function U ( m) m and then use the latter for your calculations. PROBLEM #6: 0 0 (a) The expected utility of lottery A 3 3 0 0 (b) The expected utility of lottery B 3 3 (c) and (d). The indifference curve that goes through A is the set of lotteries that yield an expected utility of 3.7. It is a convex curve since the function U displays risk aversion. The slope of the indifference curve at point A p U(0) is equal to 3 0 p U (0) 3 0. Similarly, the indifference curve that goes through B is the set of lotteries that yield an expected utility of.303. It is a convex curve. The slope of the indifference curve at point B is equal to p U (0). p U (00) 3 0 3 0 is ln 0 3 ( ) ln 0 3 ( ) 3.7 is ln 0 3 ( ) ln 0 3 ( ).303. 0 0 z (-p) 0 slope -(/) slope - 5 degree line y (p) PROBLEM # 7: Since the individual is risk neutral, we can take his utility-of-money function to be the identity function U(m) = m. Thus the expected utility of a lottery coincides with the expected value. Page 6 of 8

(a) The expected utility of lottery 0 0 A 3 3 is 0 0 90 30 3 3 3 0 0 (b) The expected utility of lottery B is 0. 3 3 (c) and (d). The indifference curve that goes through A is the set of lotteries whose expected value is 30. It is a straight line with slope. Similarly, the indifference curve that goes 3 3 through B is the set of lotteries whose expected value is 0. It is a straight line with slope z (-p). 0 5 degree line slope -(/) 0 0 y (p) slope -(/) PROBLEM # 8: W W x If he does not buy insurance he faces the lottery whose expected value is (W p p px). If h * is the maximum premium he is willing to pay for insurance [that is, h * is the solution to the equation U ( W h) ( p) U ( W ) pu ( W x) ] and r is the risk premium associated with the no insurance lottery [that is, r is the solution to the equation Page 7 of 8

U ( W px r) ( p) U ( W ) pu ( W x) ], then h * = px + r. Thus we have the following equation 800 500 0 x, which gives x = 3,000. PROBLEM # 9: (i) The probability of the loss is 0.05, the size of the loss is $0,000. Thus the expected loss is 0,000 (0.05) = $5,500. (ii) (iii) Bob s expected wealth if he does not buy insurance is: (0.05) 85,000 + (0.95) 95,000 = 89,500. Bob s expected utility if he does not buy insurance is: (0.05) [800 (0 8.5) ] + (0.95) [800 (0 9.5) ] = 793.5. (iv) If Bob buys full insurance for $5,500, he is guaranteed a wealth of $89,500. Thus his utility is [800 (0 8.95) ] = 798.8975. (v) Since 798.8975 > 793.5, Bob would indeed by insurance if the premium were $5,500. (vi) To find the maximum premium Bob is willing to pay, we need to solve the following equation with respect to h (the LHS is Bob s expected utility if he does not buy insurance): 793.5 = 800 [0 h)]. The solution is h = $,73: almost four times the expected loss! An alternative way of obtaining the same answer is the following. Solve the following equation with respect to w: 793.5 = 800 (0 w) The solution is w = 7.387. Thus if Bob were guaranteed a wealth of $73,87, his utility would be the same as his expected utility without insurance. Thus Bob is willing to pay up to $(95,000 73,87) = $,73 for full insurance. PROBLEM # 0: (a) 0.9 80, 000 0. 60, 000 79.053 (b) Expected utility from a policy with premium h and deductible D is 0.9 80, 000 h 0. 80, 000 h D Substituting the values from the possible policies we get: premium deductible expected utility,30 500 78.586, 80, 000 78.603, 0,500 78.6,60, 000 78.637 None of the policies gives her a higher expected utility than no insurance. Hence she will not buy insurance. Page 8 of 8

PROBLEM # : u(z) = a b e z (a>0, b>0), u(z) = b e z > 0, u(z) = b e z < 0 thus risk-averse. Absolute risk aversion: u'' u' =, hence constant. The maximum premium h is determined by the solution to: u(w h) = p u(w x) + ( p) u(w), i.e. a b e w+h = pa b e w+x + ( p) a b e w = pa + (p)a b p e w+x + (p) e w. Thus: a b e w+h = a b p e w+x + (p) e w. Subtract a from both sides and then multiply by b : e w e h = p e w e x + (p) e w. Multiply both sides by e w to obtain e h = p e x + (p). Thus: h = ln (p e x + p) hence independent of w. PROBLEM # : Expected utility from policy (h, D) with h = 0.8 0.D is: f(d) = 6 ln[0 D (0.8 0.D)] + 5 6 ln[0 (0.8 0.D)]. Optimal deductible given by the solution to f (D) = 0, i.e. 5 0 0 0 6 0 D ( 0. 8 0. D) (. ) 6 0 ( 0. 8 0. D) (. ) which gives D =.9 and h = 0.8 0.(.9) = 0.6. PROBLEM # 3: The expected utility from choosing a contract with deductible D is f ( D) ( p)ln( w h) p ln( w h D) where h = p( + k)(x D). The optimal deductible is given by the solution to f '( D) 0. d Recall that ln( x). dx x (a) if w = 0, x =, p = 6, k = 5, then h = p( + k)(x D) = D D. 6 5 5 5 5 6 6 Thus ( ) ln 0 D ln 0 D ln D f D D ln D 6 5 6 5 6 5 6 5. 5 5 f '( D) 6 6 D 5 6 6 D 5 6 6 D 6 6 D 5 5 5 This is equal to zero when, that is, when 5(6 D) (6 D), 6 D 6 D that is, when D = 6 5 =.9 and h = = 0.6 (same as in Problem 8) Page 9 of 8

(b) if w =, x = 6, p = 9, k = 8, then 8 86 D 86 7D f ( D) ln ln 9 8 9 8 The solution to f '( D) 0 is D = 6.95 which gives a premium of 8 h 0.38. PROBLEM # : 700 Contract A gives rise to the following lottery for the Agent: and therefore an expected utility of V (700) (700) 0. The lottery for the Principal is, 00 700, 600 700 900 700, 700 900 00 with corresponding expected 5 5 5 5 5 5 utility of EU ln(, 700) ln(900) ln(00) 6.38. 5 5 5, 00, 000 00 Contract B gives rise to the following lottery for the Agent: and therefore 5 5 5 an expected utility of EV (, 00) (,000) (00). The lottery for the 5 5 5, 00, 00, 600, 000 900 00, 00 600 700 Principal is with 5 5 5 5 5 5 corresponding expected utility of EU ln(, 00) ln(600) ln(700) 6.597. 5 5 5 Thus both Principal and Agent prefer contract B to contract A, that is, contract A is Pareto dominated by contract B. PROBLEM # 5: (a) Since U( m) 0, John is risk averse. 3 m (b) Since V ( m) 0, Joanna is risk neutral. (c) Contract A gives rise to the following lottery for John:,000, 000 3, 000, 600, 000 600 with corresponding expected utility of 3 3 3, 000 600.68. Joanna s utility from contract A is V(,000) = (,000) =,000. 3 3,000,500,500, 600 Contract B gives rise to the following lottery for John: with 3 3 corresponding expected utility of,500,600 6.67. Thus John prefers contract B. 3 3 Page 0 of 8

,500 0 For Joanna contract B gives rise to the following lottery with corresponding 3 3 expected utility of V (,500) V (0) (,500) (0) 000. Thus Joanna is indifferent 3 3 3 3 between the two contracts. (d) The theory of optimal risk sharing says that if one party is risk neutral and the other risk averse, then Pareto efficiency requires that the risk-averse party be guaranteed a fixed income. This principle, however, applies only if the contract is in the interior of the Edgeworth box. There are also Pareto efficient contracts that lie on the long side of the Edgeworth box and off the 5 o line for the risk -averse person. In the case under consideration, the set of Pareto-efficient contracts is shown as the thick line in the following figure:,600 Contract B has coordinates (w =,500, w = 0) (from the point of view of the Agent) or (x w =,500, x w =,600) (from the point of view of the Principal) and is thus on the horizontal part of the thick line. Hence contract B is Pareto efficient. (Contract B would not be Pareto efficient if the Agent had some savings she could draw from to pay the Principal if the profits turned out to be $,600: in that case there is a contract outside the box that Pareto dominates contract B.) PROBLEM # 6: (a) The Principal is risk-averse, since U( m) 0. m x 00 (b) The Agent is also risk-averse, since V ( m) e d x x 0 (recall that e e ). 00 dx x U( x w ) V ( w ) (c) Pareto efficiency requires. Now, U 00 ( m) and V ( m) e. Thus U( x w ) V ( w ) m U( x w ) U(600) 600 00 = 0.67 while U( x w ) U(00) 00 600 3 Thus the contract is not Pareto efficient. V ( w ) V (00) e V ( w ) V (00) e e 0.35. Page of 8

(d) From the above calculations we see that the Principal s indifference curve through the proposed contract is steeper than the Agent s indifference curve. Thus any contract in the shaded region is Pareto superior to the given contract. Hence w should be decreased and w should be increased. w = 00 indifference curve of the Agent origin for the Agent w = 00 origin for the Principal slope of A's indiff. curve slope of P's indifference curve indifference curve of Principal (i) (ii) (iii) P s expected utility is: 3 0 A s expected utility is: 3 (50) + 7 6 PROBLEM # 7: 50-50 + 7 0 00-80 =.0 3 0 + 3 (80) + 7 6 7 0 = 53.9375 A necessary condition for there not to exist a Pareto superior contract is that U(70) U(0) = V(50) V (80). Now, U (y) = V(w) = 3 for every w. U(70). Thus y U(0) = 0 70 = 0.67. Thus V(50) V (80) = 3 3 =. Hence the above condition is not satisfied and there is a Pareto superior contract. Page of 8

3 0 Notice that P is risk-averse and is facing a lottery that gives him $70 with probability 7 and $0 with probability 0. The expected value of the lottery is $06.5. Thus if given $06.5 for sure, P will be better off. On the other hand, since A is risk-neutral, she will be indifferent between the original contract (that gives her $50 with probability 3/0 and 80 with probability 7/0, with expected value 77.75) and a contract that gives P $06.5 for sure (so that A would get $33.75 with probability 3/0 and would pay $6.5 with probability 7/0, with expected value 77.75). Thus a Pareto superior contract is the following: A will get $33.75 if the firm s profit is $50 and will pay $6.5 if the firm s profit is $00. This contract leaves Ms. A as well off as before, but makes P better off. The following contract is an example of a contract that is preferred by both: A gets $30 if the outcome is $50, otherwise she gets nothing. Then P s expected utility will be (he will be getting $00 in every case): while A s expected utility will be 00 =. >.0 3 (30) + 7 6 3 0 + 3 (0) + 7 6 7 0 = 553.69 > 53.9375. Let R, S and T denote the following contracts: R = Ms. A gets $50 if the profit is $50, otherwise she gets $80. S = Ms. A gets $33.75 if the profit is $50, otherwise she pays $6.5. T = Ms. A gets $30 if the profit is $50, otherwise she gets nothing. These contracts are represented in the following Edgeworth box. Page 3 of 8

06.5 _ 6.5 00 50 0 80 00 06.5 70 How on earth did I think of these two points, S and T? Well, the original contract gives Mr. P $70 with probability (3/0) and $0 with probability (7/0). The expected value of this lottery is: (3/0) 70 + (7/0) 0 = 06.5. Being risk-averse, Mr. P would prefer to get $06.5 for sure, that is, would prefer to be at point S (on the 5 o line through 0 P ). Since S is not in the box, the point in the box which is closest to S and also on the 5 o line through 0 P is T. Simple, isn t it? PROBLEM # 8: (i) The Agent s utility is zero, while the Principal s expected utility is: 6 5 + 3 6 3 + 6 = 0.9. [Note: what sum of money for sure would the Principal consider equivalent to this lottery? That sum of money x such that x = 0.9. Thus x = (0.9) = 0.88. (ii) Since the Principal is risk-averse and the Agent is risk-neutral, Pareto efficiency requires that the Agent bear all the risk (i.e. the Principal must be guaranteed a fixed income). An optimal contract would be, for example: w = x 0.88 (so that the Principal gets $0.88 in every state with a utility of 0.88 = 0.9). The Agent therefore would get: 6 5 0.88 3 + 6 3 0.88 + 6 ( 0.88 ) = 0.0 Page of 8

PROBLEM # 9: (i) Under contract C the Agent s utility is V ($0) 0, while the Principal s utility is 0 6 0 6 0 65 0 79 0 ( 5 7) 9. 5 5 5 5 5 5 (ii) Under contract D the Agent s utility is 3 5 0 5 60 and thus the Agent prefers contract D to contract C. Under contract D the Principal s utility is: 5 6 6 65 60 79 60 9.37. Thus also the Principal prefers contract D to contract C. Hence contract D is Pareto superior to contract C. PROBLEM # 30: CONTRACT A. If the Agent works hard, he will get a utility of V(0,H) = 90+0 0 = 0 0 = 0. If he does not work hard, his utility will be: V(0,L) = 90+0 9 = 0 9 =. Since > 0, he will choose e = L, that is, he will not work hard. The Principal can figure this out and will realize that his expected utility from this contract is: ½ (00 0) + ¼ (00 0) + ¼ (500 0) = 90. CONTRACT B. If the Agent works hard, his expected utility will be: ¼ ( 90 0) + ¼ ( 90 0) + ½ ( 90+00 0) =.635. If he does not work hard, his expected utility will be: ½ ( 90 9) + ¼ ( 90 9) + ¼ ( 90+00 9) =.56. Since.635 >.56, he will choose e = H, that is, he will work hard. The Principal can figure this out and will realize that his expected utility from this contract is: ¼ (00) + ¼ (00) + ½ (500 00) = 00. Thus contract B is Pareto superior to contract A, despite the fact that it does not allocate risk optimally. Page 5 of 8

PROBLEM # 3: CONTRACT A If Ms. Managy is lazy she will get a utility of 08 =, if she works hard she will get a utility of 0 0 =. Hence she will be lazy. Mr. Owny s expected utility will be: (0) + (00 0) + (800 0) = 5. CONTRACT B If Ms. Managy is lazy she will get an expected utility of: (8) + (8) If she works hard she will get an expected utility of: Hence she will work hard. (0) + (0) + ( 8) =. + ( 0) =. Given that she will work hard, Mr. Owny s expected utility will be: 0 + 00 + (800 ) = 3. Hence Ms. Managy would be indifferent between the two contracts (and accept either of them), while Mr. Owny prefers contract B. Unlike Contract A, Contract B provides Ms. Managy with the incentive to work hard. PROBLEM # 3: (a) From column E in the following table we get that she should plan to work for at least 5 years after obtaining the Master s degree (thus 7 years into the future). (b) From column G in the following table we get that she should plan to work for at least years after obtaining the Master s degree (thus 3 years into the future). Page 6 of 8

A B C D E F G Year Master degree cost/benefit current job (opportunity cost) Net benefit of MBA Cumulative net benefit Discounted benefit Cumulative discounted benefit -0,000 0,000-60,000-60,000-5,7-5,7-0,000 0,000-60,000-0,000-5,369-97,53 3 65,000 0,000 5,000-95,000 6,38-8,05 65,000 0,000 5,000-70,000,9-66,8 5 65,000 0,000 5,000-5,000,9-5,38 6 65,000 0,000 5,000-0,000 0,808-3,573 7 65,000 0,000 5,000 5,000 9,398-3,75 8 65,000 0,000 5,000 30,000 8,73-6,00 9 65,000 0,000 5,000 55,000 7,07-8,896 0 65,000 0,000 5,000 80,000 6,80 -,76 65,000 0,000 5,000 05,000 5,37-7,3 65,000 0,000 5,000 30,000,673 -,670 3 65,000 0,000 5,000 55,000,063,393 65,000 0,000 5,000 80,000 3,533,97 PROBLEM # 33: Nobody will want to acquire a level of education y > y* or a level 0 < y < y*. Every individual will limit himself to choosing between y = 0 and y = y*. If choose y = 0 get w = pay C = 0 For a GROUP L individual If choose y = y* net wage = get w = pay C = y* net wage = y* For a GROUP H individual If choose y = 0 If choose y = y* get w = pay C = 0 net wage = get w = pay C = y* net wage = * y Page 7 of 8

* y * If y* is such that y* < and, that is, if y then group L individuals will choose y = 0 and group H individuals will choose y = y* and therefore the employers beliefs will be confirmed: people with low education will turn out to be of low productivity and people with high education will turn out to have high productivity. This is called a separating signaling equilibrium. PROBLEM # 3: The wage offered by the employer is represented by the thick lines in the following diagram: + y/ + y/ y 0 For example, if y 0 = 3, anybody with y = will be offered a salary of + / = (even if he belongs to Group II, because the employer does not know to which group the applicant belongs) and anybody with y = 6 will be offered a salary of + 6/ = 6 (even if he belongs to Group I). First of all, note that the only sensible choices are y = 0 and y = y 0. In fact, if you increase y by unit, you get an extra $(/) but you pay more than this (you pay $ if you belong to Group I and $ 0.5 if you belong to Group II). Decision for a Group I person: wage cost net income y = 0 + 0/ = 0 y = y 0 + y 0 / y 0 + y 0 / y 0 In equilibrium a Group I person chooses what the employer expects him to choose, namely y = 0. However, it must be in his interest to make this choice, i.e. it must be the case that > + yo yo Decision for a Group II person: wage cost net income y Page 8 of 8

y = 0 + 0/ = 0 y = y 0 + y 0 / y 0 / + y 0 / y 0 / In equilibrium a Group II person chooses what the employer expects him to choose, namely y = y 0. However, it must be in his interest to make this choice, i.e. it must be the case that + yo yo >. These two inequalities are simultaneously satisfied if and only if 3 < yo <. PROBLEM # 35: (a) 6,000 5,000,000 3,000. The expected value is $,000. 8 8 8 8 (b) No, because if the price is $3,800, only owners of cars of quality C and D will offer their,000 3, 000 cars for sale and thus buying a car means facing the lottery which has 5 5 an expected value of $3,00 (less than the price of $3,800). (c) Because of the adverse selection problem, only the lowest quality cars (those of quality D) will be traded. Any price P such that $,700 < P < $3,000 would lead to all and only cars of quality D being traded. Thus the total number of cars traded would be 00. PROBLEM # 36: (a) If the firm offers $0,00 then everybody will apply and the firm s expected profit will be 3 3 (5,000 0,00) (8, 000 0,00) (,900) (,00) $350 Thus the firm would lose money. (b) Clearly, requirement () amounts to w > 0,000. Since the firm cannot tell applicants apart, everybody will apply and for each applicant the firm will face a probability that the applicant is H and probability 3 that the applicant is L. Thus the expected profit from each hired worker is 3 3 (5,000 w) (8, 000 w) (5, 000) (8, 00) w $9,750 w. Thus requirement () is w > 0,000 and requirement () is 9,750 w > 0, i.e. w < 9,750. Obviously they are incompatible. Page 9 of 8

(c) Clearly, profits are zero (for each unit of output the firm collects $,000 from consumers and pays $,000 to the worker who produced it). [By the way, only H-workers would apply: see below.] (d) An H-worker will apply if and only if 5b 0,000, that is, if and only if b 800. Similarly, an L-worker will apply if and only if 8b 0,000, that is, if and only if b,.. Thus if b = $900, only H-workers apply. (e) Profits would be zero, because nobody would apply for a job at this firm! PROBLEM # 37: If price is Number of cars offered for sale Average quality of cars offered for sale. $500 (/8)00 = 5 000 $300 [(/8)+(3/8)]00=00 (/)000+(3/) 3000 = 750 $600 (6/8)00 = 50 (/6)000+(3/6)3000+(/6)000 = 366 $550 00 (all the cars) (/8)000+(3/8)(3000)+(/8)000+(/8)5000=365 $600 00 (all the cars) (/8)000+(3/8)(3000)+(/8)000+(/8)5000=365 PROBLEM # 38: (a) Since the owner of a car of quality =3 values the car at $,00, when P = $,700 she will not be willing to sell. Hence the answer is No. (b) The owner of a car of quality = values it at $800 and the owner of a car of quality = values it at $,600. Hence both qualities will be offered for sale. Thus the buyer faces the following lottery: 3 3 whose expected utility is: q q 3 3 q 9, 05, 700, 000 q 9, 05, 700, 000 36.86q 96.57.85q 96.57 7.99q The buyer will be willing to buy if 96.57 7.99q 905 95, that is, if q 0.965. So the answer is: Yes all the values of q less than or equal to 0.965. (c) No. If q 0.965 then both qualities = and = are traded and if q 0.965 then both qualities = and = are offered for sale, but buyers are not willing to buy. Page 0 of 8

PROBLEM # 39: (a) For a U type the expected utility of not insuring is 9 00 93, 600 00 93, 600 7, 00 3,800. Thus the maximum premium that 0 0 she is willing to pay for full insurance is given by the solution to 00 93, 600 h 3, 800 which is h = $,756. (b) If the premium is $3,50, it follows from part (a) that the U types will not apply for insurance. For a V type the expected utility of not insuring is 00 ln(93, 600) 00 ln(93, 600 7, 00),5.95. The utility from the 5 5 contract is 00 ln(93, 600 3, 50) 5.55685. Thus the V types will buy insurance and the monopolist s expected profits are ( nv ) 3, 50 (7, 00) nv 0nv 5. (c) We already know that the U types will not consider the full insurance contract. The partial insurance contract gives them an expected utility of 9 00 93, 600 5 00 93, 600 5 5000 3,800.807, higher than no 0 0 insurance. Thus they will buy the partial insurance contract. For the V type the partial insurance contract gives an expected utility of 00 ln(93, 600 5) 00 ln(93, 600 5 5, 000),5.6379, higher than 5 5 the expected utility from the full-insurance contract. Thus everybody will buy the partial insurance contract and the monopolist s expected profits are ( n, n ) 5 (7, 00 5, 000) n 5 (7, 00 5, 000) n 5 0 5n 5n u v u v u v (d) (00) $,000 and (,00) 500. Thus option (b) is better. (e) (00) $,000 and (,700) $,000. Thus option (c) is better. Page of 8

PROBLEM # 0: (a) If she chooses low effort, her utility is 0.5 80,000 36,000 0.85 80,000 7.88 and if she chooses high effort, her utility is 0.05 80, 000 36, 000 0.95 80, 000 78.89. Thus she will choose high effort. (b) Low effort, because her utility will be 80,000, 50 while with high effort it would be 80, 000, 50. (c) Yes, because her utility if she accepts it is 80,000, 50 78.837. The best alternative would be to remain uninsured and choose high effort with an expected utility of 78.89. (d) Since Emily will indeed buy insurance (and exert low effort), expected profits will be, 50 0.536, 000 3,50, that is, a loss. Thus it would not be a good idea for the insurance company to offer this contract. PROBLEM # : (a) If he chooses to spend $x on preventive measures his expected utility when not insured is x x NI( x) 0 ln 950,000 0, 000 x 0 ln 950, 000 x 0 5, 000 0 5, 000 Since NI(0) = 37.096, NI(00) = 37.37, NI(750) = 37.36 and NI(,000) = 37.9, of the four options he will choose x = $,000. (b) If he is fully insured at a premium of h then his utility if he does not spend any money on preventive measures is ln(950,000 h), while if he spends $x (with x > 0) then his utility is ln(950, 000 h x). Thus he will choose x = 0. (c) As determined in part (b), if he buys the full insurance contract with premium $0,000 then he will choose x = 0, so that his utility will be 0 ln(950, 000 0, 000) 0 ln(90, 000) 37.. This is less than the expected utility if he remains uninsured and spends $,000 on preventive measures (which is 37.9 as calculated in part a). Thus he will not accept the contract. Page of 8

PROBLEM # : (a) In the following figure the loss is denoted by rather than x: wealth in good state W NI indifference curve corresponding to effort E indifference curve coresponding to no effort W- wealth in bad state (b) The slope of the e-indifference curve at NI is pe U ( W x) 900 5 0.0877 p ( ) 9 e U W 57,500 (c) and the slope of the n-indifference curve is pn U ( W x) 900 5 0.85. p ( ) 9 n U W 7, 500 9 EU n( NI) 900,500 8 and 0 0 9 5 EU e( NI) 900,500 8.065. Thus she would exert effort. 0 0 6 (d) EUn( NI) 8 and exert effort. 9 3 EU e( NI) 900, 500 7.5. Thus she would not 0 0 (e) Using the calculations of part (c) contracts E and F are shown in the following figure: Page 3 of 8

W wealth in good state NI indifference curve corresponding to effort and utility level 8.065 F E indifference curve coresponding to NO effort and utility level 8 W- wealth in bad state (e.) The premium of contract E is given by the solution to which is h 99 (and zero deductible). 5,500 h 8.065 6 (e.) The premium of contract F is given by the solution to,500 h 8 which is h 96 (and zero deductible). (e.3) The customer will be indifferent between choosing NI with effort and contract E with effort and thus, given the assumption made, she will choose E and the monopolist s profits will be 99, 600 9. 0 (e.) The customer has the following options: () choose NI and no effort, with a corresponding utility of 8, () choose NI and effort, with a corresponding utility of 8.065, (3) choose contract F and no effort, with a corresponding utility of 8 and () 5 choose contract F and effort, with a corresponding utility of 8 6. Thus she will choose option (), that is, no insurance and the monopolist s profits will be zero. (e.5) Contract N is shown in the figure below: wealth in good state W NI indifference curve corresponding to effort and utility level 8.065 N E indifference curve coresponding to NO effort and and utility level 8.065 W- wealth in bad state The deductible is zero and the premium is given by the solution to,500 h 8.065 which is h = 89.99. Page of 8

PROBLEM # 3: Recall that if the highest offer so far is a wage of x, then one more search would give rise to one of the following two events: the event that the new offer, call it y, is less then or equal to x and the event that the new offer y is greater than x. If the first event occurs, you go back to the highest offer obtained so far, namely x. If the second event occurs you have to compute the expected wage. Now, CASE : the highest offer so far is w=0. Searching once more means playing the lottery 0 0 30 0 50 60 3 which has an expected value of 33.33. Thus it pays to search once more (you expect to increase the wage by 3.33 at a cost of 0.5). An alternative way of thinking about it is as follows. Prob{y 0}= and Prob{y > 0} =. Thus with probability the highest offer will remain 0, while with probability the highest offer will be greater than 0. Thus your expected wage if you search once more is (using Bayes rule): Prob{y0} 0 + Prob{y>0} [ 0 Prob{y=0} Prob{y=30} Prob{y=0} Prob{y=50} + 30 + 0 + 50 + 60 Prob{y=60} Prob{y>0} Prob{y>0} Prob{y>0} Prob{y>0} Prob{y>0} ] = Prob{y0} 0 +[ 0 Prob{y=0} + 30 Prob{y=30} + 0 Prob{y=0} + 50 Prob{y=50} ] = = 0 + 0 3 + 30 + 0 + 50 + 60 = 33.33. CASE : the highest offer so far is w=0. Searching once more means playing the lottery 0 30 0 50 60 which has an expected value of 3.6. [Alternatively, the expected wage from one more search can be computed as: 0 + 30 + 0 + 50 + 60 = 3.6.] CASE 3: the highest offer so far is w=30. Searching once more means playing the lottery 30 0 50 60 6 which has an expected value of 37.5. [Alternative computation: 6 30 + 0 + 50 + 60 = 37.5.] Thus it pays to search once more (expect to increase the wage by 7.5 at a cost of 0.5). CASE : the highest offer so far is w=0. Searching once more means playing the lottery 0 50 60 0 0 which has an expected value of.5. [Alternative computation: 0 + 50 + 60 =.5.] Thus it pays to search once more (expect to increase the wage by.5 at a cost of 0.5). Page 5 of 8

CASE 5: the highest offer so far is w=50. Searching once more means playing the lottery 50 60 which has an expected value of 50.83. [Alternative computation: 50 + 60 = 50.83.] Thus it pays to search once more (expect to increase the wage by 0.83 at a cost of 0.5). Thus the optimal strategy is to continue searching until offered a wage of 60, that is set a reservation wage of 60. PROBLEM # : x Let F(x) be the cumulative distribution function, that is, F(x) = f(t) dt. Thus 0 if x < 0 F(x) = x 0 50 if x[0,60] if x > 60 The optimal strategy is to keep searching until a wage of at least x * is found, where x * solves: [ F(x)] dx = 0.5. x * 60 x Now, F(x) = 50 and, for every z[0,60], 60 [ F(x)] dx = 60 x 50 dx = z z = 50 60 (60z (3600z ) = Thus x *, the reservation wage, is the solution to: 50 60 60 60 dx x dx z z = z 00 6 5 z + 36. z 00 6 5 z + 36 = 0.5. This quadratic equation has two roots: z = 55 and z = 65. Only the first one is in the range [0,60] hence x * = 55. Thus the optimal search strategy is: keep searching until you find a wage of at least 55 and then accept. Page 6 of 8

PROBLEM # 5: Let n be the number of searches already undertaken (n could be 0 or or or 3, etc.), that is, the number of firms approached so far. Highest salary offered so far 0 0 50 80 searching once more means playing the following lottery 0 0 50 80 0 3 0 0 0 0 50 80 5 0 0 0 50 80 9 0 0 80 expected value of lottery 8 53 80 expected salary gain 0 = 8 0 = 8 53 50 = 3 80 80 = 0 expected net gain x 8 x 3 x x utility if she does not search once more (and accepts highest offer so far) expected utility if she searches once more difference between row 7 and row 6 (Note: same as row 5!) 0 nx 0 nx 50 nx 80 nx nx x 8 nx x 53 nx x 80 nx x x 8 x 3 x x The optimal strategy, as a function of x, is as follows: Page 7 of 8

VALUE OF x x > x = OPTIMAL STRATEGY Do not search (not even once) Either do not search or search only once > x > Search once and accept whatever salary is offered. x = Either search once and accept whatever salary is offered, or keep searching until offered a salary of at least 0 then accept. > x > 8 Keep searching until offered a salary of at least 0 then accept. x = 8 Either keep searching until offered a salary of at least 0 and then accept, or keep searching until offered a salary of at least 50 and then accept 8 > x > 3 Keep searching until offered a salary of at least 50 and then accept x = 3 Either keep searching until offered a salary of at least 50 and then accept, or keep searching until offered a salary of 80 and then accept 3 > x 0 Keep searching until offered a salary of 80 and then accept. PROBLEM # 6: (a) We need to solve, 6 p 0, 6 for p. The solution is p = $,30. 68 (b) If she buys for $,00 her utility is,6, 00 80 0 68.5 If she searches a second time her expected utility is, 6, 00 60 0, 6, 900 60 0, 6,800 60 0 7.99 Thus she should search once more. Page 8 of 8