STX FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO Risk Aversion and the Purchase of Risky Insurance. Harris Schlesinger

Similar documents
Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies

MORAL HAZARD AND BACKGROUND RISK IN COMPETITIVE INSURANCE MARKETS: THE DISCRETE EFFORT CASE. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama.

Precautionary Insurance Demand with State-Dependent. Background Risk

A note on health insurance under ex post moral hazard

STX FACULTY WORKING! PAPER NO An Error-Learning Model of Treasury Bill Future* and Implications for the Expectation Hypothesis. nun.

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Explaining Insurance Policy Provisions via Adverse Selection

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

IS TAX SHARING OPTIMAL? AN ANALYSIS IN A PRINCIPAL-AGENT FRAMEWORK

Characterization of the Optimum

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion.

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

BACKGROUND RISK IN THE PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama. and. Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas

The Theory of Insurance Demand

UNIVERSITY OF. ILLINOIS LIBRARY At UrbanA-champaign BOOKSTACKS

Citation for published version (APA): Oosterhof, C. M. (2006). Essays on corporate risk management and optimal hedging s.n.

Mock Examination 2010

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

A Note on Ramsey, Harrod-Domar, Solow, and a Closed Form

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

This paper addresses the situation when marketable gambles are restricted to be small. It is easily shown that the necessary conditions for local" Sta

Choice under Uncertainty

Elasticity of risk aversion and international trade

Non-Expected Utility and the Robustness of the Classical Insurance Paradigm: Discussion

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

AMS Portfolio Theory and Capital Markets

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application

The Probationary Period as a Screening Device: The Monopolistic Insurer

In this chapter, we discuss the fundamental problem of adverse selection in health insurance.

E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space.

SOLVENCY, CAPITAL ALLOCATION, AND FAIR RATE OF RETURN IN INSURANCE

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

UNIVERSITY Of ILLINOIS LIBRARY AT URBANA-CHAMPA1GN STACKS

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013

Internet Appendix to: Common Ownership, Competition, and Top Management Incentives

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS SEPTEMBER 13, 2010 BASICS. Introduction

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

TIME AND RISK PREFERENCES IN THE COVERAGE. W. DAVID BRADFORD, PH.D. Department of Public Administration and Policy, University of Georgia.

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Section 9, Chapter 2 Moral Hazard and Insurance

Portfolio optimization problem with default risk

ECONOMICS 100A: MICROECONOMICS

Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited

ECONOMICS 100A: MICROECONOMICS

On Monopoly Insurance Pricing when Agents Differ in Risk Aversion

The demand for health insurance in a multirisk context

BEBR STX FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO FEB 1 9. Case of Program Trading. Empirical Evidence on Stock Index Arbitrage: The

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

EFFECTS OF RISK AVERSION ON VALUE OF INFORMATION IN TWO-ACTION DECISION PROBLEMS ZHENGWEI SUN DISSERTATION

A comparison of optimal and dynamic control strategies for continuous-time pension plan models

Transactions with Hidden Action: Part 1. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Modern Portfolio Theory

Total /20 /30 /30 /20 /100. Economics 142 Midterm Exam NAME Vincent Crawford Winter 2008

Equation Chapter 1 Section 1 A Primer on Quantitative Risk Measures

Background Risk and Insurance Take Up under Limited Liability (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Reinsuring Group Revenue Insurance with. Exchange-Provided Revenue Contracts. Bruce A. Babcock, Dermot J. Hayes, and Steven Griffin

Uncertainty. Contingent consumption Subjective probability. Utility functions. BEE2017 Microeconomics

FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 1069

Measuring and Utilizing Corporate Risk Tolerance to Improve Investment Decision Making

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

How do we cope with uncertainty?

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

* CONTACT AUTHOR: (T) , (F) , -

The concept of risk is fundamental in the social sciences. Risk appears in numerous guises,

The calculation of optimal premium in pricing ADR as an insurance product

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

Uncertainty Improves the Second-Best

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Essays on Risk Management for Insurance Companies

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

The Spillover Effect of Compulsory Insurance

ECON 5113 Microeconomic Theory

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Welfare Analysis of the Chinese Grain Policy Reforms

Adverse Selection in the Market for Crop Insurance

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

SWITCHING, MEAN-SEEKING, AND RELATIVE RISK

Moral Hazard and Risk Management. in Agri-Environmental Policy

The Welfare Cost of Asymmetric Information: Evidence from the U.K. Annuity Market

Leasing and Debt in Agriculture: A Quantile Regression Approach

Crop Insurance Contracting: Moral Hazard Costs through Simulation

A Note on the Relation between Risk Aversion, Intertemporal Substitution and Timing of the Resolution of Uncertainty

Bureaucratic Efficiency and Democratic Choice

Measuring farmers risk aversion: the unknown properties of the value function

The Disadvantages of Aggregate Deductibles

Initial Public Offerings With Bankruptcy Risk: The Entrepreneur's Problem. Paul D. Thistle * Department of Finance University of Nevada Las Vegas

Transcription:

STX FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 1348 *P«F?VOFTH Risk Aversion and the Purchase of Risky Insurance Harris Schlesinger J. -Matthias Graf v. d. Schulenberg College of Commerce and Business Administration Bureau of Economic and Business Research University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign

BEBR FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 1348 College of Commerce and Business Administration University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign April 1987 Risk Aversion and the Purchase of Risky Insurance Harris Schlesinger, Associate Professor Department of Finance J. -Matthias Graf v.d. Schulenburg International Institute of Management, Berlin

Abstract: This paper examines the choice of an insurance contract when insurers might default on indemnity claims. In particular, we show that more-risk-averse preferences do not necessarily lead to the purchase of higher levels of insurance coverage in such situations. Our results are shown not to apply in situations where the insured receives a premium refund for nonperforming insurance policies.

Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign http://www.archive.org/details/riskaversionpurc1348schl

1. INTRODUCTION Insurance purchased at "fair" prices is usually considered a method of reducing a particular financial risk. However, this need not be the case when insurance policies have a possibility of not paying indemnities for their claims. If there exists a chance that the individual will not be indemnified following a loss claim, then the purchase of insurance also introduces a new risk, which is the risk of losing premium dollars as well as experiencing the loss. Since a higher degree of risk aversion implies a greater relative emphasis on downside risk, an increase in the level of risk aversion, ceteris paribus, will not necessarily lead to the purchase of a higher level of insurance coverage a result which stands in marked contrast to the usual insurance literature. The purpose of this paper is to present this result more formally. Types of situations in which a nonpayment of insurance claims is possible include the following: (i) Insurer insolvency. In this case, the insurer has a probability of defaulting on claims, (ii) Questionable perils and hazards. Although most claims are clearly valid or not, some occurrences are questionable within the legal scope of which losses are covered and which are not. (iii) Contract conditions. Certain losses may not be covered under prescribed conditions. For example, there may be a waiting period before some loss is covered so that an

-2- occurrence during the waiting period is essentially uninsured. Each of the above possibilities might be known by the insured and reflected in lower insurance premiums; but the insurance market still remains incomplete since these losses cannot generally be covered. The model we use is essentially that of Doherty and Schlesinger (1986). Readers interested in a more complete development of tbe model are referred to this paper. 2. THE MODEL Consider a risk-averse individual with preferences expressed by the von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function U(W), U'>0, U"<0. We consider a simple three-state model in which no loss occurs with probability q, a loss that can be indemnified occurs with probability q, 9 and a loss that cannot be indemnified occurs with probability q. The size of the loss itself is assumed to be the same in states 2 and 3. Thus, our model is a variation of the simple two-state, loss vs. no-loss model, modified to account for the chance of nonpayment. The model abstracts from any potential moral-hazard and/or adverseselection problems, and the probabilities q, q and q. are assumed to be fixed and known. We should also point out that states 2 and 3 are identical when no insurance coverage is purchased. The consumer may protect against the loss by purchasing an insurance policy which promises to pay a fixed proportion a of the loss if it occurs. The complication is, of course, that there is a q /(l-q ) probability that the insurer does not pay on a loss claim.

-3- The individual's expected utility following the purchase of insurance is where EU = qjucwj) + q 2 U(W 2 ) + q 3 U(W 3 > (1) W = A - P W=A-P-L+aL W = A - P - L A = initial wealth level P = insurance premium L = magnitude of potential loss. Insurance prices are assumed to be proportional to the expected insurance payment so that P = maq L where m >_ 1. (2) Note that insurance prices also reflect the probability of nonpayment since they don't include q. Since we assume the premium to be given, we do not concern ourselves with the relationship between m and q_ here. The consumer's objective is to maximize expected utility (1) subject to the price schedule (2). The first-order condition is where p = U'(W 2 ) - [BU'CWj) + CU'(W 3 )] = 0, (3) B = mq /(1-mq ) and C = mq /(1-mq ). It is straightforward from (3) to show that full coverage is purchased only when both q 3 = Q (a zero chance of nonpayment) and m = 1

-4- (actuarially-f air insurance prices). Otherwise, less than full coverage is purchased. 3. INCREASED RISK AVERSION We now turn our attention to the main focus of the paper, namely how insurance purchases are affected by the consumer's level of risk aversion. To this end, let utility function V represent uniformly more risk-averse preferences than U. By Kihlstrom and Mirman (1974), there exists a concave function g such that V = g U. Consider now the marginal expected utility of V with respect to a, evaluated at the optimal insurance level under U, a*. dev da - g'[u(w 2 )] U'(W 2 ) (4) - {g'hkwj)] BU'Cwp +g'[u(w 3 )] cu»(w 3 )} We can assume, without loss of generality, that g'[u(w )] = 1. Thus, by the concavity of g, g'llkw^] < 1 < g»[u(w 3 )]. (5) Comparing (4) with (3), it follows from (5) that dev/da can be either positive or negative at a*. Thus, the optimal level of insurance coverage can be either higher or lower with the more riskaverse utility. This result stands in contrast to the more definitive result that more coverage is always purchased (whenever possible)

. -5- under more risk-averse preferences in models that don't allow for nonpayment of claims. Note that when nonpayment is impossible q = and thus comparing (4) with (3) it is trivial to show that more coverage is purchased under preferences V. 4. AN EXAMPLE We consider the following example to demonstrate our point that it is possible for a more risk-averse individual to purchase less insurance coverage if there is a positive probability of not being indemnified for a loss. Let us suppose the following utility function U(W) = -e~ 6W with 8 > 0. (6) This function has the property that the individual's absolute risk aversion as defined by Arrow and Pratt is given by the exponential coefficient 8 In our example, 8 will vary from 0.5 to 4.5. We further assume that A = 3.43, L = 1.43, m = 1.3 and q = 0.8. This implies a thirty percent loading on the net-premium and a loss-probability of 0.2. We will consider three different cases: q~ = 0, q = 0.02, and q_ = 0.06. The first case describes what standard insurance-economic theory normally assumes, that the insured will always be indemnified if a loss occurs. In the second and third case, a ten or thirty percent chance is respectively assumed that a loss occurs but the insurance company refuses to reimburse the individual.

-6- Computer simulation results are plotted in Figure 1. The upper curve shows the optimal level of insurance coverage for the case where q = 0. As is well known, a* increases as risk aversion increases. Insert Figure about here The optimal level of coverage is 0.52 for 3 = 0.5 and increases to 0.95 as 3 grows to 4.5. The second and third curves correspond to the cases where there is a positive probability that the insurer will not indemnify the insured's loss-claim. When q =.02, the optimal level of insurance coverage is increasing to a maximum of approximately 0.77 at 3 = 1.75 and decreases afterwards as absolute risk aversion. Similar results are seen to obtain for the case where q =.06 as well. 5. "MONEY BACK GUARANTEES" There is a provision in some actual life insurance contracts that suggests an interesting extension of our model. Under this provision, there is a return of the premium paid if the insured dies and the cause of death is excluded under the policy. Although we know of no similar provisions in property and liability insurance contracts, It is interesting to examine whether unambiguous comparative-static results hold (with respect to the degree of risk aversion) for the case where the premium is returned to the policyholder following the nonpayment of an insurance claim a "money back guarantee" of sorts. In this case, the actuarially-based premium is given by P = (moq 2 L)/(l-q ). (7)

7- It is straightforward to show that ^ a - mq.u'oo + [q. + (l-in)qju'(wj. (8) da li l l i From the proportionality condition (8) we see that the sign of deu/da is independent of q~. It follows trivially from (8) that full coverage is purchased whenever prices are actuarially fair (m=l) and partial coverage is purchased when prices are "loaded" (m>l), thus restoring the usual results of rational insurance purchasing (cf. Mossin (1968)). It is also straightforward to show from (8) that strictly-raore-riskaverse preferences would lead to the purchase of a higher level of insurance coverage, unless of course in=l, in which case full coverage is purchased with both utility functions. 3 6. CONCLUDING REMARKS We have shown that increased risk aversion does not necessarily imply a higher level of insurance coverage when insurers can default on indemnity payments. However, we should caution against making too much of our results in a practical sense. Our previous example shows an inverse relationship between the degree of risk aversion and the level of insurance coverage only for levels of risk aversion that are much higher than levels thought to be empirically valid. The probabilities of nonpayment by insurers in the example seem to also be unrealistically high. We were unable to obtain an example with parameter values in more realistic ranges. Thus, while we have shown that it is theoretically possible to see such inverse relationships between insurance levels and risk aversion, we might not expect to observe such results very often as a matter of practice.

-8- FOOTNOTES Second-order conditions are not trivially satisfied, but are assumed to hold. For a discussion of the complexities involved in the secondorder conditions, the reader is referred to Schlesinger (1985). 2 For a more complete analysis of insurance levels, see Doherty and Schlesinger (1986). 3 This is accomplished by substituting V = g o U for U in the righthand-side of the proportionality condition (8) and differentiating. Evaluating dev/da at the optimal coverage level for U shows that coverage should be increased.

-9- REFERENCES Doherty, N. A., H. Schlesinger (1986), "The Demand for Risky Insurance Policies," IIM/IP Discussion Paper, Wissenschaf tszentrum Berlin. Kihlstrom, R. E., J. Mirraan (1974), "Risk Aversion With Many Commodities, Journal of Economic Theory 3, 361-388. Mossin, J. (1968), "Aspects of Rational Insurance Purchasing," Journal of Political Economy 76, 553-568. Schlesinger, H. (1985), "Choosing a Deductible for Insurance Contracts: Best or Worst Insurance Policy," Journal of Risk and Insurance 52, 522-528. D/326A

Figure 1 : Optimal Insurance Purchasing and Risk-Aversion optimal insurance coverage (a*) 1.0 9 8 6 5 q 3 = 0,06 i T 0-5 1.0 1.5 2.0 2.5 i r~ 3.0 3.5 4.0 4.5 absolute risk- aversion (6)