EU i (x i ) = p(s)u i (x i (s)),

Similar documents
Notes on the Farm-Household Model

1 Dynamic programming

Slides III - Complete Markets

Graduate Macro Theory II: Two Period Consumption-Saving Models

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

NOTES ON THE FARM-HOUSEHOLD MODEL

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

Risk and Insurance in Village India

Optimal Risk in Agricultural Contracts

Consumption- Savings, Portfolio Choice, and Asset Pricing

Macro 1: Exchange Economies

Risk and Insurance Market Failures

14.05 Lecture Notes. Labor Supply

Labor Economics Field Exam Spring 2011

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Fall, 2010

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Dynamic Contracts. Prof. Lutz Hendricks. December 5, Econ720

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Linear Capital Taxation and Tax Smoothing

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Optimal Financial Contracts and The Dynamics of Insider Ownership

MACROECONOMICS. Prelim Exam

ECON 6022B Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions Fall 2011

1 Asset Pricing: Replicating portfolios

ECON385: A note on the Permanent Income Hypothesis (PIH). In this note, we will try to understand the permanent income hypothesis (PIH).

Lecture Notes - Insurance

1 Asset Pricing: Bonds vs Stocks

Final Exam (Solutions) ECON 4310, Fall 2014

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS SEPTEMBER 13, 2010 BASICS. Introduction

Problem Set 3. Thomas Philippon. April 19, Human Wealth, Financial Wealth and Consumption

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

Real Business Cycles (Solution)

Labor Economics Field Exam Spring 2014

Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Consumers

The stochastic discount factor and the CAPM

BACKGROUND RISK IN THE PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama. and. Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas

Assets with possibly negative dividends

Lecture Notes. Macroeconomics - ECON 510a, Fall 2010, Yale University. A Neo-Classical Benchmark Economy. Guillermo Ordoñez Yale University

Lecture 2: Stochastic Discount Factor

PhD Qualifier Examination

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Spring, 2016

UNIVERSITY OF OSLO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

Homework 3: Asset Pricing

Lecture 8: Asset pricing

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Preliminary Examination: Macroeconomics Fall, 2009

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

Period State of the world: n/a A B n/a A B Endowment ( income, output ) Y 0 Y1 A Y1 B Y0 Y1 A Y1. p A 1+r. 1 0 p B.

Lecture 2. (1) Permanent Income Hypothesis. (2) Precautionary Savings. Erick Sager. September 21, 2015

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Fire sales, inefficient banking and liquidity ratios

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013

Discussion of Optimal Monetary Policy and Fiscal Policy Interaction in a Non-Ricardian Economy

Complete nancial markets and consumption risk sharing

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours

Moral Hazard, Retrading, Externality, and Its Solution

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Comprehensive Examination: Macroeconomics Spring, 2009

MORAL HAZARD AND BACKGROUND RISK IN COMPETITIVE INSURANCE MARKETS: THE DISCRETE EFFORT CASE. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama.

Notes on Syllabus Section VI: TIME AND UNCERTAINTY, FUTURES MARKETS

A Baseline Model: Diamond and Dybvig (1983)

Microeconomic Foundations of Incomplete Price Adjustment

A unified framework for optimal taxation with undiversifiable risk

Final Exam. Consumption Dynamics: Theory and Evidence Spring, Answers

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Lecture Notes: November 29, 2012 TIME AND UNCERTAINTY: FUTURES MARKETS

Consumption-Savings Decisions and State Pricing

JEFF MACKIE-MASON. x is a random variable with prior distrib known to both principal and agent, and the distribution depends on agent effort e

Answer: Let y 2 denote rm 2 s output of food and L 2 denote rm 2 s labor input (so

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Characterization of the Optimum

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Risk Sharing Across Communities

Graduate Macro Theory II: The Basics of Financial Constraints

Asset Prices in Consumption and Production Models. 1 Introduction. Levent Akdeniz and W. Davis Dechert. February 15, 2007

Return to Capital in a Real Business Cycle Model

Development Economics Part II Lecture 7

Optimal Credit Market Policy. CEF 2018, Milan

Homework 2: Dynamic Moral Hazard

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Portfolio Investment

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

Monetary Economics Final Exam

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Bernanke and Gertler [1989]

Ramsey s Growth Model (Solution Ex. 2.1 (f) and (g))

Quantitative Significance of Collateral Constraints as an Amplification Mechanism

Disaster risk and its implications for asset pricing Online appendix

Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano

Lecture 2 General Equilibrium Models: Finite Period Economies

Final Exam Solutions

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Appendix to: Long-Run Asset Pricing Implications of Housing Collateral Constraints

THE PROBABILITY APPROACH TO GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM WITH PRODUCTION

Final Exam II (Solutions) ECON 4310, Fall 2014

FISCAL POLICY AND THE PRICE LEVEL CHRISTOPHER A. SIMS. C 1t + S t + B t P t = 1 (1) C 2,t+1 = R tb t P t+1 S t 0, B t 0. (3)

Transcription:

Abstract. Agents increase their expected utility by using statecontingent transfers to share risk; many institutions seem to play an important role in permitting such transfers. If agents are suitably risk-averse, then in the absence of any frictions the benchmark Arrow-Debreu model predicts that all risk will be shared, so that idiosyncratic shocks will have no effect on individuals; we call this full risk sharing. Real-world tests of full risk sharing tend to reject it; accordingly, researchers have devised models incorporating various frictions to try and explain the partial risk sharing evident in the data. Risk sharing Any two agents may be said to share risk if they employ state-contingent transfers to increase the expected utility of both by reducing the risk of at least one. A very wide variety of human institutions seem to play an important role in risk sharing, including insurance, credit, financial markets, and sharecropping in developing countries. To be precise, consider a set of agents indexed by i = 1,..., n each with von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function U i and a finite set of possible states of the world s = 1,..., S, each of which occurs with probability p(s). For simplicity, suppose that each agent i receives a quantity of a single consumption good x i (s) in state s, thus receiving expected utility S EU i (x i ) = p(s)u i (x i (s)), s=1 where x i denotes the random variable, {x i (s)} denotes its realizations, and E is the expectation operator. We assume that U i is strictly increasing, weakly concave, and continuously differentiable for all i = 1,..., n, so that all agents are at least weakly risk averse. Define the risk faced by agent i to be a quantity R i (x i ) = U i (Ex i ) EU(x i ). This cardinal measure orders probability distributions in the same manner as Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970). We say that i faces idiosyncratic risk if R i (x i ) > 0 and corr(u i(x i ), U j(x j )) < 1 for some j, where U j denotes j s marginal utility. If any agent i bears idiosyncratic risk, then there exists a set of state-contingent transfers of the consumption 1

good between i and j, {τ j i (s)} which will strictly increase the expected utility of each, while strictly decreasing the risk of at least one of i and j. Implementing such transfers is risk sharing. 2 Full risk sharing What might be termed full risk-sharing (Allen and Gale, 1988; Rosenzweig, 1988) is a situation in which all idiosyncratic risk is eliminated. While agents may still face risk, this risk is shared, so that marginal utilities of consumption are perfectly correlated across all agents. Full risk-sharing is a hallmark of any Pareto efficient allocation in an Arrow- Debreu economy, provided that agents have von Neumann-Morgenstern preferences, no one is risk-seeking, and at least one agent is strictly risk averse. Let us establish the necessity of full risk-sharing for any interior Pareto efficient allocation in a simple multi-period endowment economy. The environment is similar to that described above, but agents consume in several periods indexed by t = 1,..., T, with agent i discounting future expected utility using a discount factor β i. Different states of the world are realized in each period, with the probability of state s t {1,..., S} being realized in period t allowed to depend on the period, and so given by p t (s t ). Then consider the problem facing a social planner, who assigns state-contingent consumption allocations to solve max {(c it (s))} n i=1 λ i T t=1 β t 1 i subject to the resource constraints S p t (s t )U i (c it (s t )) s t=1 n c it (s t ) i=1 n x it (s t ), i=1 which must be satisfied at every period t and state s t ; the planner takes as given the initial state s 0 and a set of positive weights {λ i }. By varying these weights one can compute the entire set of interior Pareto efficient allocations (Townsend, 1987). If we let µ t (s t ) denote the Lagrange multiplier associated with the resource constraint for period t in state s t, then the first order conditions for the social planner s problem are (1) λ i β t 1 i p t (s t )U i(c it (s t )) = µ t (s t ).

Since this condition must be satisfied in all periods and states for every agent, it follows that U i(c it (s t )) = λ ( ) t 1 j βj U λ i β j(c it (s t )) i for any period t, any pair of agents (i, j) and any state s t, so that corr(u i(c it ), U j(c jt )) = 1, and we have full risk-sharing. Thus far, we ve only considered risk-sharing in the context of an endowment economy. However, the thrust of the claims advanced above holds much more generally. If we were, for example, to add production and some kind of intertemporal technology (e.g., storage), the first order conditions of the planner s problem with respect to state-contingent consumptions (1) would remain unchanged the effect of these changes would be that the Lagrange multipliers {µ t (s t )} would change. This is an illustration of what is sometimes called separability between production and consumption, which typically prevails only when there is full risk sharing (see, e.g., Benjamin, 1992). Risk sharing can also be thought of as a means to smooth consumption across possible states of the world. This suggests a connection to the permanent income hypothesis, which at its core involves agents smoothing consumption across periods. And indeed, it s easy to show that full risk sharing in every period implies the kind of smoothing across periods implied by the consumption Euler equation. However, the consumption Euler equation doesn t imply full risk sharing. Tests of full risk sharing The insight that Pareto efficient allocation among risk-averse agents implies full risk sharing has led to tests of versions of (1). The usual strategy involves adopting a convenient parameterization of U i, and then calculating the logarithm of both sides of (1). For example, if U i (c) = c1 γ, with γ > 0, then this yields the relationship 1 γ (2) γ log c it (s t ) = log µ t(s t ) p t (s t ) log λ i β i t log β i. This is a simple consumption function, which we would expect to be consistent with any efficient allocation. The quantity µt(st) p t(s t) is related to the aggregate supply of the consumption good. Note that this is the only determinant of consumption which depends on the random state. This reflects the fact that the only risk borne by agents in an efficient allocation will be aggregate risk. The second term varies with neither the state nor the date, and can be thought of as depending on the levels of consumption that agent i can expect (in a decentralization 3

of this endowment economy, λ i could be interpreted as a measure of i s time zero wealth). The final term has to do with differences in agents patience. Now, suppose one has panel data on realized consumption for a sample of agents over some period of time. If we let c it denote observed consumption for agent i in period t, (2) implies the estimating equation (3) log c it = η t + α i + δ i t + ɛ it, where η t = log µt(st), α γp t(s t) i = log λ i γβ i, δ i = log β i, and ɛ it is some disturbance term. Because this final disturbance term isn t implied by the model it s typically motivated by assuming that it s related either to measurement error in consumption, or to some preference shock. The reduced form consumption equation (3) can be straightforwardly estimated using ordinary least squares, but this doesn t constitute a test of full risk-sharing. To construct such a test, one typically uses data on other time-varying, idiosyncratic variables which would plausibly influence consumption under some alternative model which predicts less than full risk sharing. Perhaps the most obvious candidate for such a variable is some measure of income, for example the observed endowment realizations x it referred to in the model above. Then one can add (the logarithm of) this variable to (3) as an additional regressor, yielding an estimating equation of the form (4) log c it = η t + α i + δ i t + φ log x it + ɛ it (Mace, 1991; Cochrane, 1991; Deaton, 1992; Townsend, 1994). Then full risk sharing and an auxilliary assumption that ɛ it is mean independent of the regressors implies the exclusion restriction φ = 0, which can be easily tested. Partial risk sharing Restrictions along the lines of (4) have been used to test for full risk sharing in a wide variety of settings, including within-dynasty risk sharing (Hayashi et al., 1996) in the U.S., risk sharing across countries (Obstfeld, 1994), risk sharing within networks in the Philippines (Fafchamps and Lund, 2003), and risk sharing across households in India (Townsend, 1994), Africa, or the U.S. (Mace, 1991). A typical finding is that the estimated response of consumption to income shocks is small but significant, leading one to reject the null hypothesis of full risk sharing. In this case it is tempting to interpret the estimated relationship as determining the response of consumption to income. However, this is generally a mistake. By rejecting the hypothesis of full risk sharing one also rejects the model which generated the 4

hypothesis, so that theory no longer supports the interpretation of (4) as a consumption function. Given this kind of evidence against full risk sharing, scholars have been led to devise and test alternative models in which some kind of friction leads to agents bearing some idiosyncratic income risk. Two promising frictions are private information and limited commitment. In the case of private information, realized or announced incomes may provide a useful signal regarding hidden actions or information, and thus an agent s consumption will optimally depend on this signal, leading to a balance between risk sharing and incentives (Holmström, 1979); Ligon (1998) tests this weaker risk-sharing hypothesis in three Indian villages, and is unable to reject it. In the case of limited commitment, an agent who receives an unusually large endowment realization may be tempted to renege on a pre-existing risk-sharing arrangement unless she receives a larger share of resources (Kocherlakota, 1996); a test of this model in the same three Indian villages by Ligon et al. (2002) finds that this model predicts a response of consumption to income of just the right magnitude. Still, the construction, estimation, and testing of well-specified models which predict only partial risk sharing remains in its infancy. 5 Ethan Ligon References Allen, F. and D. Gale (1988). Optimal security design. The Review of Financial Studies 1 (3), 229 263. Benjamin, D. (1992). Household composition, labor markets, and labor demand: Testing for separation in agricultural household models. Econometrica 60 (2), 287 322. Cochrane, J. H. (1991). A simple test of consumption insurance. Journal of Political Economy 99, 957 976. Deaton, A. (1992). Understanding Consumption. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Fafchamps, M. and S. Lund (2003). Risk-sharing networks in rural Philippines. Journal of Development Economics 71, 261 87. Hayashi, F., J. Altonji, and L. J. Kotlikoff (1996). Risk-sharing between and within families. Econometrica 64 (2), 261 294. Holmström, B. (1979, Spring). Moral hazard and observability. Bell Journal of Economics 10, 74 91. Kocherlakota, N. R. (1996). Implications of efficient risk sharing without commitment. The Review of Economic Studies 63 (4), 595 610.

Ligon, E. (1998). Risk-sharing and information in village economies. Review of Economic Studies 65, 847 864. Ligon, E., J. P. Thomas, and T. Worrall (2002). Informal insurance arrangements with limited commitment: Theory and evidence from village economies. The Review of Economic Studies 69 (1), 209 244. Mace, B. J. (1991). Full insurance in the presence of aggregate uncertainty. Journal of Political Economy 99, 928 956. Obstfeld, M. (1994). Risk-taking, global diversification, and growth. American Economic Review 84 (5), 1310 1329. Rosenzweig, M. R. (1988). Risk, implicit contracts and the family in rural areas of low-income countries. Economic Journal 98, 1148 1170. Rothschild, M. and J. E. Stiglitz (1970). Increasing risk: I. A definition. Journal of Economic Theory 2, 225 243. Townsend, R. M. (1987). Microfoundations of macroeconomics. In T. F. Bewley (Ed.), Advances in Economic Theory, Fifth World Congress. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Townsend, R. M. (1994). Risk and insurance in village India. Econometrica 62 (3), 539 591. 6