EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Similar documents
Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

ECON Financial Economics

ECON Micro Foundations

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Lecture Notes 1

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Handout on Rationalizability and IDSDS 1

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Social Choice

Mean-Variance Analysis

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

Econ 277A: Economic Development I. Final Exam (06 May 2012)

Answer: Let y 2 denote rm 2 s output of food and L 2 denote rm 2 s labor input (so

Expected Utility Inequalities

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2009 examination. 2008/2009 syllabus

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Characterization of the Optimum

Expected Utility Inequalities

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Questions and Answers Econ 8712

EconS Micro Theory I 1 Recitation #7 - Competitive Markets

Exercises - Moral hazard

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Fiscal policy and minimum wage for redistribution: an equivalence result. Abstract

Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Optimal Auctions with Ambiguity

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

Behavioral Finance and Asset Pricing

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

1. Expected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

For on-line Publication Only ON-LINE APPENDIX FOR. Corporate Strategy, Conformism, and the Stock Market. June 2017

Maximization of utility and portfolio selection models

Optimal Auctions with Ambiguity

Consumption-Savings Decisions and State Pricing

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Gains from Trade and Comparative Advantage

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 5. Property Rights Theory. The key question we are staring from is: What are ownership/property rights?

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion.

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Choice under Uncertainty

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

Econ Homework 4 - Answers ECONOMIC APPLICATIONS OF CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION. 1. Assume that a rm produces product x using k and l, where

PREPRINT 2007:3. Robust Portfolio Optimization CARL LINDBERG

Practice Questions Chapters 9 to 11

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies

Financial Economics Field Exam January 2008

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Choice Under Uncertainty

Equilibrium Asset Returns

Expected utility inequalities: theory and applications

Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Lecture 5. Varian, Ch. 8; MWG, Chs. 3.E, 3.G, and 3.H. 1 Summary of Lectures 1, 2, and 3: Production theory and duality

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

Problem Set (1 p) (1) 1 (100)

Bounding the bene ts of stochastic auditing: The case of risk-neutral agents w

Robust portfolio optimization

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Problem Set 1 Answer Key. I. Short Problems 1. Check whether the following three functions represent the same underlying preferences

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty

Uncertainty Aversion and Systemic Risk

5. COMPETITIVE MARKETS

Ambiguity Aversion. Mark Dean. Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University

EconS Micro Theory I 1 Recitation #9 - Monopoly

Lectures on Trading with Information Competitive Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibrium (Grossman and Stiglitz AER (1980))

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

Some Notes on Timing in Games

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2011 Examination. 2010/2011 Syllabus ONLY

OPTIMAL INCENTIVES IN A PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL WITH ENDOGENOUS TECHNOLOGY. WP-EMS Working Papers Series in Economics, Mathematics and Statistics

Advanced Risk Management

Technical Appendix to Long-Term Contracts under the Threat of Supplier Default

Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part 1

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

Answer for Homework 2: Modern Macroeconomics I

The Economics of State Capacity. Ely Lectures. Johns Hopkins University. April 14th-18th Tim Besley LSE

Continuous-Time Consumption and Portfolio Choice

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Choice Under Uncertainty

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Credit Card Competition and Naive Hyperbolic Consumers

1 Two Period Production Economy

Temptation and Self-control

Insurance Contracts with Adverse Selection When the Insurer Has Ambiguity about the Composition of the Consumers

Subjective Measures of Risk: Seminar Notes

Martingale Approach to Pricing and Hedging

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

Transcription:

EconS 50 - Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II. Exercise 6.E.: The purpose of this exercise is to show that preferences may not be transitive in the presence of regret. Let there be S states of the world, indexed by s ; :::; S. Assume that state s occurs with probability s. De ne the expected regret associated with lottery x (x ; :::; x s ) relative to lottery x 0 x 0 ; :::; xs 0 by SX s o s h max n0; x 0s x s, where h () is a given increasing function. [We call h () the regret valuation function; it measures the regret the individual has after the state of nature is known.] We de ne x to be at least as good as x 0 in the presence of regret if and only if the expected regret associated with x relative to x 0 is not greater than the expected regret associated with x 0 relative to x. Suppose that S ;, and h (x) p x. lotteries: Consider the following three x (0; ; ), x 0 (0; ; ), x 00 (; ; ). Show that the preference ordering over these three lotteries is not transitive. Answer: Denote by R (x; x 0 ) the expected regret associated with lottery x relative to x 0, and similarly for the other lotteries. A direct calculation yields: R (x; x 0 ) p ' 0:66; and R (x0 ; x) ' 0:577; p p + 5 R (x 0 ; x 00 ) ' 0:804; and R (x 00 ; x 0 ) ' 0:745; p p + R (x 00 ; x) ' 0:804; and R (x; x 00 ) ' 0:47: Hence, R (x; x 0 ) > R (x 0 ; x) ; R (x 0 ; x 00 ) > R (x 00 ; x 0 ) ; R (x 00 ; x) > R (x; x 00 ) : Thus, x 0 is preferred to x; x 00 is preferred to x 0 ; but x is preferred to x 00 :

. Exercise 6.F.: The purpose of this exercise is to explain the outcomes of the experiments described in Example 6.F. (page 07 MWG) by means of the theory of nonunique prior beliefs of Gilboa and Schmeidler (989). We consider a decision maker with a Bernoulli utility function u() de ned on f0; 000g. We normalize u() so that u(0) 0 and u(000). The probabilistic belief that the decision maker might have on the color of the H-ball being white is a number [0; ]. We assume that the decision maker has, not a single belief but a set of beliefs given by a subset P of [0; ]. The actions that he may take are denoted R or H with R meaning that he chooses the R-ball and H meaning that he chooses the H-ball. As in Example 6.F., the decision maker is faced with two di erent choice situations. In choice situation W, he receives 000 dollars if the ball chosen is white and 0 dollars otherwise. In choice situation B, he receives 000 dollars if the ball chosen is black and 0 dollars otherwise. For each of the two choice situations, de ne his utility function over the actions R and H in the following way: For situation W; U W : fr; Hg! R is de ned by U W (R) :49 and U W (H) min f : P g : For situation B; U B : fr; Hg! R is de ned by U B (R) :5 and U B (H) min f( ) : P g. Namely, his utility from choice R is the expected utility of 000 dollars with the (objective) probability calculated from the number of white and black balls in urn R. However, his utility from choice H is the expected utility of 000 dollars with the probability associated with the most pessimistic belief in P. a. Prove that if P consists of only one belief, then U W and U B are derived from a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function and that U W (R) > U W (H) if and only if U B (R) < U B (H). Answer: If P fg, then U W (H) and U B (H). Hence they are determined from the expected utility u (000) + ( ) u (0). Moreover, U W (R) > U W (H) if and only if 0:49 >. But this is equivalent to 0:5 <, which is, in turn, equivalent to U B (R) < U B (H). b. Find a set P for which U W (R) > U W (H) and U B (R) > U B (H). Answer: We have U W (R) > U W (H) if and only if 0:49 > min P. We have U B (R) > U B (H) if and only if 0:5 > min f : P g, which is equivalent to 0:49 < max P. Hence min P < 0:49 < max P if and only if U W (R) > U W (H) and U B (R) > U B (H).

. Exercise.6: Esperanza has been an expected utility maximizer ever since she was ve years old. As a result of the strict education she received at an obscure British boarding school, her utility function u is strictly increasing and strictly concave. Now, at the age of thirty-something, Esperanza is evaluating an asset with stochastic outcome R which is normally distributed with mean and variance. Thus, its density function is given by ( f (r) ) p exp r. (a) Show that Esperanza s expected utility from R is a function of and alone. Thus, show that E [u (R)] ;. Answer (a): Note that E [u (R)] Z u (s) (b) Show that () is increasing in. ( p exp s ) ds ;. Di er- Answer (b): [See the gure below] Normalize u () such that u () 0. entiating, we have E [u (R)] Z u (s) (s ) f (s) ds > 0, since the terms [u (s) (s )] and f (s) are positive for all s. Figure

(c) Show that () is decreasing in. Answer (c): [See the gure at the end of this handout] Now we have E [u (R)] Z u (s) (s ) f (s) ds < Z u 0 () (s ) (s ) f (s) ds Z u0 () Z (s ) f (s) ds (s ) f (s) ds 0. The rst inequality follows from the concavity of u () and the normalization imposed; the hlast equality follows from the fact that R is normally distributed and, hence E R E [R] ki 0 for k odd. 4

4. Exercise 6.C.7: Prove that, in Proposition 6.C., condition (iii) implies condition (iv), and (iv) implies (i). (i) r A (x; u ) r A (x; u ) for every x. (iii) c (F; u ) c (F; u ) for any F (). (iv) (x; "; u ) (x; "; u ) for any x and ". Suppose rst that condition (iii) holds. Let x R and " > 0. Denote by F () the distribution function that puts probability (x; "; u ) on x " and + (x; "; u ) on x + ". That is, 8 < F (z) : 0 if z < x ", (x; "; u ) if x " z < x + ", if x + " z. then c (F; u ) x. By (iii), c (F; u ) x. Thus u (c (F; u )) u (x). But by de nition 6.C. (on page 86 MWG) we have u (c (F; u )) (x; "; u ) u (x ") + u (x ") + + (x; "; u ) u (x + ") u (x + ") + (x; "; u ) (u (x + ") u (x ")) and u (x) (x; "; u ) u (x ") + u (x ") + + (x; "; u ) u (x + ") u (x + ") + (x; "; u ) (u (x + ") u (x ")). Hence, condi- Thus the last inequality is equivalent to (x; "; u ) (x; "; u ). tion (iv) holds. Suppose now that condition (iv) holds. Since (iv) implies that Since (i) follows. (x; 0; u ) (x; 0; u ) 0, (x; 0; u ) (x; 0; u ) 0, (x; 0; u ) " r A (x; u ) 4 (x; 0; u ) " 5 (x; 0; u ). " and r A (x; u ) 4 (x; 0; u ), "

5. Exercise 6.C.8: Assume that the Bernoulli utility function u(:) exhibits decreasing absolute risk aversion. Show that for the asset demand model of Example 6.C. (page 88 MWG), the optimal allocation between the safe and the risky assets implies that the allocation of wealth on the risky asset is increasing as w rises (i.e., the risky asset is a normal good). Answer: Let w and w be two wealth levels such that w > w and de ne u (z) u (w + z) and u (z) u (w + z), then u () is a concave transformation of u () by (i) and (ii) of Proposition 6.C. on page 9 in MWG. It was shown in Example 6.C. (continued) that the demand for the risky asset of u () is greater than that of u (). This means that the demand for the risky asset of u () is greater at wealth level w than at w. Intuitively, if the demand for risky assets is larger for the individual with the less concave utility function, u (), then if we evaluate u () at a higher wealth level w than the wealth level at which we evaluate u (), the ranking between the risky assets of individual and still holds. 6. Exercise 6.C.5: Assume that, in a world with uncertainty, there are two assets. The rst is a riskless asset that pays dollar. The second pays amounts a and b with probabilities of and, respectively. Denote the demand for the two assets by (x ; x ; ). Suppose that a decision maker s preferences satisfy the axioms of expected utility theory and that he is a risk averter. The decision maker s wealth is, and so are the prices of the assets. Therefore, the decision maker s budget constraint is given by x + x ; x ; x [0; ]. Throughout this answer, we assume that a 6 b, because, otherwise, there would be no uncertainty involved in the payment of the second asset. a. Give a simple necessary condition (involving a and b only) for the demand for the riskless asset to be strictly positive. Answer: If min fa; bg, the risky asset pays at least as high a return as the riskless asset at both states, and a strictly higher return at one of them. Then all the wealth is invested to the risky asset. Thus, min fa; bg < is a necessary condition for the demand for the riskless asset to be strictly positive. b. Give a simple necessary condition (involving a; b; and only) for the demand for the risky asset to be strictly positive. Answer: If a + ( ) b, then the expected return does not exceed the payments of the riskless asset and hence the risk-averse decision maker does not demand the risky asset at all. Thus a + ( ) b > is a necessary condition for the demand for the risky asset to be strictly positive. 6

In the next three parts, assume that the conditions obtained in (a) and (b) are satis ed. In the following answers, we assume that the demands for both assets are always positive. c. Write down the rst-order conditions for utility maximization in this asset demand problem. Answer: Since the prices of the two assets are equal to one, their marginal utilities must be equal. Thus u 0 (x + x a) + ( ) u 0 (x + x b) au 0 (x + x a) + ( ) bu 0 (x + x b). That is, ( a) u 0 (x + x a) + ( ) ( b) u 0 (x + x b) 0. This and x + x constitute the rst-order condition. d. Assume that a <. Show by analyzing the rst-order conditions that dx da 0. Answer: Taking b as constant, de ne (a; ; x ) ( a) u 0 (x + ( x ) a) + ( ) ( b) u 0 (x + ( x ) b), then a u0 (x + ( x ) a) + ( a) ( x ) u 00 (x + ( x ) a) < 0, x ( a) u 00 (x + ( x ) a) + ( ) ( b) u 00 (x + ( x ) b) < 0. Thus, by the implicit function theorem (Theorem M.E.), e. Which sign do you conjecture for dx d? dx da a x < 0. Give an economic interpretation. Answer: It follows from the condition of (b) that b >, that is, that a is the worse outcome of the risky asset. Thus, if the probability of the worse outcome is increased, then it is anticipated that the demand for the riskless asset is increased. f. Can you prove your conjecture in (e) by analyzing the rst-order conditions? Answer: Since b >, ( a) u0 (x + ( x ) a) ( b) u 0 (x + ( x ) b) ( a) u 0 (x + ( x ) a) + (b ) u 0 (x + ( x ) b) > 0, because a < < b. as anticipated. Thus dx d x > 0, 7