Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Similar documents
Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Choice under Uncertainty

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

Choice Under Uncertainty

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

Part 4: Market Failure II - Asymmetric Information - Uncertainty

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Characterization of the Optimum

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Advanced Risk Management

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion.

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Consumption and Asset Pricing

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral.

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance

Stat 6863-Handout 1 Economics of Insurance and Risk June 2008, Maurice A. Geraghty

1. Expected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Advanced Financial Economics Homework 2 Due on April 14th before class

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

ECON Financial Economics

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty

Optimizing Portfolios

Advanced Microeconomic Theory

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno. Economics 103: Economics of uncertainty and information PRACTICE PROBLEMS

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Period State of the world: n/a A B n/a A B Endowment ( income, output ) Y 0 Y1 A Y1 B Y0 Y1 A Y1. p A 1+r. 1 0 p B.

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

B. Online Appendix. where ɛ may be arbitrarily chosen to satisfy 0 < ɛ < s 1 and s 1 is defined in (B1). This can be rewritten as

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences

Economic of Uncertainty

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec

Lecture 8: Asset pricing

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models

Mock Examination 2010

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Investment and Portfolio Management. Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 9. Demand for Insurance

On the Judgment Proof Problem

PhD Qualifier Examination

MATH 5510 Mathematical Models of Financial Derivatives. Topic 1 Risk neutral pricing principles under single-period securities models

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Problem Set 3 Solutions

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Department of Economics. Ph. D. Preliminary Examination: Macroeconomics Fall, 2009

Lecture 7. The consumer s problem(s) Randall Romero Aguilar, PhD I Semestre 2018 Last updated: April 28, 2018

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

Microeconomics 3200/4200:

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

14.13 Economics and Psychology (Lecture 5)

Attitudes Towards Risk

Midterm 2 (Group A) U (x 1 ;x 2 )=3lnx 1 +3 ln x 2

Homework 3: Asset Pricing

Hedonic Equilibrium. December 1, 2011

1 Dynamic programming

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Answers Econ 8712

Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013

Comprehensive Exam. August 19, 2013

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Transcription:

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 12, October 4 Outline 1 Risk Aversion 2 Certainty Equivalent 3 Risk Premium 4 Relative Risk Aversion 5 Stochastic Dominance

Notation From Last Class A cumulative distribution function (cdf) is a function F : R [0, 1] which is nondecreasing, right continuous, and goes from 0 to 1. µ F denotes the mean (expected value) of F, i.e. µ F = x df (x). δ x is the degenerate distribution function at x; i.e. δ x yields x with certainty: { 0 if z < x δ x (z) = 1 if z x. { 0 if z <µ Given some F, δ µf = F is a probability distribution that yields the 1 if z µ F expected value of F for sure. Preferences are over cumulative distributions.

Risk Aversion Definitions The preference relation is risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F, δ µf F. risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F, F δ µf. risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δ µf F ). DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µ F for sure to the uncertain distribution F. This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or any other). Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Risk Aversion: An example Exercise Let be a preference relation on (R), the space of all cumulative distribution functions, be represented by the following utility function: { x if F = δx for some x R U(F ) = 0 otherwise True of false: is risk averse. False: If µ F < 0, then F µ F.

Certainty Equivalent Definition Given a strictly increasing and continuous vnm index v over wealth, the certainty equivalent (CE) of F, denoted c(f, v), is defined by v(c(f, v)) = v ( ) df. By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c( ) such that that c( ) F. DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of that distribution. The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfies this indifference. One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents. Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a given preference representation (needs some utility function that represents preferences). The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Risk Premium Definition Given a strictly increasing and continuous vnm index v over wealth, the risk premium of F, denoted r(f, v) is defined by r(f, v) = µ F c(f, v). This measures the difference between the expected value of a particular distribution and its certainty equivalent. The definition of risk premium also assumes a given preference representation. This also seems related to risk aversion.

Risk Aversion, Certainty Equivalent, and Risk Premium If preferences satisfy the vnm axioms, risk aversion is completely characterized by concavity of the utility index and a non-negative risk-premium. Proposition Suppose has an expected utility representation and v is the corresponding von Neumann and Morgestern utility index over money.the following are equivalent: 1 is risk averse; 2 v is concave; 3 r(f, v) 0; The proof uses Jensen s inequality.

Jensen s inequality Jensen s Inequality A function g is concave if and only if ( g (x) df g ) xdf This says g(e(x )) E(g(X )) Consequences of Jensen s inequality Hence, v( ) is concave if and only if ( ) vdf v df }{{}}{{} expected utility of F utility of the expected value of F Since we also know that v is non decreasing, ( c(f, v) vdf is equivalent to v (c(f, v)) v or ( ) v df v vdf ) vdf

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium is risk averse }{{} (1) v } is concave {{} r(f, v) 0 }{{} (2) (3) We prove (1) (2) (3) (1). Start with (1) (2). Proof. is risk averse, hence δ µf F for all F R. For any x, y R and α [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be such that P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1 α. Let F α x,y be the associated cumulative distribution. By risk aversion we have: v(µ F α x,y ) v(αx + (1 α)y) z Thus v is concave. v(z)df α x,y (z) v(z)p(x = z) = αv(x) + (1 α)v(y)

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium Now prove that (2) (3) Proof. is risk averse }{{} (1) v } is concave {{} r(f, v) 0 }{{} (2) (3) Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F. By Jensen s inequality: or v(e(x )) E(v(X )) v(µ F ) v(x)df (x) = v(c(f, v)) Since v is an increasing function, we have Thus µ F c(f, v) µ F c(f, v) = r(f, v) 0

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium is risk averse }{{} (1) v } is concave {{} r(f, v) 0 }{{} (2) (3) (3) (1) Proof. Let r(f, v) 0 for all cdfs F. Then we have µ F c(f, v) which in turn implies that v(µ F ) v(c(f, v)) = v(x)df (x) Hence δ µf F for all F R; therefore is risk averse. We have shown that (1) (2) (3) (1), thus the proof is complete.

Relative Risk Aversion When can we say that one decision maker is more risk averse than another? Relative risk aversion answers this question in a preference-based way. Definition Given two preference relations, 1 is more risk averse than 2 if and only if for all F and x. F 1 δ x F 2 δ x If DM1 prefers the lottery F to the sure payout x, then anyone who is less risk averse than DM1 also prefers the lottery F to δ x. Conversely, if DM2 prefers the sure payout x to the lottery F, then anyone who is more risk averse than DM2 also prefers the sure payout δ x to the lottery F. Again, this definition does not assume anything about preferences. When both preferences satisfy expected utility, we have extra implications.

Relative Risk Aversion Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: more concavity of the utility index, a smaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium. Proposition Suppose 1 and 2 are preference relations represented by the vnm indices v 1 and v 2. The following are equivalent: 1 1 is more risk averse than 2 ; 2 v 1 = φ v 2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R R; 3 c(f, v 1 ) c(f, v 2 ), for all F ; 4 r(f, v 1 ) r(f, v 2 ), for all F. Proof. Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Another Application: Asset Demand An asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future. Asset Demand An agent has initial wealth w; she can invest in a safe asset that returns $1 per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested. The general version has N assets each yielding a return z n per unit invested. The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume z df > 1. Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively. Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β. The agent solves max v(αz + β) df s. t. α, β 0 and α + β = w The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is (z 1)v (α(z 1) + w) df = 0 If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) because of the concavity of v. One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 then her optimal α 1 is smaller than the corresponding α 2 : the more risk averse consumer invests less in the risky asset.

How to Measure Risk Aversion Since concavity of v reflects risk aversion, v is a natural candidate measure of risk aversion. Unfortunately, v is not appropriate since it is not robust to strictly increasing linear transformations. Definition Suppose is a preference relation represented by the twice differentiable vnm index v : R R. The Arrow Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion λ : R R is defined by λ(x) = v (x) v (x). The second derivative is normalized to measure risk aversion properly. Notice that by integrating λ(x) twice one could recover the utility function. How about the constants of integration?

Absolute Risk Aversion Proposition Suppose 1 and 2 are preference relations represented by the twice differentiable vnm indices v 1 and v 2. Then 1 is more risk averse than 2 λ 1 (x) λ 2 (x) for all x R This confirms that the Arrow-Pratt coeffi cient is the correct measure of increasing absolute risk aversion. One can add this to the characterizations of more risk averse than that you have to prove in the homework... but I decided to do this in class instead.

Proof. 1 is more risk averse than 2 λ 1 (x) λ 2 (x) for all x R We know v 1 = φ(v 2 ) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework). Differentiating v 1 (x) = φ (v 2 (x))v 2 (x) and v 1 (x) = φ (v 2 (x))v 2 (x) + φ (v 2 (x))v 2 (x) Dividing v 1 by v 1 > 0 we have v 1 (x) v 1 (x) = φ (v 2 (x))v 2 (x) v 1 (x) Subsitute the first equation v 1 (x) v 2 v 1 = (x) (x) or v 1 (x) 2 v 1 = (x) v (x) using the definition of Arrow-Pratt: since φ is concave and v is increasing. + φ (v 2 (x))v 2 (x) v 1 (x) v 2 (x) + φ (v 2 (x))v 2 (x) v 1 (x) v 2 (x) φ (v 2 (x))v 2 (x) v 1 (x) λ 1 (x) = λ 2 (x) + something

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD) What kind of relationship must exist between lotteries F and G to ensure that anyone, regardless of her attitude to risk, will prefer F to G so long as she likes more wealth than less? In general, if a consumer s utility of wealth is increasing, but its functional form unknown, we do not have enough information to know her rankings among all distributions...but we know how she ranks some pairs; namely, those comparable with respect to the following transitive, but incomplete, binary relation. Definition F first-order stochastically dominates G, denoted F FOSD G, if v df v dg, for every nondecreasing function v : R R. If F FOSD G, then anyone who prefers more money to less prefers F to G. This follows because F G U(F ) = v df v dg = U(G ). Proposition F FOSD G if and only if F (x) G(x) for all x R.

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD) F FOSD G, if v df v dg, for every nondecreasing function v : R R. FOSD is characterized by only looking at distribution functions. Proposition F FOSD G if and only if F (x) G(x) for all x R. This follows from integration by parts Thus b a b v (x) f (x) dx = v (x) F (x) b a v (x) F (x) dx = v (b) 1 v (0) 0 a b b = v (b) v (x) F (x) dx a a v (x) F (x) dx b b b v df v dg = v (x) [G (x) F (x)] dx a a a and you can fill in the blanks for a formal proof.

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD) If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealth is concave), we know how she ranks more pairs. Definition F second-order stochastically dominates G, denoted F SOSD G, if v df v dg, for every nondecreasing concave function v : R R. If F SOSD G, then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averse prefers F to G. By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of those ranked by SOSD F FOSD G implies F SOSD G. Proposition F SOSD G if and only if x F (t) dt x G(t) dt for all x R. SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions. What if F SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a reasonable choice?

Preferences and Lotteries Over Money So far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money. Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from? There are N commodities and ranks lotteries on X = R N +. The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utility maximzer, and U : R N + R is her expected utility function. One can also think of U ( ) as a utility function in the sense of consumer theory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p, w). Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumers learns how much money she has before she goes to the markets to buy x. Fix prices p R N ++; let w [0, ) be income, and x (p, w) the Walrasian demand. Clearly, v (p, w) = U (x) for x x (p, w). How does the consumer rank lotteries over income? A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0, ). The expected utility of π is y support(π) π (w) v (p, w); and π ρ π (w) v (p, w) ρ (w) v (p, w) y support(π) y support(π) The indirect utility function v ( ) is the utility of income. How do properties of transfer to v ( )? Think about the answer.

Next Week MIDTERM 75 minutes long, covers everything so far, you can consult the class handouts (in printed form), no access to any other materials. Past midterm exams with Kelly... but content has changed over the years. I cannot hold offi ce hours next Wednesday. Since there is no class next Tuesday (there is no next Tuesday at Pitt), and Roee is not teaching during his class slot, we can use that time for collective offi ce hours. I will be in 4716 starting at 9am ready to answer any questions about the material relevant for the midterm.