Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Similar documents
Choice under risk and uncertainty

1. Expected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Choice Under Uncertainty

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Choice under Uncertainty

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

Advanced Risk Management

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

3. Prove Lemma 1 of the handout Risk Aversion.

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral.

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

Characterization of the Optimum

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

Summer 2003 (420 2)

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Measuring Risk Preferences. Professor: Pamela Jakiela

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

Lecture 2 Basic Tools for Portfolio Analysis

Chapter 4. Uncertainty

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Notes for Session 2, Expected Utility Theory, Summer School 2009 T.Seidenfeld 1

ECON Financial Economics

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Lecture 06 Single Attribute Utility Theory

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

STOCHASTIC CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL: CANONICAL APPLICATIONS FEBRUARY 19, 2013

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

Attitudes Towards Risk

Income distribution orderings based on differences with respect to the minimum acceptable income

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

This paper addresses the situation when marketable gambles are restricted to be small. It is easily shown that the necessary conditions for local" Sta

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Part 4: Market Failure II - Asymmetric Information - Uncertainty

Stat 6863-Handout 1 Economics of Insurance and Risk June 2008, Maurice A. Geraghty

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Economic of Uncertainty

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Up till now, we ve mostly been analyzing auctions under the following assumptions:

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

( 0) ,...,S N ,S 2 ( 0)... S N S 2. N and a portfolio is created that way, the value of the portfolio at time 0 is: (0) N S N ( 1, ) +...

Chapter 1. Utility Theory. 1.1 Introduction

Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited

From Discrete Time to Continuous Time Modeling

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS MODEL JANUARY 19, 2018

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

Risk management. Introduction to the modeling of assets. Christian Groll

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Notes 10: Risk and Uncertainty

Project Risk Analysis and Management Exercises (Part II, Chapters 6, 7)

WORKING PAPER SERIES 2011-ECO-05

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

THE PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIVERSITY. Department of Economics. January Written Portion of the Comprehensive Examination for

Game Theory - Lecture #8

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

PURE-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA WITH NON-EXPECTED UTILITY PLAYERS

Project Risk Evaluation and Management Exercises (Part II, Chapters 4, 5, 6 and 7)

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Homework Assignment #1: Answer Sheet

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

ANSWERS TO PRACTICE PROBLEMS oooooooooooooooo

Microeconomics 3200/4200:

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Uncovered Interest Rate Parity: Risk-Behavior

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

Transcription:

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Preliminaries We treat, for convenience, money as a continuous variable when dealing with monetary outcomes. Strictly speaking, the derivation of the expected utility representation assumed a finite number of outcomes; however, the theory can be extended, with some minor complications, to the case of an infinite domain. Suppose that we denote amounts of money by the continuous variable x. We can describe a monetary lottery by means of a cumulative distribution function F : R [0, 1]. That is, for any x, F (x) is the probability that the realised payoff is less than or equal to x. 2/23

Preliminaries Note that if the distribution function of a lottery has a density function f( ) associated with it, then F (x) = x f(t)dt for all x. The advantage of a formalism based on distribution functions over one based on density functions, is that the former is completely general; it does not exclude a priori the possibility of a discrete set of outcomes. From this point on, we shall work with distribution functions to describe lotteries over monetary outcomes. We take the lottery space L to be the set of all distribution functions over nonnegative amounts of money, or, more generally, over an interval [α, + ]. 3/23

Preliminaries Assume a decision maker who has rational preferences defined over L. The application of the Expected Utility Theorem to outcomes defined by a continuous variable tells us that under the assumptions of the theorem, there is an assignment of utility values u(x) to nonnegative amounts of money with the property that any F ( ) can be evaluated by a utility function U( ) of the form: U(F ) = u(x)df (x). (1) Expression (1) is the exact extension of the expected utility form to the current setting. Recall that we distinguish between the vnm utility function, U( ), defined on lotteries, and the Bernoulli utility function, u( ), defined on sure amounts of money. 4/23

Risk Aversion From now onwards, it makes sense in the current monetary context to postulate that u( ) is increasing and continuous. We now concentrate on the important property of risk aversion, its formulation in terms of the Bernoulli utility function u( ), and its measurement. DEFINITION 1. A decision maker is a risk averter (or exhibits risk aversion) if for any lottery F ( ), the degenerate lottery that yields the amount xdf (x) with certainty is at least as good as the lottery f( ) itself. If the decision maker is always (i.e. for any F ( ) ) indifferent between these two lotteries, we say that he is risk neutral. 5/23

Risk Aversion If preferences admit an expected utility representation with Bernoulli utility function u(x), it follows directly from the definition of risk aversion that the decision maker is risk averse if and only if u(x)df (x) u( ) xdf (x) for all F ( ). (2) Inequality (2) is called Jensen s Inequality, and it is the defining property of a concave function. In the context of Expected Utility Theory, we see that risk aversion is equivalent to the concavity of u( ). 6/23

Risk Aversion Given a Bernoulli utility function, we have the following definition. DEFINITION 2. The certainty equivalent of F ( ), denoted c(f, u), is the amount of money from which the individual is indifferent between the gamble F ( ) and the certain amount c(f, u); that is, u(c(f, u)) = u(x)df (x). (3) 7/23

Risk Aversion PROPOSITION 1. Suppose a decision maker is an expected utility maximiser with a Bernoulli utility function u( ) on amounts of money. Then, the following properties are equivalent: (i) The decision maker is risk averse; (ii) u( ) is concave; (iii) c(f, u) xdf (x) for all F ( ). 8/23

Measurement of Risk Aversion DEFINITION 3. Given a (twice-differentiable) Bernoulli utility function u( ) for money, the Arrow-Pratt coefficient of absolute risk aversion at x is defined as r A (x) = u (x) u (x). (4) Thus, the degree of risk aversion is related to the curvature of u( ) (i.e. u (x)). However, this is not an adequate measure because it is not invariant to positive linear transformations of the utility function at x. To make it invariant, the simplest modification is to use u (x). We also change the sign to have a positive number u (x) for an increasing and concave u( ). 9/23

Example Consider the utility function u(x) = e αx for α > 0. Then, u (x) = αe αx and u (x) = α 2 e αx. Therefore, r A (x) = ( α2 e αx ) αe αx = α for all x. 10/23

Measurement of Risk Aversion Once we are equipped with a measure of risk aversion, we can put it to use in comparative statics exercises. Two common situations are comparisons of risk attitudes across individuals with different utility functions and the comparisons of risk attitudes for one individual at different levels of wealth. 11/23

Measurement of Risk Aversion Given two Bernoulli utility functions u 1 ( ) and u 2 ( ), when can we say that u 2 ( ) is unambiguously more risk averse than u 1 ( )? Several possible approaches to a definition seem plausible. (i) r A (x, u 2 ) r A (x, u 1 ) for every x. (ii) There exists an increasing concave function ψ( ) such that u 2 (x) = ψ(u 1 (x)) at all x; that is, u 2 ( ) is a concave transformation of u 1 ( ) (u 2 ( ) is more concave than u 1 ( )). (iii) c(f, u 2 ) c(f, u 1 ) for any F ( ). These three definitions are equivalent. 12/23

Measurement of Risk Aversion It is common contention that wealthier people are willing to bear more risk than poorer people. Although this might be due to differences in utility functions across people, it is more likely that the source of the difference lies in the possibility that richer people can afford to take a chance. DEFINITION 4. The Bernoulli utility function u( ) for money exhibits decreasing absolute risk aversion if r A (x, u) is a decreasing function of x. Individuals whose preferences satisfy the decreasing absolute risk aversion property take more risk as they become wealthier. 13/23

Measurement of Risk Aversion The assumption of decreasing absolute risk aversion yields many other economically reasonable results concerning risk-bearing behavior. However, in applications, it is often too weak and, because of it is analytical convenience, it is sometimes complemented by a stronger assumption: nonincreasing relative risk aversion. To understand the concept of relative risk aversion, note that the concept of absolute risk aversion is suited to the comparison of attitudes towards risky projects whose outcomes are absolute gains or losses from current wealth. But it is also of interest to evaluate risky projects whose outcomes are percentage gains or losses of current wealth. 14/23

Measurement of Risk Aversion DEFINITION 5. Given a Bernoulli utility function u( ), the coefficient of relative risk aversion at x is r R (x, u) = xu (x). (5) u (x) Consider now how this measure varies with wealth. The property of nonincreasing relative risk aversion says that the individual becomes less risk averse with regard to gambles that are proportional to his wealth as his wealth increases. This is a stronger assumption than decreasing absolute risk aversion, since r R (x, u) = xr A (x, u); a risk-averse individual with decreasing relative risk aversion will exhibit decreasing absolute risk aversion but the converse is not necessarily true. 15/23

Comparison of Payoff Distributions In contrast to the previous contexts where we compared utility functions, here, we will compare payoff distributions. There are two natural ways that random outcomes can be compared: according to the level of returns and according to the dispersion of returns. We will therefore attempt to give meaning to two ideas: that of a distribution F ( ) yielding unambiguously higher returns than G( ) and that of F ( ) being unambiguously less risky than G( ). These notions are known, respectively, by the technical terms of first-order stochastic dominance and second-order stochastic dominance. 16/23

First-Order Stochastic Dominance Note we restrict ourselves to distributions F ( ) such that F (0) = 0 and F (x) = 1 for some x. We want to attach meaning to the expression: The distribution F ( ) yields unambiguously higher returns than the distribution G( ). At least two sensible criteria suggest themselves. First, we could test whether every expected utility maximiser who values more over less prefers F ( ) to G( ). Alternatively, we could verify whether, for every amount of money x, the probability of getting at least x is higher under F ( ) than under G( ). Fortunately, these two criteria lead to the same concept. 17/23

First-Order Stochastic Dominance DEFINITION 6. The distribution F ( ) first-order stochastically dominates G( ) if, for every nondecreasing function u : R R, we have u(x)df (x) u(x)dg(x). (6) 18/23

First-Order Stochastic Dominance PROPOSITION 2. The distribution of monetary payoffs F ( ) first-order stochastically dominates the distribution G( ) if and only if F (x) G(x) for every x. Note that first-order stochastic dominance does not imply that every possible return of the superior distribution is larger than every possible return of the inferior distribution (i.e. the set of possible outcomes could be the same in the two distributions). Although F ( ) first-order stochastically dominating G( ) implies that the mean of x under F ( ), xdf (x), is greater than its mean under G( ), a ranking of the means of the two distributions does not imply that one first-order stochastically dominates the other; rather, the entire distribution matters. 19/23

Second-Order Stochastic Dominance Next, we introduce a comparison based on relative riskiness or dispersion. To avoid confusing this issue with the trade-off between returns and risk, we will restrict ourselves to comparing distributions with the same mean. Once again, a definition suggests itself: Given two distributions F ( ) and G( ) with the same mean (i.e. xdf (x) = xdg(x)), we say that G( ) is riskier than F ( ) if every risk averter prefers F ( ) to G( ). DEFINITION 7. For any two distributions F ( ) and G( ) with the same mean, F ( ) second-order stochastically dominates (or is less risky than) G( ) if, for every nondecreasing concave function u : R + R, we have u(x)df (x) u(x)dg(x). (7) 20/23

Mean-Preserving Spreads Consider the following compound lottery. In the first stage, we have a lottery over x distributed according to F ( ). In the second stage, we randomize each possible outcome x further so that final payoff is x + z, where z has a distribution function H x (z) with a mean of zero (i.e. zdhx (z) = 0). Thus, the mean of x + z is x. Let the resulting reduced lottery be denoted by G( ). When lottery G( ) can be obtained from lottery F ( ) in this manner for some distribution H x ( ), we say that G( ) is a mean-preserving spread of F ( ). 21/23

Example F ( ) is an even probability distribution between $2 and $3. In the second step, we may spread the $2 outcome to an even probability between $1 and $3, and the $3 outcome to an even probability between $2 and $4. Then, G( ) is the distribution that assigns probability 1 to the four outcomes: 1, 2, 3, 4. 4 Thus, we say that G( ) is a mean-preserving spread of F ( ) (and F ( ) second-order stochastically dominates G( ) as indicated next). 22/23

Second-Order Stochastic Dominance PROPOSITION 3. Consider two distributions F ( ) and G( ) with the same mean. Then, the following statements are equivalent: (i) F ( ) second-order stochastically dominates G( ). (ii) G( ) is a mean-preserving spread of F ( ). 23/23