Probability, Expected Payoffs and Expected Utility

Similar documents
Homework Assigment 1. Nick Polson 41000: Business Statistics Booth School of Business. Due in Week 3

Decision making under uncertainty

Experimental Probability - probability measured by performing an experiment for a number of n trials and recording the number of outcomes

Notes 10: Risk and Uncertainty

Their opponent will play intelligently and wishes to maximize their own payoff.

Expected value is basically the average payoff from some sort of lottery, gamble or other situation with a randomly determined outcome.

a. List all possible outcomes depending on whether you keep or switch. prize located contestant (initially) chooses host reveals switch?

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

05/05/2011. Degree of Risk. Degree of Risk. BUSA 4800/4810 May 5, Uncertainty

ECO 203: Worksheet 4. Question 1. Question 2. (6 marks)

Choice under risk and uncertainty

AP Statistics Section 6.1 Day 1 Multiple Choice Practice. a) a random variable. b) a parameter. c) biased. d) a random sample. e) a statistic.

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Managerial Economics

1. better to stick. 2. better to switch. 3. or does your second choice make no difference?

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2008 David Wagner Final Exam

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

1 Solutions to Homework 4

DECISION ANALYSIS. Decision often must be made in uncertain environments. Examples:

Chapter 3: Probability Distributions and Statistics

MATH/STAT 3360, Probability FALL 2013 Toby Kenney

6.1 Binomial Theorem

Economics Homework 5 Fall 2006 Dickert-Conlin / Conlin

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

Probability and Sample space

WorkSHEET 13.3 Probability III Name:

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Managerial Economics Uncertainty

Lecture 12: Introduction to reasoning under uncertainty. Actions and Consequences

Lecture 3. Sample spaces, events, probability

Section Distributions of Random Variables

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

Homework Assignment Section 1

Unit 04 Review. Probability Rules

Section 8.1 Distributions of Random Variables

ECON 312: MICROECONOMICS II Lecture 11: W/C 25 th April 2016 Uncertainty and Risk Dr Ebo Turkson

Examples: On a menu, there are 5 appetizers, 10 entrees, 6 desserts, and 4 beverages. How many possible dinners are there?

Section Distributions of Random Variables

SECTION 4.4: Expected Value

Part 1 In which we meet the law of averages. The Law of Averages. The Expected Value & The Standard Error. Where Are We Going?

7.1: Sets. What is a set? What is the empty set? When are two sets equal? What is set builder notation? What is the universal set?

FIGURE A1.1. Differences for First Mover Cutoffs (Round one to two) as a Function of Beliefs on Others Cutoffs. Second Mover Round 1 Cutoff.

Homework Assignment Section 1

Section 3.1 Distributions of Random Variables

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

DECISION ANALYSIS. (Hillier & Lieberman Introduction to Operations Research, 8 th edition)

Overview: Representation Techniques

ESD.71 Engineering Systems Analysis for Design

What do Coin Tosses and Decision Making under Uncertainty, have in common?

List of Online Quizzes: Quiz7: Basic Probability Quiz 8: Expectation and sigma. Quiz 9: Binomial Introduction Quiz 10: Binomial Probability

Chapter 14. From Randomness to Probability. Copyright 2010 Pearson Education, Inc.

Homework Assignment Section 1

Exercises for Chapter 8

Fall 2015 Math 141:505 Exam 3 Form A

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Stat 20: Intro to Probability and Statistics

Central Limit Theorem 11/08/2005

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Chapter 4 Discrete Random variables

Section 8.1 Distributions of Random Variables

Section Random Variables and Histograms

Uncertainty, Risk, and Expected Utility

Section M Discrete Probability Distribution

Chapter 15, More Probability from Applied Finite Mathematics by Rupinder Sekhon was developed by OpenStax College, licensed by Rice University, and

CS 5522: Artificial Intelligence II

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

Lecture 2 Basic Tools for Portfolio Analysis

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Math 160 Professor Busken Chapter 5 Worksheets

Chapter 6: Probability: What are the Chances?

Resource Allocation and Decision Analysis (ECON 8010) Spring 2014 Fundamentals of Managerial and Strategic Decision-Making

Determine whether the given events are disjoint. 1) Drawing a face card from a deck of cards and drawing a deuce A) Yes B) No

Project Risk Analysis and Management Exercises (Part II, Chapters 6, 7)

MATH 446/546 Homework 1:

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Problem Set #4. Econ 103. (b) Let A be the event that you get at least one head. List all the basic outcomes in A.

Problem Set 3 Solutions

MATH 10 INTRODUCTORY STATISTICS

Expected Utility Theory

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Choice under Uncertainty

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

MATH/STAT 3360, Probability FALL 2012 Toby Kenney

MATH1215: Mathematical Thinking Sec. 08 Spring Worksheet 9: Solution. x P(x)

Chapter 4 Discrete Random variables

Resource Allocation and Decision Analysis (ECON 8010) Spring 2014 Foundations of Decision Analysis

Economic Risk and Decision Analysis for Oil and Gas Industry CE School of Engineering and Technology Asian Institute of Technology

Price Theory Lecture 9: Choice Under Uncertainty

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

MATH 10 INTRODUCTORY STATISTICS

Simple Random Sample

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Transcription:

robability, Expected ayoffs and Expected Utility In thinking about mixed strategies, we will need to make use of probabilities. We will therefore review the basic rules of probability and then derive the notion of expected value. We will also develop the notion of expected utility as an alternative to expected payoffs. robabilistic analysis arises when we face uncertainty. In situations where events are uncertain, a probability measures the likelihood that a particular event or set of events occurs. e.g. The probability that a roll of a die comes up 6. The probability that two randomly chosen cards add up to 21 Blackjack. k

Sample Space or Universe Let S denote a set collection or listing of all g possible states of the environment known as the sample space or universe; a typical state is denoted as s. For example: S={s 1, s 2 }; success/failure, or low/high price. S={s 1, s 2,...,s n-1,s n }; list of units sold or offers received. S=[0, ; stock price or salary offer. continuous positive set space.

Events An event is a collection of those states s that result in the occurrence of the event. An event can be that state s occurs or that multiple states occur, or that one of several states occurs there are other possibilities. Event A is a subset of S, denoted as A S. E ta ifth t t t i Event A occurs if the true state s is an element of the set A, written as sa.

Venn Diagrams Illustrates the sample space and events. S A 1 A 2 S is the sample space and A 1 and A 2 are events within S. Event A 1 does not occur. Denoted A 1 c Complement of A 1 Event A 1 or A 2 occurs. Denoted A 1 A 2 For probability use Addition Rules Event A 1 and A 2 both occur, denoted A 1 A 2 For probability use Multiplication Rules.

robability To each uncertain event A, or set of events, e.g. A1 or A2, we would like to assign weights which measure the likelihood or importance of the events in a proportionate manner. Let Ai be the probability of Ai. We further assume that: A all i i all i A i A A i S 0. 1

Addition Rules The probability of event A or event B: A B If the events do not overlap, i.e. the events are disjoint subsets of S, so that A B =, then the probability of A or B is simply the sum of the two probabilities. A B = A + B. If the events overlap, are not disjoint, so that A B, use the modified addition rule: AUB = A + B A B

Example Using the Addition Rule Suppose you throw two dice. There are 6x6=36 possible ways in which both can land. Event A: What is the probability that both dice show the same number? A={{1,1}, {2,2}, {3,3}, {4,4}, {5,5}, {6,6}} so A=6/36 Event B: What is the probability that the two die add up to eight? B={{2,6}, {3,5}, {4,4}, {5,3}, {6,2}} so B=5/36. Event C: What is the probability that A or B happens, i.e., AB? First, note that AB = {{4,4}} so AB =1/36. AB=A+B-AB=6/36+5/36-1/36 = 10/36 =5/18.

Multiplication Rules The probability of event A and event B: AB Multiplication rule applies if A and B are independent events. A and B are independent events if A does not depend on whether B occurs or not, and B does not depend d on whether e A occurs or not. AB= A*B=AB Conditional probability for non independent events. The probability of A given that B has occurred is A B= AB/B.

Examples Using Multiplication li Rules An unbiased coin is flipped 5 times. What is the probability of the sequence: TTTTT? T=.5, 5 independent flips, so.5x.5x.5x.5x.5=.03125. Suppose a card is drawn from a standard 52 card deck. Let B be the event: the card is a queen: B=4/52. Event A: Conditional on Event B, what is the probability that the card is the Queen of Hearts? First note that AB=A B= AB=AB= 1/52. robability the Card is the Queen of Hearts A B=AB/B = 1/52/4/52=1/4.

Bayes Rule Suppose events are A, B and not B, i.e. B c Then Bayes rule can be stated as: A B B B A c c A B B A B B Example: Suppose a drug test is 95% effective: the test will be positive i on a drug user 95% of the time, and will be negative on a non-drug user 95% of the time. Assume 5% of the population are drug users. Suppose an individual tests positive. What is the probability he is a drug user?

B R l E l Bayes Rule Example Let A be the event that the individual tests positive. Let B be the event individual is a drug user. Let B c be the complementary event, that p y the individual is not a drug user. Find B A. A B=.95. A B c =.05, B=.05, B c =.95 A B.95. A B.05, B.05, B.95 c c B B A B B A B B A A B.50 95 05 05 95.95.05 B B A B B A.05.95 95.05.

Monty Hall s 3 Door roblem There are three closed doors. Behind one of the doors is a brand new sports car. Behind each of the other two doors is a smelly goat. You can t see the car or smell the goats. You win the prize behind the door you choose. The sequence of play of the game is as follows: You choose a door and announce your choice. The host, Monty Hall, who knows where the car is, always selects one of the two doors that you did not choose, which he knows has a goat behind it. Monty then asks if you want to switch your choice to the unopened door that you did not choose. Should you switch? 1 2 3

You Should Always Switch Let C i be the event car is behind door i and let G be the event: Monty chooses a door with a goat behind it. Suppose without loss of generality, the contestant chooses door 1. Then Monty shows a goat behind door number 3 According to the rules, G=1, and so G C 1 =1; Initially, C 1 =C 2 =C 3 =1/3. By the addition rule, we also know that C 2 UC 3 =2/3. After Monty s move, C 3 =0. C 1 remains 1/3, but C 2 now becomes 2/3! According to Bayes Rule: G C1 C1 11/ 3 C1 G 1/ 3. G 1 It follows that C 2 G=2/3, so the contestant always does better by switching; the probability is 2/3 he wins the car.

Here is Another roof Let w,x,y,z describe the game. w=your initial door choice, x=the door Monty opens, y=the door you finally decide upon and z=w/l whether you win or lose. Without loss of generality, assume the car is behind door number 1, and that there are goats behind door numbers 2 and 3. Suppose you adopt the never switch strategy. The sample space under this strategy is: S=[1,2,1,W,1,3,1,W,2,3,2,L,3,2,3,L]. If you choose door 2 or 3 you always lose with this strategy. But, if you initially choose one of the three doors randomly, it must be that the outcome 2,3,2,L 232L and d323l 3,2,3,L each occur with ih probability 1/3. That means the two outcomes 1,2,1,W and 1,3,1,W have the remaining 1/3 probability so you win with probability 1/3. Suppose you adopt the always switch strategy. The sample space under this strategy is: S=[1,2,3,L,1,3,2,L,2,3,1,W,3,2,1,W]. Since you initially choose door 2 with probability 1/3 and door 3 with probability 1/3, the probability you win with the switching strategy is 1/3+1/3=2/3 so you should always switch.

Expected Value or ayoff One use of probabilities to calculate expected values or payoffs for uncertain outcomes. Suppose that an outcome, e.g. a money payoff is uncertain. There are n possible values, X 1, X 2,...,X N. Moreover, we know the probability of obtaining each value. The expected value or expected payoff of the uncertain outcome is then given by: X 1 X 1 +X 2 X 2 +...X N X N.

An Example You are made the following proposal: You pay $3 for the right to roll a die once. You then roll the die and are paid the number of dollars shown on the die. Should you accept the proposal? The expected payoff of the uncertain die throw is: 1 1 1 1 1 1 $1 $2 $3 $4 $5 $6 $3.50 6 6 6 6 6 6 The expected payoff from the die throw is greater than the $3 price, so a risk neutral player accepts the proposal.

Extensive Form Illustration: Nature as a layer ayoffs are in net terms: $3 winnings. 0.5

Accounting for Risk Aversion The assumption that individuals treat expected payoffs the same as certain payoffs i.e. that they are risk neutral may not thold ldin practice. Consider these examples: A risk neutral person is indifferent between $25 for certain or a 25% chance of earning $100 and a 75% chance of earning 0. A risk neutral person agrees to pay $3 to roll a die once and receive as payment the number of dollars shown on the die. Many people are risk averse and prefer $25 with certainty to the uncertain gamble, or might be unwilling to pay $3 for the right to roll the die once, so imagining that people base their decisions on expected payoffs alone may yield misleading results. What can we do to account for the fact that many ypeople p are risk averse? We can use the concept of expected utility.

Utility Function Transformation Let x be the payoff amount in dollars, and let Ux be a continuous, increasing function of x. The function Ux gives an individual s level of satisfaction in fictional utils from receiving payoff amount x, and is known as a utility function. If the certain payoff of $25 is preferred to the gamble, due to risk aversion then we want a utility function that satisfies: U$25 >.25 U$100 +.75 U$0. The left hand side is the utility of the certain payoff and the right hand side is the expected utility from the gamble. In this case, any concave function Ux will work, e.g. U X X 25.25 100.75 0, 5 2.5

Graphical Illustration The blue line shows the utility of any certain monetary payoff between $0 and $100, assuming U X X Utility Function Transformation Illustrated Utility Level 12 10 8 6 4 2 0 0 25 50 75 100 Do llars Utility diminishes with increases in monetary payoff this is just the principle of diminishing marginal utility requires risk aversion. Black dashed line shows the expected utility of risky payoff At $25, the certain payoff yields higher utility than the risky payoff.

Another Example If keeping $3 were preferred to rolling a die and getting paid the number of dollars that turns up expected payoff $3.5 we need a utility function that satisfied: 1 1 1 1 1 1 U $ 3 U $1 U $2 U $3 U $4 U $5 U $6 6 6 6 6 6 6 In this case, where the expected payoff $3.5 is strictly higher than the certain amount the $3 price the utility function must be sufficiently concave for the above relation to hold. 1/2 If we used U x x x, we would find that the left-hand-side of the expression above was 3 1.732, while the right-hand-side equals 1.805, so we need a more concave function. We would need a utility function transformation of 1 / 100 U x x for the inequality above to hold, 50 times more risk aversion!

Summing up The notions of probability and expected payoff are frequently encountered in game theory. We mainly assume that players are risk neutral, so they seek to maximized expected payoff. We are aware that expected monetary payoff might not be the relevant consideration that aversion to risk may play a role. We have seen how to transform the objective from payoff to utility maximization so as to capture the possibility of risk aversion the trick is to assume some concave utility function transformation. Now that we know how to deal with risk aversion, we are going to largely ignore it, and assume risk neutral behavior