Common Knowledge AND Global Games

Similar documents
Introduction to Game Theory

During the previous lecture we began thinking about Game Theory. We were thinking in terms of two strategies, A and B.

Game Theory: Global Games. Christoph Schottmüller

Replicator Dynamics 1

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

SI 563 Homework 3 Oct 5, Determine the set of rationalizable strategies for each of the following games. a) X Y X Y Z

Preliminary Notions in Game Theory

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma

Game Theory. Analyzing Games: From Optimality to Equilibrium. Manar Mohaisen Department of EEC Engineering

Best Reply Behavior. Michael Peters. December 27, 2013

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

CS711 Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

CMPSCI 240: Reasoning about Uncertainty

Notes for Section: Week 4

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance

Answers to Odd-Numbered Problems, 4th Edition of Games and Information, Rasmusen

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW-PART 2. Contracts. I.1 Investment in Performance

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

Symmetric Game. In animal behaviour a typical realization involves two parents balancing their individual investment in the common

Notes for Section: Week 7

Advanced Microeconomics

Game Theory Problem Set 4 Solutions

Game Theory Lecture #16

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Game Theory - Lecture #8

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

Microeconomic Theory III Final Exam March 18, 2010 (80 Minutes)

Prisoner s Dilemma. CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma. Prisoner s Dilemma. Prisoner s Dilemma.

Notes on Auctions. Theorem 1 In a second price sealed bid auction bidding your valuation is always a weakly dominant strategy.

Using the Maximin Principle

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two

Problem Set 2 - SOLUTIONS

Now we return to simultaneous-move games. We resolve the issue of non-existence of Nash equilibrium. in pure strategies through intentional mixing.

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1

Economics 171: Final Exam

Advanced Micro 1 Lecture 14: Dynamic Games Equilibrium Concepts

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

CSI 445/660 Part 9 (Introduction to Game Theory)

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Player 2 H T T -1,1 1, -1

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions.

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HOMEWORK #7 ANSWER KEY

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

Test 1. ECON3161, Game Theory. Tuesday, September 25 th

ECO303: Intermediate Microeconomic Theory Benjamin Balak, Spring 2008

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

if a < b 0 if a = b 4 b if a > b Alice has commissioned two economists to advise her on whether to accept the challenge.

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

Follow the Leader I has three pure strategy Nash equilibria of which only one is reasonable.

Game Theory: Minimax, Maximin, and Iterated Removal Naima Hammoud

Solution to Tutorial /2013 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012

Oligopoly Games and Voting Games. Cournot s Model of Quantity Competition:

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002

When we did independent private values and revenue equivalence, one of the auction types we mentioned was an all-pay auction

October An Equilibrium of the First Price Sealed Bid Auction for an Arbitrary Distribution.

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Microeconomics III Final Exam SOLUTIONS 3/17/11. Muhamet Yildiz

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010

MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 395

Economics 335 March 2, 1999 Notes 6: Game Theory

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Recap First-Price Revenue Equivalence Optimal Auctions. Auction Theory II. Lecture 19. Auction Theory II Lecture 19, Slide 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Epistemic Game Theory

Rationalizable Strategies

CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory)

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

January 26,

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Econ 711 Final Solutions

Day 3. Myerson: What s Optimal

Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibrium. player 2

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

LECTURE NOTES ON GAME THEORY. Player 2 Cooperate Defect Cooperate (10,10) (-1,11) Defect (11,-1) (0,0)

Economic Management Strategy: Hwrk 1. 1 Simultaneous-Move Game Theory Questions.

CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Transcription:

Common Knowledge AND Global Games 1

This talk combines common knowledge with global games another advanced branch of game theory See Stephen Morris s work 2

Today we ll go back to a puzzle that arose during the Hawk-Dove lecture: Why do we typically see the Bourgeois equilibrium and (almost) never see the anti- Bourgeois equilibrium? EVEN WHEN there is no (or little) physical advantage to being the incumbent! 3

At the time, we didn t yet have the tools to answer this. Now that you ve learned about common knowledge and the importance of higher order beliefs, we do We ll formalize this with a toy model again 4

EVEN WHEN there is no (or little) physical advantage to being the incumbent! But SOMETIMES there is. Once incorporated into the model, this SOMETIMES is enough to make Bourgeois the only REAL equilibrium 5

Here s the model 6

We assume the incumbent has an X% chance of winning a fight, where X ~U[½, 1] Here s the payoff matrix 7

(E)ntrant H D H X(v)+(1-X)(-c), (1-X)(v) + X(-c) v, 0 (I)ncumbent D 0, v ½v, ½v 8

(E)ntrant H D H X(2)+(1-X)(-4), (1-X)(2) + X(-4) 2, 0 (I)ncumbent D 0, 2 1, 1 9

We make the (realistic) assumption that each player does not EXACTLY know X Instead each gets a noisy signal of X. The amount of noise could be arbitrarily small. (So you can be REALLY sure what X is and REALLY sure what other thinks X is, but X isn t common knowledge) We model this as: player i gets signal X i where X i =X+ϵ i and ϵ i i.i.d.~u[-ϵ, ϵ] for some small ϵ>0 In our example, we ll let ϵ =.002 10

(Ignore edge cases) We now describe the normal form game The players: (I)ncumbent, (E)ntrant The strategies: S i : [½, 1] {H, D} E.g., S I (X I )=H iff X I >.7348 S E (X E )=H iff X E is a rational number 11

What are the NE of this game? Interestingly, there is EXACTLY one: S I (X I )=H for all X I S E (X E )=D for all X E This equilibrium has a very cool implication: Play Hawk if arrive first EVEN WHEN there is no (or little) advantage (Except when ϵ=0, in which case it can be common knowledge that there 12

Here s the proof 13

First let s show that: S I (X I )=H for all X I S E (X E )=D for all X E is indeed a Nash equilibrium Proof: Is there any signal at which I can deviate and play D and do better? No. On those occasions, I will get 1. This is less than 2, which is what I is currently getting Is there any signal at which E can deviate and play H and do better? No. On those occasions, E expects to get X E (-4) + (1 X E )(2). Since X E 1/2, this is 0 which is what E is currently getting 14

Next, we ll show that there is no other equilibrium 15

It will prove useful to define X*as the value of X for which the incumbent is indifferent between playing H or D given entrant plays H X* 2 + (1 X*) (-4) = 0 X*= 4/(2+4) = 2/3 =.667 Next, suppose the strategy pair S i, S E is a NE S I (X I ) = H at least when for X I.667 (b/c at.667, I is indifferent EVEN IF E were to play H everywhere, so he must CERTAINLY play H above) S E (X E ) = D at least when X E.665 (b/c above this D is a best response EVEN IF I plays D everywhere not yet specified) S I (X I ) = H for X I 1/2 (b/c at ½, I is indifferent between D and H EVEN IF E plays D everywhere not yet specified) S E (X E ) = D for X E 1/2 Notice this same logic would work for different c,v or any ϵ>0, albeit it might have taken more steps. (Prove this? What about other distributions of ϵ and X?) 16

The proof also shows us the learning/evolutionary process 17

Suppose that we start at a different strategy profile. Claim: the population will evolve/learn to play Bourgeoisie equilibrium. Here s the logic. 18

Regardless of where population starts all the incumbents will learn/evolve to play S I (X I ) = H at least when for X I.667 because any incumbent who doesn t play this will get lower payoff Before long, all the entrants will learn/evolve to play S E (X E ) = D at least when X E.665 because any entrant who doesn t play this will get lower payoff (In general, evolution/learning iteratively eliminates strictly dominated strategies ) 19

Let s see if we can use this framework to explain additional puzzles 20

Why isn t it the case that size acts as the uncorrelated asymmetry? I.e. why doesn t simply the bigger animal play hawk and the smaller play dove? Turns out, this isn t a Nash equilibrium, once we recognize that there is some (albeit perhaps miniscule) uncertainty over size 21

Proof: Suppose they play strategy: play hawk whenever estimate bigger Suppose one animal thinks he is only slightly bigger. Then he estimates there is nearly a 50% chance the other also thinks he is slightly bigger. So he thinks other will play H with probability nearly 50% If plays Hawk gets ½ ½ (v-c) + ½v = ¾v ¼c If plays Dove gets ½ (0) + ½ ½v = ¼v If ¾v ¼c > ¼v, i.e. v/c > ¼, is better off playing Dove If v/c < ¼, then when animal is slightly smaller will strictly prefer to play hawk. Either way, our purported equilibrium won t hold unless v/c is exactly ¼ Notice the problem arose because size differences can get arbitrarily small, i.e. size is continuous 22

Third and final animal question: Can Bourgeois be an equilibrium, even if there is slight uncertainty over who arrived first? Answer: yes. Suppose is 5% error rate. Then regardless of signal receive, cannot benefit from deviating [insert proof] Notice: this differs from size b/c arriving first is discrete/categorical. Noise works differently arriving first is still evident p for sufficiently high p (here p is ). Whenever believe likely arrived first, believe other believed likely arrived first (.90) and whenever don t believe likely (.90) arrived first, believe other doesn t believe likely arrived first...this wasn t true for size 23

Next application categorical vs continuous norms 24

Suppose -It is ONLY worth attacking countries if we are PRETTY CONFIDENT others will attack (e.g. we need to be confident 60%) -We cannot detect EXACTLY how many civilians are killed (e.g. we get a signal which is uniformly distributed between the true value+/-10) We will show: It is not possible to attack a country depending on our estimate of the number of civilians killed, regardless of how large the number is (e.g. attack if signal>100,000) Sketch of proof: Imagine that to attack, we need to be 60% confident that others attack, and that we set a rule that we attack any country whenever we estimate that the despot kills 100,000 civilians. Suppose we estimate that 100,001 civilians were killed. Should we attack? No! There s a 45% chance France thinks there were <100,000 civilian casualties and won t attack, so we are better off not attacking. 25

OK so it s not an equilibrium but only rarely can you benefit from deviating, so maybe if norm is 100,000 and get signal of 200,000 will attack? Two reasons why not: 1) evolution/learning 2) if states are rational and believe other states are rational and 26

Evolution / Learning When we get signal 101,000, we quickly learn not to attack. Same for France. Shortly Thereafter, when we get 102,000, we will ALSO learn to not attack, because France won t attack at 101,000. EVENTUALLY, we won t attack at 200,000 either (but this might take a REALLY long time ) (Although, this gives us some sense of how continuous norms will unravel. What about if the payoffs were such that want to attack so long as 45% sure? Only difference is unraveling will go in OTHER direction. (So now we gain prediction of DIRECTION of unraveling. Cool!) 27

If states are rational, and expect each other to be rational, and expect the other to expect them to be rational: The U.S. knows France would never attack if she received 101,000. So the U.S. won t attack at 102,000. The U.S. knows that France would anticipate this, so the U.S. knows France wouldn t attack at 103,000 28

What about a norm against chemical weapons? (A categorical norm) 29

Suppose each country gets a WRONG signal of whether a chemical weapon was used with probability.05 Recall our result from last class. p=.95, so there IS an equilibrium where punish when get signal other used chemical weapon (if we assume payoffs assumed last class) The proof works the same way as our proofs did last class 30

Let s assume the following payoffs U(both attack) = -1 U(attack alone) = -2 U(only other attacks) = -1 U(neither attacks) = -2 31

Current payoffs to each country:.95 * U(both attack) +.05 * U(attack alone) = -.95 -.1 = -1.05 Should either country deviate and not punish when it gets the signal? Then payoffs are:.95 * U(only others attack) +.05 * U(no one attacks) = -1.9 -.1 = -2 Should a country deviate and punish when it doesn t get the signal? Then payoffs are: U(attack alone) = -2 Neither deviation is worthwhile 32

For which payoffs does this work? What distribution on signals needs to be assumed? Turns out our main CK theorem will play a role! 33

Insights: 1) Which norms are categorical? 2) When do we expect to see categorical norms? 3) When ought we to see categorical norms? 4) What will happen to continuous norms over time? 5) Which emotions should vary continuously? 6) Why does the U.S. fight over a tree in N. Korea? 7) Why did the Nazis take away rights of Jews in slow steps? 34

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 14.11 Insights from Game Theory into Social Behavior Fall 2013 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.