Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions

Similar documents
Further Reflections on Prospect Theory

Investment Decisions and Negative Interest Rates

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences *

Framing Lottery Choices

INCENTIVES IN PUBLIC GOODS EXPERIMENTS: IMPLICATIONS FOR THE ENVIRONMENT

Reverse Common Ratio Effect

Preference Reversals and Induced Risk Preferences: Evidence for Noisy Maximization

Risk aversion, Under-diversification, and the Role of Recent Outcomes

Limitations of Dominance and Forward Induction: Experimental Evidence *

Self Control, Risk Aversion, and the Allais Paradox

Charles A. Holt and Roger Sherman *

The Effect of Pride and Regret on Investors' Trading Behavior

Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

Supplementary Material: Strategies for exploration in the domain of losses

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

HANDBOOK OF EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS RESULTS

Risk Aversion in Laboratory Asset Markets

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 10 Number 3 Fall 1997 CORPORATE MANAGERS RISKY BEHAVIOR: RISK TAKING OR AVOIDING?

Diminishing Preference Reversals by Inducing Risk Preferences

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Measuring Risk Preferences. Professor: Pamela Jakiela

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

THE CODING OF OUTCOMES IN TAXPAYERS REPORTING DECISIONS. A. Schepanski The University of Iowa

I A I N S T I T U T E O F T E C H N O L O G Y C A LI F O R N

Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects

Risk Preference Differentials of Small Groups and Individuals

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

Altruism and Noisy Behavior in One-Shot Public Goods Experiments

Decision Analysis under Uncertainty. Christopher Grigoriou Executive MBA/HEC Lausanne

Electronic Supplementary Materials Reward currency modulates human risk preferences

Risk Management Decisions in Low Probability and High Loss Risk Situations: Experimental Evidence

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

COMPARING THE PREDICTIVE POWER OF RISK ELICITATION INSTRUMENTS: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE FROM GERMAN FARMERS

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

Quantal Response Equilibrium and Overbidding in Private-Value Auctions * Jacob K. Goeree, Charles A. Holt, and Thomas R. Palfrey

A study on the significance of game theory in mergers & acquisitions pricing

An Introduction to Experimental Economics and Insurance Experiments. J. Todd Swarthout

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

SIMPLE AGENTS, INTELLIGENT MARKETS*

On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries. James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt

You should already have a worksheet with the Basic Plus Plan details in it as well as another plan you have chosen from ehealthinsurance.com.

Do Unto Others: A Theory and Experimental Test of Interpersonal Factors in Decision Making Under Uncertainty *

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM

Chapter 15 Trade-offs Involving Time and Risk. Outline. Modeling Time and Risk. The Time Value of Money. Time Preferences. Probability and Risk

Does Portfolio Theory Work During Financial Crises?

Demand for Insurance: Which Theory Fits Best?

SIMPLE AGENTS, INTELLIGENT MARKETS*

Behavioral Economics (Lecture 1)

BIASES OVER BIASED INFORMATION STRUCTURES:

Cascades in Experimental Asset Marktes

Department of Economics, UCB

ARE LOSS AVERSION AFFECT THE INVESTMENT DECISION OF THE STOCK EXCHANGE OF THAILAND S EMPLOYEES?

BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS IN ACTION. Applying Behavioral Economics to the Financial Services Sector

Inconsistent Choices in Lottery Experiments: Evidence from Rwanda. April 2007

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK of ATLANTA

Homework 1: Preferences, Lotteries, Expected Value and Expected Utility

EC102: Market Institutions and Efficiency. A Double Auction Experiment. Double Auction: Experiment. Matthew Levy & Francesco Nava MT 2017

Evolution of Market Heuristics

Summer 2003 (420 2)

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

Investment in Information Security Measures: A Behavioral Investigation

Reference Wealth Effects in Sequential Choice

On the provision of incentives in finance experiments. Web Appendix

Inflation Targeting and Revisions to Inflation Data: A Case Study with PCE Inflation * Calvin Price July 2011

Asset Pricing in Financial Markets

Inflation Expectations and Behavior: Do Survey Respondents Act on their Beliefs? October Wilbert van der Klaauw

Notes 10: Risk and Uncertainty

Preference Reversals Without the Independence Axiom

Definition of Incomplete Contracts

Reference Dependence Lecture 1

Psychological Factors of Voluntary Retirement Saving

A comparison of first price multi-object auctions

Expectations and market microstructure when liquidity is lost

23.1 Probability Distributions

Risk Aversion and Tacit Collusion in a Bertrand Duopoly Experiment

Effect of Nonbinding Price Controls In Double Auction Trading. Vernon L. Smith and Arlington W. Williams

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Portfolios with Hedge Funds and Other Alternative Investments Introduction to a Work in Progress

* Financial support was provided by the National Science Foundation (grant number

PowerPoint. to accompany. Chapter 11. Systematic Risk and the Equity Risk Premium

Expectations structure in asset pricing experiments

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

$$ Behavioral Finance 1

Decision Theory. Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Frontiers in Social Neuroscience and Neuroeconomics: Decision Making under Uncertainty. September 18, 2008

NOTES ON THE BANK OF ENGLAND OPTION IMPLIED PROBABILITY DENSITY FUNCTIONS

OMEGA. A New Tool for Financial Analysis

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

FOREX Risk & Money Management. By Low Jie Ji, Research Analyst 1/12/2013. NUS Students Investment Society NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF SINGAPORE

January 26,

Is Loss Aversion Causing Investors to Shun Equities?

Effect of Health on Risk Tolerance and Stock Market Behavior

Ten Little Treasures of Game Theory and Ten Intuitive Contradictions: Instructions and Data

Are Lost Decades in the Stock Market Black Swans?

EC989 Behavioural Economics. Sketch solutions for Class 2

Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining

Resistance to support

CHAPTER 3 WHAT DO WE THINK ABOUT RISK?

Transcription:

Payoff Scale Effects and Risk Preference Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions Susan K. Laury and Charles A. Holt Prepared for the Handbook of Experimental Economics Results February 2002 I. Introduction Economists are primarily concerned with decisions that involve monetary consequences, and therefore, laboratory economics experiments almost always use financial incentives. The psychologist Sidney Siegel established the importance of using real (instead of hypothetical) payments. For example, Siegel and Goldstein (1959) report a probability matching experiment in which subjects had to predict which of two light bulbs would be illuminated in a sequence of trials. For at least 20 years, psychologists had conducted probability-matching experiments, concluding that subjects consistently violated rationality assumptions. However, when Siegel and Goldstein (1959) paid subjects a small reward for correct choices, optimal behavior was observed more than 90 percent of the time. Of course, when more interesting tasks are used, incentives may not matter as much. For example, subjects may enjoy playing out choices among risky prospects, regardless of whether they are paid based on the outcome. If using real incentives does not matter, conducting experiments with hypothetical payments is an attractive, inexpensive alternative. There is an additional (frequently cited) motive for using hypothetical payments. If the naturally occurring decisions of interest involve substantial sums of money (for example, purchasing insurance against large losses), it is not feasible to pay experimental subjects comparable sums of hundreds or thousands of dollars. If "people often know how they would behave in actual situations of choice, and the subjects have no special reason to disguise their true preferences" (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979, p. 265) then it may be preferable to use high hypothetical payments over the low real payments typically used in the lab.

The effect of using hypothetical payments is not yet settled. Smith and Walker (1993) report that mean bidding behavior in auctions is little affected by the choice of payment method, but that noise is reduced when payments are real. In a follow-up paper, Tversky and Kahneman (1992) state that none of their conclusions are contradicted when real payoffs are used. These are important procedural issues, and it is natural to use experiments to evaluate them. This chapter summarizes some recent evidence on the effects of payoffs on risk attitudes. In particular we compare choices under real and hypothetical incentives, and look at the effect of payoff scale (up to several hundred dollars) under both real and hypothetical conditions, for gains and losses. II. Incentive Effects for Choices Involving Gains Holt and Laury (2001) examined the effects of payoff magnitudes in an experiment where people were asked to choose between matched pairs of safe and risky lotteries. These pairs were arranged in a menu of the type shown in Table 1. In all rows, the payoffs are $1.60 and $2.00 for Option A, the safe lottery, and $3.85 and $0.10 for the Option B, the risky lottery. The probability of the higher payoff in each pair is 0.1 in the top row, and then increases by 0.1 in each subsequent choice. The choice in Decision 10, listed in the bottom row, is between a sure $2.00 and a sure $3.85. Table 1. Menu of Lottery Choices Option A Option B Your Choice Decision 1 $2.00 with probability = 0.1 $3.85 with probability = 0.1 $1.60 with probability = 0.9 $0.10 with probability = 0.9 Decision 2 $2.00with probability = 0.2 $3.85 with probability = 0.2 $1.60 with probability = 0.8 $0.10 with probability = 0.8 Decision 9 $2.00 with probability = 0.9 $3.85 with probability = 0.9 $1.60 with probability = 0.1 $0.10 with probability = 0.1 Decision 10 $2.00 with probability = 1.0 $3.85 with probability = 1.0 Earnings were determined on the basis of one decision, selected at random after all choices had been made. In total, 93 subjects made the choices in Table 1, followed by a hypothetical choice menu for payoffs scaled up by a factor of 20 ($40 or $32 for the safe option, and $77 or $2 for the risky option). After the hypothetical earnings were determined, these same subjects were given an identical payoff menu with a clear

statement that all earnings would be paid in cash. (See Holt and Laury, 2001, for complete procedural details and instructions.) Figure 1 shows the results, with the Decision (1 through 10) on the horizontal axis and the percentage of safe choices shown on the vertical axis. The dashed black line represents the risk neutral choice pattern: choose safe with probability 1.0 in Decisions 1-4, then choose risky (0% safe choices) for all remaining decisions. More than four safe choices indicate risk aversion, and fewer safe choices indicate risk preference. The colored lines show actual choice frequencies in each of our treatments, where real payoffs are shown with thick lines and hypothetical payoffs with thin lines. The percentages for the low payoff trial, the yellow line, generally lie to the right of the risk neutral prediction, indicating some risk aversion even for low payoffs. Choices under scaled up hypothetical payoffs (see the thin red line), are quite close to the 1x real line. It became apparent to us, however, that subjects were not able to predict how risk averse they would be when actually faced with these choices. The thick red line shows observed choices when these high payoffs were actually paid; it lies significantly to the right, indicating a greater degree of risk aversion. We ran an additional 19 subjects through the same sequence, but with hypothetical and real payoffs scaled up by a factor of 50 (blue lines), and another group of 18 had payoffs scaled up by 90 (green lines). In the 90x payoff treatment, the safe lottery earned $180 or $144, and the risky lottery earned $346.50 or $9. It is clear from the thin lines in Figure 1, scaling up of hypothetical payoffs had little effect on choice frequencies. In contrast, the thick lines show that each successive increase in real payoffs resulted in higher risk aversion. In the 90x real condition, one-third of the subjects chose the safe option in Decisions 1-9, only switching on Decision 10 where the highest payoff was a certainty. The safe option in this condition ensured earnings of at least $144; this minimum was sufficiently attractive that a large fraction of people did not take any risk of receiving the low ($9) payoff from the risky lottery. A similar tendency to observe more risk aversion as payoffs are scaled up was reported by Binswanger (1980), who ran experiments with farmers in rural Bangladesh with some payoffs equivalent to the average monthly income.

These results indicate the danger of comparing low real payoffs with high hypothetical payoffs, and concluding that payoff effects may not be present (as has been done in some widely cited papers). They also suggest that high hypothetical payments may not yield good predictions of behavior under high real payoffs. The next section considers these issues when lottery choices involve losses. III. Choices in the Loss Domain, and the Reflection Effect In a second paper, Laury and Holt (2002) consider the effect of reflecting all payoffs around zero to obtain lotteries over losses. The choice menu was like that shown in Table 1, with two exceptions. The top row involved a sure thing (a probability of 0 for the higher payoff); as before, the probability of the high payoff increased by 0.1 in each successive row, so the probability of the high payoff was 0.9 in Decision 10. Also, the choices in the low-payoff gain treatment were twice the level shown in Table 1 ($4 or $3.20 for the safe option and $7.70 or $0.20 for the risky option). When these numbers were reflected, the payoffs were -$4 or -$3.20 for the safe option and -$7.70 or -$0.20 for the risky option. The structure of the menu was such that a risk-neutral person would choose exactly 5 safe choices, and a risk-averse person would choose more safe choices, whether the payoffs were in terms of gains or losses. Each subject completed the menu of lottery choices for both gains and losses. Typically when losses are possible, subjects are given an initial stake by the experimenter. In these experiments, subjects first participated in another decisionmaking experiment during which they built up their initial stake. We hoped to minimize any "found money" effects by having subjects earn this money. After the initial experiment, subjects were given the menu of lottery choices, first for gains (losses), and then for losses (gains). The order in which gains and losses were presented was varied between sessions. Results from the first lottery choice treatment were not revealed until choices in the second treatment had been made. We separated the two lottery choice experiments by a neutral matching pennies experiment. See Laury and Holt (2002) for a complete description of the procedures. Figure 2 shows the relationship between an individual's choices in the gain and loss conditions in our hypothetical payoff sessions (81 subjects). The blue bar in the back

right corner of the graph (labeled "Reflection") represents subjects who made choices consistent with risk aversion in the lottery over gains, and risk preference in the lottery over losses. This choice pattern is the well known "reflection effect," which is one component of Prospect Theory, as described by Kahneman and Tversky (1979) and Tversky and Kahneman (1992). Although the rate of reflection observed in our experiment (26 percent) is lower than that obtained in Kahneman and Tversky's pair-wise lotteries (with hypothetical payments), this is the modal choice pattern in these sessions. Figure 3 presents the same information when payoffs are real (76 subjects). The difference is dramatic. The rate of reflection (13 percent) is half that observed when hypothetical payments are used. Moreover, the modal choice pattern involves risk aversion under both gains and losses (29 percent). The rate of reflection is even lower when payoffs (real and hypothetical) are increased by a factor of 15 (to 30 times the levels shown in Table 1; earnings from the initial experiment were similarly increased). Only about 19 percent of subjects reflect under high hypothetical payoffs, compared with 9 percent of subjects who faced high real payoffs. Considering the average number of safe choices made under gains and losses, subjects are less risk averse under losses, which is consistent with Prospect Theory's directional prediction. However, people tend to be risk averse for gains and approximately risk neutral for losses (not risk preferring for losses as Prospect Theory predicts), regardless of whether incentives are real or hypothetical, low or high. Harbaugh, Krause, and Vesterlund (2001) similarly find that support for reflection depends on how the choice problem is presented. Specifically, they report that risk attitudes are consistent with Prospect Theory when subjects price gambles, but not when they choose between the gamble and its expected value. Others have found evidence of reflection when cash payments are used (Myagkov and Plott, 1997, Camerer, 1989, and Battalio, et al., 1990). However, taken together, these studies suggest that the degree of observed reflection may be context specific (for example, whether real payments are used, how the choice problem is presented, market context, and initial stake in the loss treatment).

IV. Conclusion The use of monetary incentives may not affect behavior much in some contexts, or it may simply reduce the dispersion of data around some theoretical prediction. But our experiments indicate that incentive effects may be large and systematic in other contexts. In the absence of a widely accepted theory of when incentives matter, it is probably not advisable to derive scientific conclusions from laboratory studies that do not provide clear, salient motivation. While hypothetical choice studies are not common in economics, and are rarely published in the top journals, this is not the case in other disciplines. Al Roth (1995, p. 86) comments that the question of actual versus hypothetical choices has become one of the fault lines that have come to distinguish experiments published in the economics journals from those published in psychology journals. In a recent paper, Hertwig and Ortmann (2001) reviewed all papers published in the Journal of Behavioral Decision Making for a recent 10-year period. In 186 experimental studies, financial incentives were only used in 26% of those. In a second survey of about 100 papers on Bayesian inference tasks in a variety of psychology journals, only about 2-3 papers used financial incentives. The evidence surveyed here shows that relying on hypothetical payments can yield misleading results in some circumstances. Moreover, social scientists do not have a good feel for when to believe hypothetical choice patterns. Given this, we believe that performance based incentives should be used in economics experiments, and results motivated by hypothetical incentives should be interpreted with caution.

References Battalio, R. C., J. H. Kagel, and Komain Jiranyakul (1990) Testing Between Alternative Models of Choice Under Uncertainty: Some Initial Results, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 3(1), 25-50. Binswanger, H. P. (1980) Attitude Toward Risk: Experimental Measurement in Rural India, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 62: 395-407. Camerer, C. F. (1989) An Experimental Test of Several Generalized Utility Theories, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2, 61-104. Harbaugh, W., K. Krause, and L. Vesterlund (2001) "Prospect Theory in Choice and Pricing Tasks," Working Paper. Hertwig, R. and Ortmann, A. (2001) Experimental Practices in Economics: A Challenge for Psychologists? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24 (4). Holt, C. A. and Laury, S. K. (2001) Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects, Working Paper, Department of Economics, University of Virginia. Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (1979) Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Choice Under Risk, Econometrica, 47(2):263-291. Laury, S. K. and Holt, C. A. (2002) Further Reflections on Prospect Theory, Working Paper, Department of Economics, Georgia State University. Myagkov, M. and C. R. Plott (1997) Exchange Economies and Loss Exposure: Experiments Exploring Prospect Theory and Competitive Equilibria in Market Environments, American Economic Review, 87(5): 801-828. Roth, A. E. (1995) Introduction to Experimental Economics, in J. Kagel and A. Roth, eds., Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Siegel, S. and Goldstein, D. A. (1959) Decision Making Behavior in a Two-choice Uncertain Outcome Situation, Journal of Experimental Psychology, 57: 37-42. Smith, V. L. and J. M. Walker (1993) Monetary Rewards and Decision Costs in Experimental Economics, Economic Inquiry, 31(2): 245-261. Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1992) Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5:297-323.

Figure 1. Percentage of Safe Choices Under Real and Hypothetical Conditions (1x, 20x, 50x, and 90x Payoff Scale) 1 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.6 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.1 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 Decision Number Key: Real Payoffs (thick lines), Hypothetical Payoffs (thin lines), Risk Neutral Precition (thin, dashed line)

Figure 2. Risk Aversion Categories for Losses and Gains (Hypothetical Payoffs) 0.3 Reflection 0.25 Observed Frequency 0.2 0.15 0.1 0.05 Gain Domai Risk n Averse Risk Neutral 0 Risk Averse Risk Neutral Loss Domain Risk Loving Risk Loving

Figure 3. Risk Aversion Categories for Losses and Gains (Real Payoffs) 0.3 0.25 Observed Frequency 0.2 0.15 0.1 Reflection Gain Domai n Risk Averse 0.05 Risk Neutral 0 Risk Loving Risk Averse Risk Neutral Loss Domain Risk Loving