Alternative sources of information-based trade

Similar documents
FIN CORPORATE FINANCE Spring Office: CBA 6.246, Phone: ,

Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information

Background Risk and Trading in a Full-Information Rational Expectations Economy

Information and Evidence in Bargaining

Measuring the Amount of Asymmetric Information in the Foreign Exchange Market

A Model of Rational Speculative Trade

Finish what s been left... CS286r Fall 08 Finish what s been left... 1

Definition of Incomplete Contracts

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Economics and Finance

Are more risk averse agents more optimistic? Insights from a rational expectations model

COMPARATIVE MARKET SYSTEM ANALYSIS: LIMIT ORDER MARKET AND DEALER MARKET. Hisashi Hashimoto. Received December 11, 2009; revised December 25, 2009

Financial Fragility A Global-Games Approach Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Asset Pricing(HON109) University of International Business and Economics

Lecture B-1: Economic Allocation Mechanisms: An Introduction Warning: These lecture notes are preliminary and contain mistakes!

Auction Theory: Some Basics

Chapter One NOISY RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS WITH STOCHASTIC FUNDAMENTALS

Bilateral trading with incomplete information and Price convergence in a Small Market: The continuous support case

Contagious Adverse Selection

Advanced Macroeconomics I ECON 525a, Fall 2009 Yale University. Syllabus

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome.

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Social learning and financial crises

All Equilibrium Revenues in Buy Price Auctions

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty

Financial Market Feedback:

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky

Financial Market Feedback and Disclosure

Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk

Optimal Auctions. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham

Discussion of Liquidity, Moral Hazard, and Interbank Market Collapse

Ambiguous Information and Trading Volume in stock market

Liquidity and Asset Prices in Rational Expectations Equilibrium with Ambiguous Information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3

Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

Making Derivative Warrants Market in Hong Kong

The Value of Information in an Agency Model with Moral Hazard

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure

Robust Trading Mechanisms with Budget Surplus and Partial Trade

ISSN BWPEF Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions. Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University of London.

Price Discrimination As Portfolio Diversification. Abstract

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

Internet Trading Mechanisms and Rational Expectations

SONDERFORSCHUNGSBEREICH 504

Speculative Bubble Burst

Signaling in an English Auction: Ex ante versus Interim Analysis

2. Elementary model of a static double auction: independent, private values

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

Advanced Microeconomics

Adverse Selection, Reputation and Sudden Collapses in Securitized Loan Markets

PERSPECTIVES ON MECHANISM DESIGN IN ECONOMIC THEORY Roger Myerson, 8 Dec

Measuring and explaining liquidity on an electronic limit order book: evidence from Reuters D

Information aggregation in dynamic markets under ambiguity

Uberrimae Fidei and Adverse Selection: the equitable legal judgment of Insurance Contracts

Ex post renegotiation-proof mechanism design

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions and Nash Paths

Commitment to Overinvest and Price Informativeness 1

Essays on Heterogeneous Beliefs, Public Information, and Asset Pricing

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński

Winners and Losers from Price-Level Volatility: Money Taxation and Information Frictions

Institutional Finance Financial Crises, Risk Management and Liquidity

ADVERSE SELECTION PAPER 8: CREDIT AND MICROFINANCE. 1. Introduction

Sequential Financial Market Trading: The Role of Endogenous Timing

Empirical Tests of Information Aggregation

Endogenous Information Acquisition with Sequential Trade

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

Lectures on Trading with Information Competitive Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibrium (Grossman and Stiglitz AER (1980))

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Essays on Herd Behavior Theory and Criticisms

Notes on Syllabus Section VI: TIME AND UNCERTAINTY, FUTURES MARKETS

Chapter 3. Dynamic discrete games and auctions: an introduction

A study on the significance of game theory in mergers & acquisitions pricing

1. Information, Equilibrium, and Efficiency Concepts 2. No-Trade Theorems, Competitive Asset Pricing, Bubbles

Transaction Costs and the Robustness of the Coase Theorem

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Revenue Equivalence and Mechanism Design

Debt Contracts and Cooperative Improvements

Volume 31, Issue 3. The dividend puzzle and tax: a note. Frank Strobel University of Birmingham

Insider trading with partially informed traders

Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game

LectureNote: MarketMicrostructure

sequence economies S000097

On Effects of Asymmetric Information on Non-Life Insurance Prices under Competition

On Information Asymmetry as a Source of Value: Intermediation, Auctions and Information

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation

An Ascending Double Auction

Dynamic Market Making and Asset Pricing

Behavioral Equilibrium and Evolutionary Dynamics

An Ascending Double Auction

Incentive Compatibility: Everywhere vs. Almost Everywhere

1 Rational Expectations Equilibrium

Learning whether other Traders are Informed

Transcription:

no trade theorems [ABSTRACT No trade theorems represent a class of results showing that, under certain conditions, trade in asset markets between rational agents cannot be explained on the basis of differences in information alone. They pose a challenge to provide a theoretical justification of the high trade volumes observed in financial markets. This article overviews existing no trade theorems and discusses alternative approaches to modelling information-based trade. ] The very high levels of daily trading activity observed in many financial markets are often attributed to speculation: agents hold different views about how much assets are worth for instance, they may have different expectations about future prices and these differences should lead them to trade. Rational agents typically hold distinct opinions if they privately observe different information. Thus, as this reasoning goes, the arrival of asymmetric information should induce agents to trade. No trade theorems challenge this premise by showing that, if the initial asset allocation is commonly known to be efficient, then any proposed trade after the arrival of new information cannot lead to a Pareto improvement over the initial allocation as long as traders interpret information in a similar fashion. As a consequence, agents do not have an incentive to trade after receiving the new information. The logic behind these results goes as follows. Consider the market of an asset in which it is common knowledge, before the arrival of new information, that the initial allocation is efficient. This implies that the asset is allocated to the agents that value it the most. Otherwise, there would be a mutually beneficial trade in which some agents holding units of the asset sell them to agents with higher valuations, contradicting the fact that the initial allocation is efficient. With the arrival of new information, some agents may value the asset more than those holding it if the former receive a more positive signal about the asset value than the latter and if agents only consider their own signal when updating their beliefs about the asset. Thus, without considering any additional information, they could get to a better allocation by trading. However, the fact that an agent is willing to acquire units of the asset at a given price conveys some information about the signal she received. Since traders interpret signals in a similar fashion, this additional information should be taken into account by the potential sellers, who then revise upwards their beliefs about the asset and become unwilling to trade at the proposed price, even though they would have agreed to trade had they only considered their own signals. No trade theorems have proven to be a major hurdle not only in the modelling of information-based trade, but also in analysing other aspects of trade under incomplete information, such as information aggregation or information acquisition in markets. In particular, they highlight a well-known paradox associated with the efficient markets hypothesis (Grossman and Stiglitz, 1980): if market prices reflect all the relevant information possessed by agents about asset values, traders sharing common prior beliefs cannot take advantage of their private information and thus have no incentive to acquire it in the first place. 1

Theoretical results There are three basic elements in no trade theorems: efficiency of the initial allocation, common knowledge of the institutional and informational environment, and some degree of agreement in they way new information should be interpreted. Efficiency of the initial allocation implies that, before the arrival of information, there is no alternative allocation that Pareto dominates it. Common knowledge requires that agents have correct beliefs about the beliefs of others and about their equilibrium behavior and all this is commonly known by all agents. Finally, traders need to exhibit some similarities in the way they interpret new information. The strongest assumption implies agents having common priors about the distribution of asset values and private information. In this context, rational agents cannot agree to disagree (Aumann, 1976; Geanakoplos, 1994), i.e. they cannot hold different beliefs after observing the same information. Weaker notions include noisy versions of concordant beliefs (priors about the value of the asset may differ but traders share the same beliefs about the distribution of information conditional on asset values) and consistent beliefs (receiving the same information leads to the same posterior beliefs). The gist of no trade theorems is to show that efficiency of the allocation before the arrival of new information leads to efficiency of the same allocation after agents receive new information. Accordingly, the stronger the notion of efficiency, the stronger the compatibility requirements on agents beliefs (see Holmstrom and Myerson (1983) for a classification of efficiency notions). It turns out that the relevant type of efficiency depends on the notion of market equilibrium, which establishes which types of trade are considered feasible. Most no trade theorems focus on three different equilibrium notions: common knowledge trade; incentive compatible trade; and rational expectations equilibria. Common knowledge trade refers to the case in which agents do not behave strategically, trades are public, and markets are complete (i.e. there exist a complete set of Arrow Debreu securities), so that trades contingent on the true state of the world are possible. In this context, it will be common knowledge for rational traders that when a public trade is carried out it is because it is feasible and mutually beneficial. If agents behave strategically feasible trades are those that induce agents to truthfully reveal their private information (incentive compatible trade). Finally, rational expectations equilibrium refers to the case in which agents are non-strategic and trades are contingent on prices, which potentially reflect agents private information. Morris (1994) identifies the relevant types of efficiency of the initial allocation that lead to no trade for these alternative equilibrium concepts and provides the corresponding restrictions on traders beliefs. Early no trade theorems (Rubinstein, 1975; Kreps, 1977; Tirole, 1982; Sebenius and Geanakoplos, 1983) focus on the common prior assumption to show that if agents are risk averse no mutually beneficial trade exists after the arrival of information. Milgrom and Stokey (1982) show that concordant beliefs are sufficient to rule out common knowledge trade. Generalising this result, Dow et al. (1990) show that, if the initial allocation is ex ante efficient with respect to prior beliefs, common knowledge trade is ruled out regardless of the nexus between prior and posterior beliefs, as long as agents are rational. On the other hand, Morris (1994) shows that consistent beliefs are associated with no trade when agents are strategic (incentive compatible trade). There are also no trade theorems dealing with the case where all information is public (Hakansson et al., 1982). 2

One may be tempted to regard no trade theorems as theoretical artifacts without much empirical content. After all, agents face uncertainty in most asset markets about the number of participants, their beliefs and the sources of information they may have access to, rendering the common knowledge assumption too restrictive. However, as we explore ways to break no trade results it becomes apparent that speculative trade does not trivially follow from weakening the conditions underlying no trade theorems. Alternative sources of information-based trade There are different routes taken by the literature to elicit trade in models of asset markets under asymmetric information. The most frequent approaches either weaken the common knowledge assumption or exogenously introduce liquidity in the market, i.e. make the initial allocation inefficient due to demand shocks. Other approaches allow agents to agree to disagree by introducing bounded rationality. Finally, some models introduce uncertainty in the market. Here is a brief overview: Lack of common knowledge: There are different ways in which the common knowledge assumption can be relaxed. For instance, traders may not have common knowledge about potential disagreements over the asset value that asymmetric information creates, or they may not have common knowledge about the rationality of other traders. One way of relaxing it is to require that traders have common beliefs rather than common knowledge (see Monderer and Samet, 1989) for a definition of common beliefs), which implies that agents are not completely certain about other agents beliefs or their rationality. In the context of common knowledge trade, Neeman (1996) shows that common belief of potential disagreements leads to trade only if rationality is not common knowledge. One interpretation of this result is that speculative trade can occur if agents exhibit some overconfidence: even if all traders are rational, some believe it is possible that other traders may not be so, or that other traders may (erroneously) think so. Another approach to relax common knowledge is to let agents interpret information in a dissimilar fashion or to introduce doubts about how to interpret information, whether public or private. Differences in interpretation of public information among bayesian agents may arise with common priors if agents additionally receive private information (Andreoni and Mylovanov, 2010) or when they hold different priors and are uncertain about how to interpret some signals (Acemoglu et al., 2009). Demand shocks/noise traders: Many theoretical models aimed at studying information aggregation, insider trading and other interesting phenomena in financial markets get around no trade by introducing exogenous sources of liquidity, that is, positive demand/supply for the asset at any given price. This is done by either having aggregate demand shocks (Hellwig, 1980; Diamond and Verrecchia, 1981; Kyle, 1985, 1989) or by introducing agents with immediate (exogenous) liquidity needs willing to sell/buy at current prices (Glosten and Milgrom, 1985; Easley and O Hara, 1992). Bounded rationality: There are many ways in which bounded rationality and psychological biases in the way agents update beliefs can elicit trade. Geanakoplos 3

(1989) characterizes the conditions on the information structures associated to bounded rationality under which speculative trade is possible, which basically require agents information structures not being represented by a partition of the space of possible states of the world (see Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1990) for an example of speculative trade when information structures are non-partitional). Uncertainty: A potential way to elicit trade is to introduce (Knightian) uncertainty by letting agents hold multiple priors rather than a single one. In this context, Kajii and Ui (2009) show that for certain classes of preferences under uncertainty the updating rule mapping priors to posteriors is the key determinant of the existence of speculative trade. A no trade theorem still applies if the set of posterior beliefs is the collection of all conditional probability distributions of the priors (full bayesian updating). If, on the other hand, the set of posteriors is the collection of all conditional distributions that maximize the likelihood of the observed private information (maximum likelihood updating) speculative trade can happen. Dow et al. (1990) provide an early example of trade in the presence of uncertainty when the arrival of information completely resolves all of the initial uncertainty. Ricardo Serrano-Padial See also asymmetric information; common knowledge. Bibliography Acemoglu, D., Chernozhukov, V. and Yildiz, M. 2009. Fragility of asymptotic agreement under bayesian learning. Mimeo. Andreoni, J. and Mylovanov, T. 2010. Diverging opinions. Mimeo. Aumann, R.J. 1976. Agreeing to disagree. Annals of Statistics 4, 1236 1239. Diamond, D.W. and Verrecchia, R.E. 1981. Information aggregation in a noisy rational expectations economy. Journal of Financial Economics 9, 221 235. Dow, J., Madrigal, V. and Werlang, S. d. C. 1990. Preferences, Common Knowledge and Speculative Trade. IFA Working Paper, pp. 125 190. Easley, D. and O Hara, M. 1992. Time and the process of security price adjustment. Journal of Finance 47(2), 577 605. Geanakoplos, J.D. 1989. Game theory without partitions, and applications to speculation and consensus. Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper no. 914. Geanakoplos, J. 1994. Common knowledge. In Handbook of Game Theory II (eds. R. Aumann and S. Hart), pp. 1437 1496. Elsevier Science, Amsterdam. Glosten, L.R. and Milgrom, P.R. 1985. Bid, ask and transaction prices in a specialist market with heterogeneously informed traders. Journal of Financial Economics 14, 71 100. Grossman, S.J. and Stiglitz, J. E. 1980. On the impossibility of informationally efficient markets. American Economic Review 70(3), 393 408. 4

Hakansson, N.H., Kunkel, J.G. and Ohlson, J.A. 1982. Sufficient and necessary conditions for information to have social value in pure exchange. Journal of Finance 37, 1169 1181. Hellwig, M.F. 1980. On the aggregation of information in competitive markets. Journal of Economic Theory 22, 477 498. Holmstrom, B. and Myerson, R.B. 1983. Efficient and durable decision rules with incomplete information. Econometrica 51(6), 1799 1819. Kajii, A. and Ui, T. 2009. Interim efficient allocations under uncertainty. Journal of Economic Theory 144(1), 337 353. Kreps, D. M. 1977. A note on fulfilled expectations equilibria. Journal of Economic Theory 14, 32 44. Kyle, A.S. 1985. Continuous auctions and insider trading. Econometrica 53(6), 1315 1336. Kyle, A.S. 1989. Informed speculation with imperfect competition. Review of Economic Studies 56(3), 317 355. Milgrom, P.R. and Stokey, N. 1982. Information, trade and common knowledge. Journal of Economic Theory 26, 17 27. Monderer, D. and Samet, D. 1989. Approximating common knowledge with common beliefs. Games and Economic Behavior 1, 170 190. Morris, S. 1994. Trade with heterogeneous prior beliefs and asymmetric information. Econometrica 62(6), 1327 1347. Neeman, Z. 1996. Common beliefs and the existence of speculative trade. Games and Economic Behavior 16, 77 96. Rubinstein, A. 1975. Security market efficiency in an Arrow Debreu economy. American Economic Review 65, 812 824. Rubinstein, A. and Wolinsky, A. 1990. On the logic of agreeing to disagree type results. Journal of Economic Theory 51, 184 193. Sebenius, J.K. and Geanakoplos, J.D. 1983. Don t bet on it: contingent agreements with asymmetric information. Journal of the American Statistical Association 78, 424 426. Tirole, J. 1982. On the possibility of speculation under rational expectations. Econometrica 50(5), 1163 1182. Key words: asset markets, demand shocks, no trade theorems, trade volume, uncertainty 5