Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky- Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function: A Cautionary Note

Similar documents
Financial Economics. A Concise Introduction to Classical and Behavioral Finance Chapter 2. Thorsten Hens and Marc Oliver Rieger

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Martina Nardon and Paolo Pianca. Prospect theory: An application to European option pricing

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Utility Maximization for an Investor with Asymmetric Attitude to Gains and Losses over the Mean Variance Efficient Frontier

Behavioral Finance Driven Investment Strategies

Choice under Uncertainty

Casino gambling problem under probability weighting

PURE-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA WITH NON-EXPECTED UTILITY PLAYERS

Measuring the Benefits from Futures Markets: Conceptual Issues

Outline. Simple, Compound, and Reduced Lotteries Independence Axiom Expected Utility Theory Money Lotteries Risk Aversion

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

Path-Dependent and Randomized Strategies in Barberis Casino Gambling Model

Time Diversification under Loss Aversion: A Bootstrap Analysis

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Advanced Risk Management

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Stocks as Lotteries: The Implications of Probability Weighting for Security Prices

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership

Optimizing S-shaped utility and risk management

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

EFFICIENT MARKETS HYPOTHESIS

Reference Dependence Lecture 1

Introduction. Two main characteristics: Editing Evaluation. The use of an editing phase Outcomes as difference respect to a reference point 2

Static portfolio choice under Cumulative Prospect Theory

Pricing Strategy under Reference-Dependent Preferences: Evidence from Sellers on StubHub

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

Distortion operator of uncertainty claim pricing using weibull distortion operator

The Capital Asset Pricing Model in the 21st Century. Analytical, Empirical, and Behavioral Perspectives

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

CONSUMPTION-BASED MACROECONOMIC MODELS OF ASSET PRICING THEORY

RISK AND RETURN REVISITED *

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

General Equilibrium with Risk Loving, Friedman-Savage and other Preferences

The Effect of Pride and Regret on Investors' Trading Behavior

RISK POOLING IN THE PRESENCE OF MORAL HAZARD

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Citation Economic Modelling, 2014, v. 36, p

The Role of Risk Aversion and Intertemporal Substitution in Dynamic Consumption-Portfolio Choice with Recursive Utility

Prospect Theory: A New Paradigm for Portfolio Choice

Demand for Insurance: Which Theory Fits Best?

Choice under risk and uncertainty

The analysis of real estate investment value based on prospect theory-- with an example in Hainan province

Behavioral Economics (Lecture 1)

Building Consistent Risk Measures into Stochastic Optimization Models

Sequential Auctions and Auction Revenue

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours

Financial Mathematics III Theory summary

ESTIMATION OF UTILITY FUNCTIONS: MARKET VS. REPRESENTATIVE AGENT THEORY

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Portfolio Selection with Quadratic Utility Revisited

Comparative Risk Sensitivity with Reference-Dependent Preferences

Financial Giffen Goods: Examples and Counterexamples

Prospect Theory and the Size and Value Premium Puzzles. Enrico De Giorgi, Thorsten Hens and Thierry Post

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

Optimal Investment with Transaction Costs under Cumulative Prospect Theory in Discrete Time

Solving the Yitzhaki paradoxe: Income tax evasion and reference dependence under cumulative prospect theory

Prospect Theory, Partial Liquidation and the Disposition Effect

ON INTEREST RATE POLICY AND EQUILIBRIUM STABILITY UNDER INCREASING RETURNS: A NOTE

ECON Financial Economics

On the evolution of probability-weighting function and its impact on gambling

The month of the year effect explained by prospect theory on Polish Stock Exchange

On the Judgment Proof Problem

A NOTE ON SANDRONI-SHMAYA BELIEF ELICITATION MECHANISM

QED. Queen s Economics Department Working Paper No. 1228

In Search of a Better Estimator of Interest Rate Risk of Bonds: Convexity Adjusted Exponential Duration Method

Prize-linked savings mechanism in the portfolio selection framework

Fractional Liu Process and Applications to Finance

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

A Double Counting Problem in the Theory of Rational Bubbles

Contents. Expected utility

An Improved Saddlepoint Approximation Based on the Negative Binomial Distribution for the General Birth Process

B. Online Appendix. where ɛ may be arbitrarily chosen to satisfy 0 < ɛ < s 1 and s 1 is defined in (B1). This can be rewritten as

What Industry Should We Privatize?: Mixed Oligopoly and Externality

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

Noureddine Kouaissah, Sergio Ortobelli, Tomas Tichy University of Bergamo, Italy and VŠB-Technical University of Ostrava, Czech Republic

Long run equilibria in an asymmetric oligopoly

Solving the Yitzhaki Paradox: Income Tax Evasion and Reference Dependence under Prospect Theory

Keeping Up with the Joneses Preferences: Asset Pricing Considerations

Pension scheme derisiking. An application of prospect theory to pension incentive exercises. June 4, 2018

Lecture 8: Asset pricing

Bargaining and Coalition Formation

* Financial support was provided by the National Science Foundation (grant number

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano

Sharpe Ratio over investment Horizon

Comparative statics of monopoly pricing

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Last-Call Auctions with Asymmetric Bidders

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Martina Nardon and Paolo Pianca. Covered call writing in a cumulative prospect theory framework

Characterization of the Optimum

Problem Set 3 Solutions

arxiv: v2 [q-fin.pr] 23 Nov 2017

Transcription:

European Financial Management, Vol. 14, No. 3, 2008, 385 390 doi: 10.1111/j.1468-036X.2007.00439.x Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky- Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function: A Cautionary Note Jonathan Ingersoll Yale School of Management, USA E-mail: jonathan.ingersoll@yale.edu Abstract Cumulative Prospect Theory has gained a great deal of support as an alternative to Expected Utility Theory as it accounts for a number of anomalies in the observed behavior of economic agents. Expected Utility Theory uses a utility function and subjective or objective probabilities to compare risky prospects. Cumulative Prospect Theory alters both of these aspects. The concave utility function is replaced by a loss-averse utility function and probabilities are replaced by decision weights. The latter are determined with a weighting function applied to the cumulative probability of the outcomes. Several different probability weighting functions have been suggested. The two most popular are the original proposal of Tversky and Kahneman and the compound-invariant form proposed by Prelec. This note shows that the Tversky-Kahneman probability weighting function is not increasing for all parameter values and therefore can assign negative decision weights to some outcomes. This in turn implies that Cumulative Prospect Theory could make choices not consistent with first-order stochastic dominance. Keywords: JEL classification: prospect theory, decision weights, probability-weighting function C91, D10, D81, G19 Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT) has been used in a wide variety of economic models as an alternative to Expected Utility Theory (EUT). It is used to account for a number of anomalies in the observed behaviour of economic agents. Like EUT, CPT uses a utility or value function to rate any given outcome. In CPT, however, the utility function is loss averse (S-shaped) rather than risk averse (concave). The other difference between the two theories is the use of decision weights rather than probabilities in computing the expectation. This note provides a caution on the use of a popular form of decision weights those proposed by Tversky and Kahneman (1992) in their introduction of the The author has benefited from his discussions with his colleagues, in particular Nick Barberis. He also thanks an anonymous referee for expository help on the manuscript., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.

386 Jonathan Ingersoll theory. In particular, the weights generated by their proposed probability weighting function can be negative for some parameter values. This could lead to evaluations that choose first-order stochastically dominated gambles rather than the dominating one. The parameter values that can cause such problems are small relative to estimated values. Nevertheless, failure to recognise this problem may prevent the proofs of some theorems or allow the proof of some theorems which would be invalid with properly restricted probability weights. The Tversky-Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function In Prospect Theory, the expected utility of any risky prospect with outcomes x i is computed as v(xi )ω i (p) (1) where v is a value (utility) function and ω i are a set of decision weights. In the original application of Prospect Theory, each decision weight was a function of the probability of the outcome; in CPT, decisions weights depend on the probability distribution. They are determined as first differences of a probability-weighting function applied to the cumulative probabilities, p i, ω i = (p i ) (p i 1 ). 1 The particular probability-weighting function originally proposed by Tversky and Kahneman (1992) is p γ (p) = 0 <γ 1 (2) [p γ + (1 p) γ ] 1/γ where p is the cumulative probability of the distribution of gains or losses. As shown in Figure 1, this weighting function has an inverted S-shape and is subproportional. 2 The latter property allows for the Allais paradox and can explain the preference for lottery tickets. Since the decision weights take the place of probabilities in the computation of expected utility, they must be positive. If they are not positive, then a first-order stochastically dominated gamble might be preferred to the dominating gamble. 3 The decision weights are first differences and will be positive for all possible risky prospects only if the weighting function is strictly increasing. But the Tversky- Kahneman probability-weighting function does not posses this property for all parameter values. Let F(p) ln[ (p)]. Since the logarithm is a strictly-increasing function, the probability-weighting function,, is strictly increasing in p if and only if F is strictly 1 In CPT, separate weighting functions are used for the probability distribution of losses and the complementary distribution of gains, but this is irrelevant to the issue presented here which is about the properties of the weighting function itself. If p(x) is a cumulative probability function for a continuous distribution with density p (x), then the continuous decision weighting density function is ω(x) = (p)p (x). 2 A function is subproportional if for p > q and 0 <λ<1, (λq)/ (q) > (λp)/ (p). 3 Let x > x and consider two risky prospects which are identical except for the inclusion of either x or x as the ith outcome. Now suppose that ω i < 0, then the dominated gamble including x will be preferred when using decision weights.

Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky-Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function 387 Fig. 1. Tversky-Kahneman probability weighting function and marginal increasing in p. The derivative of F(p) is F (p) = γ p pγ 1 (1 p) γ 1 p γ + (1 p) γ = γ pγ + γ (1 p) γ p γ + p(1 p) γ 1. (3) p[p γ + (1 p) γ ] Since the denominator of the last fraction is positive, F is negative whenever the numerator is negative. Dividing the numerator by (1 p) γ, we see that F is negative when p γ (γ 1) (1 p) + γ + p < 0. (4) γ 1 p Define x p/(1 p), then we are looking for values of the weighting function parameter, γ, for which the function f (x) (γ 1)x γ + x + γ (5) can take on negative values for some positive x. Note that f (0) = γ>0, f ( ) =, and f is strictly convex f (x) = γ (γ 1)x γ 1 + 1 0 f (x) = γ (γ 1) 2 x γ 2 (6) > 0. Therefore, the function f will take on negative values over some range when it is negative at its minimum. The minimum occurs at f (x) = γ (γ 1)x γ 1 + 1 = 0 x min = [γ (1 γ )] 1/(1 γ ) (7) So the minimum value of f for a given value of the parameter γ is f min (γ ) f (x min ) = (γ 1)[γ (1 γ )] γ/(1 γ ) + [γ (1 γ )] 1/(1 γ ) + γ = γ [ 1 (1 γ ) (2 γ )/(1 γ ) γ (2γ 1)/(1 γ )]. (8)

388 Jonathan Ingersoll Fig. 2. Tversky-Kahneman probability weighting function illustrating non-monotonicity for γ<0.279 By inspection, there is a critical value, γ critical, where f min = 0. For all values of γ less than this critical value, f min < 0, and the probability weighting-function is nonmonotonic. The critical value satisfies 1 = (1 γ ) (2 γ ) γ (2γ 1) γ critical 0.279. (9) Figure 2 illustrates the Tversky-Kahneman probability-weighting function for a parameter value of γ = 0.25. Note that the derivative is negative over the approximate range 1.6% < p < 23.6%. Any continuous probability density will have a corresponding decision weight density which is negative over this range. A discrete distribution with two (or more) cumulative probabilities in this range will have a negative decision weight(s) for the corresponding outcome(s), and could have others. If just one cumulative probability is in this range, the corresponding outcome may have a positive or negative weight. 4 Tversky and Kahneman (1992) estimated the parameters γ = 0.69 for losses and γ = 0.61 for gains. Other estimates have varied widely; Camerer and Ho (1994) report on eleven tests whose estimates for γ range from 0.28 to 1.87 with an average value of 0.55. All of these point estimates for γ are above the critical value and would lead to a monotone probability-weighting function and generate only positive decision weights. Nevertheless, the range of estimates reported does not engender great confidence that all future studies would continue to do this. Probably of more concern, however, is the use of this probability-weighting function in theory. If the Tversky-Kahneman weighting function is posited, and no restriction is placed on the parameter, it is very possible, that some results might not be provable due 4 Precisely if the cumulative probability, p i, for a discrete distribution lies in the range of decreasing, then either or both ω i and ω i +1 could be negative. If p i 1 (p i +1 ) is also in the decreasing range, then ω i (ω i +1 ) will definitely be negative.

Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky-Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function 389 to the possibility of first-order stochastic dominance. Conversely some results might be obtained that could not hold if the weighting function did not generate negative decision weights. For example, in another paper (Ingersoll, 2007), I have extended the standard result in portfolio theory that in a complete market all risk-averse investors hold portfolios with perfect rank correlation to include investors who use decision weights. This result is only true if the probability-weighting function is monotone. Other Probability-Weighting Functions Several other probability weighting functions have also been proposed. Some of them are: 5 (p) = p γ [p γ + (1 p) γ ] α Wu and Gonzalez (1996) α p γ (p) = α p γ + (1 p) γ Lattimore, Baker, and Witte (1992) (p) = γ exp [ β( ln p) α ] Compound-Invariant Prelec (1998) (p) = γ exp [ β(1 p η ) / η ] Conditionally-Invariant Prelec (1998) (p) = γ (1 αln p) β/α Projection-Invariant Prelec (1998) (10) In each case, 0 <γ 1, α>0, β>0, and η is unconstrained. 6 The LBW and all of the Prelec probability weighting functions are strictly increasing for all relevant parameter values d [ln (p)] = dp γ (1 p) γ 1 > 0 Lattimore, Baker, and Witte (1992) α p γ +1 + p(1 p) γ αβ p ( ln p)α 1 > 0 Compound Invariant. β p η 1 > 0 Conditionally Invariant γβ p (p) (1 αln p) β/α 1 > 0 Projection Invarianct (11) They cannot, therefore, assign negative decision weights to any outcomes for any probability distribution. The Wu and Gonzalez weighting function is also strictly increasing and cannot assign negative decision weights provided α 1. However, for α >1, negative decision weights are possible in some cases. This is clearly true since the TK weighting function is the special case, α = 1/γ. 5 Karmarkar s (1978) weighting function is included as a special case with α = 1 of either the Wu and Gonzalez (1996) or Lattimore, Baker, and Witte (1992) weighting function. It is strictly increasing for all parameter values just like the latter. 6 For η = 0, the conditional-invariance probability weighting function is (p) = γ p β.

390 Jonathan Ingersoll Conclusion The purpose of this note is not to comment directly on Cumulative Prospect Theory. Rather it is to point out a possible obstacle in its use. Some parameter values of the commonly used probability-weighting function, originally proposed by Tversy and Kahneman, can lead to negative decision weights and the preference for first-order stochastically dominated prospects. While the parameter values which allow this seem to be empirically not relevant, the problem could lead to awkward interpretations of results. In addition, in theoretical work, certain consequences might be found which would not obtain were only positive decision weights allowed, or conversely general propositions might remain unverifiable. References Camerer, C. F. and Ho, T.-H., Violations of the betweenness axiom and nonlinearity in probability, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1994, Vol. 8, pp. 167 96. Ingersoll, J., Theoretical prospects for cumulative prospect theory in optimal portfolios, unpublished working paper (Yale School of Management, 2007). Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A., Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk, Econometrica, Vol. 47, 1979, pp. 263 91. Karmarkar, U., Subjective weighted utility: a descriptive extension of the expected utility model, Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, Vol. 21, 1978, pp. 61 72. Lattimore, P. K., Baker, J. R. and White, A. D., The influence of probability on risky choice: a parametric examination, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 17, 1992, pp. 377 400. Prelec, D., The probability weighting function, Econometrica, Vol. 66, 1998, pp. 497 527. Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D., Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 5, 1992, pp. 297 323. Wu, G. and Gonzalez, R., Curvature of the probability weighting function, Management Science, Vol. 42, 1996, pp. 1676 90.