Pareto Concepts 1 / 46

Similar documents
Pareto Concepts 1 / 46

Externalities 1 / 40

Externalities 1 / 40

Market Design. Econ University of Notre Dame

Section 9, Chapter 2 Moral Hazard and Insurance

Chapter 7 Review questions

Theoretical Tools of Public Finance. 131 Undergraduate Public Economics Emmanuel Saez UC Berkeley

ECON 340/ Zenginobuz Fall 2011 STUDY QUESTIONS FOR THE FINAL. x y z w u A u B

PROBLEM SET 6 ANSWERS

October 9. The problem of ties (i.e., = ) will not matter here because it will occur with probability

Market failure Redistribution- Tax or subsidy Restrict or mandate private sale or purchase Public provision Public financing of private provision

Commitment Problems 1 / 24

While the story has been different in each case, fundamentally, we ve maintained:

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance

Chapter 33: Public Goods

January 26,

First Welfare Theorem in Production Economies

Moral Hazard. Economics Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior. Instructor: Songzi Du

ECON 301: General Equilibrium V (Public Goods) 1. Intermediate Microeconomics II, ECON 301. General Equilibrium V: Public Goods

Solution Problem Set 2

Cost Benefit Analysis. April 15, 2018

Second Hour Exam Public Finance Fall, Answers

Generalized Social Marginal Welfare Weights for Optimal Tax Theory

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma

Introduction to Game Theory

Computerized Adaptive Testing: the easy part

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

MS&E 246: Lecture 5 Efficiency and fairness. Ramesh Johari

Overuse of a Common Resource: A Two-player Example

preferences of the individual players over these possible outcomes, typically measured by a utility or payoff function.

if a < b 0 if a = b 4 b if a > b Alice has commissioned two economists to advise her on whether to accept the challenge.

Prisoner s Dilemma. CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma. Prisoner s Dilemma. Prisoner s Dilemma.

Game Theory I. Author: Neil Bendle Marketing Metrics Reference: Chapter Neil Bendle and Management by the Numbers, Inc.

PubPol 201. Module 3: International Trade Policy. Class 2 Outline. Class 2 Outline. Class 2. The Gains and Losses from Trade

Price Theory Lecture 9: Choice Under Uncertainty

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

15 Week 5b Mutual Funds

Chapter 19 Optimal Fiscal Policy

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Game Theory Notes: Examples of Games with Dominant Strategy Equilibrium or Nash Equilibrium

The Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanism

Moral Hazard. Economics Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior. Shih En Lu. Simon Fraser University (with thanks to Anke Kessler)

Answers to June 11, 2012 Microeconomics Prelim

EQ: What is an Indifference Curve? EQ: What is Indifference?

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW-PART 2. Contracts. I.1 Investment in Performance

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1

Graduate Macro Theory II: Two Period Consumption-Saving Models

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy, Tufts University. The Economics of Public Policy. Prof George Alogoskoufis. 1. Introduction

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

PARTIAL EQUILIBRIUM Welfare Analysis

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Closed book/notes exam. No computer, calculator, or any electronic device allowed.

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions.

Supplementary Material to: Peer Effects, Teacher Incentives, and the Impact of Tracking: Evidence from a Randomized Evaluation in Kenya

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

PubPol 201. Module 3: International Trade Policy. Class 2 The Gains and Losses from Trade

ECMC49S Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Feb 27, 2007 Duration: From 3:05pm to 5:00pm Total Marks: 100

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Matching Markets and Google s Sponsored Search

Common Knowledge AND Global Games

Chapter 4. Specific Factors and Income Distribution

Introduction to mechanism design. Lirong Xia

PhD Qualifier Examination

Game Theory. Analyzing Games: From Optimality to Equilibrium. Manar Mohaisen Department of EEC Engineering

CSI 445/660 Part 9 (Introduction to Game Theory)

A brief introduction to economics

Expected value is basically the average payoff from some sort of lottery, gamble or other situation with a randomly determined outcome.

Mohammad Hossein Manshaei 1394

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

LECTURE NOTES ON GAME THEORY. Player 2 Cooperate Defect Cooperate (10,10) (-1,11) Defect (11,-1) (0,0)

CS 573: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture date: 22 February Combinatorial Auctions 1. 2 The Vickrey-Clarke-Groves (VCG) Mechanism 3

Summary The Justifiability and Sustainability of the Corporate Management Inconsistent

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Continuing game theory: mixed strategy equilibrium (Ch ), optimality (6.9), start on extensive form games (6.10, Sec. C)!

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

A brief introduction to economics. Outline. Reading reminder. Risk attitude example (take 3): antivirus software. Notes. Notes. Notes. Notes.

Recall the idea of diminishing marginal utility of income. Recall the discussion that utility functions are ordinal rather than cardinal.

University of Victoria. Economics 325 Public Economics SOLUTIONS

Markets with Intermediaries

Markets with Intermediaries

THEORETICAL TOOLS OF PUBLIC FINANCE

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #9: Beyond Quasi-Linearity

Other Regarding Preferences

EC 202. Lecture notes 14 Oligopoly I. George Symeonidis

The Ben s Strategy Guide for Binary Trading

Public Sector Economics Test Questions Randall Holcombe Fall 2017

CHAPTER 6. Risk Aversion and Capital Allocation to Risky Assets INVESTMENTS BODIE, KANE, MARCUS

Political Economy. Pierre Boyer. Master in Economics Fall 2018 Schedule: Every Wednesday 08:30 to 11:45. École Polytechnique - CREST

Hedonic Equilibrium. December 1, 2011

Coupled with firm subsidies, a minimum wage is not that bad. Alain Trannoy (AMSE and EHESS) 4 th Labor AMSE & Banque de France workshop

Answers To Chapter 6. Review Questions

Transcription:

Pareto Concepts 1 / 46

The Project Consider something much less ambitious than complete agreement on what we mean by good policy Identify limited instances of unequivocally good policy Makes some people better off and no one worse off 2 / 46

Utility Functions Each individual s preferences can be represented with a utility function The utility function, U i, represents person i s preferences if: 1. If person i preferes a policy x to another policy y, then U i (x) > U i (y) 2. If person i is indifferent between x and y, then U i (x) = U i (y) 4 / 46

Pareto Dominance A policy x Pareto dominates another policy y if two conditions are satisfied: 1. No one strictly prefers y to x that is, for all i, U i (x) U i (y). 2. At least one person strictly prefers x to y that is, for at least one i, U i (x) > U i (y). If one policy Pareto dominates another, everyone should be able to agree that policy is better 5 / 46

Pareto Improvement The move from a policy y to an alternative policy x is a Pareto improvement if x Pareto dominates y. From any reasonable welfarist perspective, a policy change that is a Pareto improvement is unambiguously good 6 / 46

Pareto Efficiency A policy x is Pareto efficient if no other policy Pareto dominates it. A policy x is Pareto inefficient if at least one other policy Pareto dominates it. Pareto efficiency is important for two reasons 1. The set of policies from which there is no unambiguously good policy move 2. We know a lot about how to achieve Pareto efficiency 7 / 46

Pareto Efficiency and Pareto Improvements U 1 (x) = 5 U 1 (y) = 2 U 1 (z) = 4 U 2 (x) = 1 U 2 (y) = 3 U 2 (z) = 7 U 3 (x) = 4 U 3 (y) = 1 U 3 (z) = 1 What are the Pareto efficient policies? Is there a Pareto improvement from x, y, z? 9 / 46

Pareto Efficiency and Pareto Improvements 2 U 1 (x) = 3 U 1 (y) = 4 U 1 (z) = 4 U 2 (x) = 3 U 2 (y) = 4 U 2 (z) = 1 U 3 (x) = 3 U 3 (y) = 4 U 3 (z) = 2 What are the Pareto efficient policies? Is there a Pareto improvement from x, y, z? 10 / 46

Pareto Efficiency and Pareto Improvements 3 U 1 (x) = 1 U 1 (y) = 2 U 1 (z) = 3 U 2 (x) = 3 U 2 (y) = 2 U 2 (z) = 0 U 3 (x) = 2 U 3 (y) = 4 U 3 (z) = 0 What are the Pareto efficient policies? Is there a Pareto improvement from x, y, z? 11 / 46

Pareto Efficiency and Pareto Improvements 4 U 1 (x) = 3 U 1 (y) = 4 U 1 (z) = 5 U 2 (x) = 3 U 2 (y) = 4 U 2 (z) = 1 U 3 (x) = 3 U 3 (y) = 4 U 3 (z) = 2 What are the Pareto efficient policies? Is there a Pareto improvement from x, y, z? 12 / 46

Efficiency vs. Improvement U 1 (x) = 5 U 1 (y) = 2 U 1 (z) = 4 U 2 (x) = 1 U 2 (y) = 3 U 2 (z) = 7 U 3 (x) = 4 U 3 (y) = 1 U 3 (z) = 1 y is not Pareto efficient x and z are Pareto efficient Move from y to x not Pareto improvement 14 / 46

The Problem We care about achieving Pareto improvements We know how to achieve Pareto efficiency Moving from a Pareto inefficient to a Pareto efficient policy need not result in a Pareto improvement Distributional concerns Let s see if we can build a bridge between Pareto efficiency and Pareto improvements 15 / 46

The Model of Policy A policy has two components An action A transfer scheme Think of the action as the policy lever to be pulled Free trade, high stakes testing, carbon tax, sanctions The transfer scheme is a redistribution of money 17 / 46

Formalizing the Model Society has n people A is the set of possible actions t = (t 1, t 2,..., t n ) is a transfer scheme Individual transfers can be positive or negative Transfer schemes must have balanced budgets n t i = 0 A policy is a pair (a, t) i=1 18 / 46

Individual Preferences A person i s preferences over policies, (a, t) are given by that person s utility function, U i (a, t) If person i prefers (a, t) to (a, t ), then U i (a, t) > U i (a, t ) If person i is indifferent between (a, t) and (a, t ), then U i (a, t) = U i (a, t ) 19 / 46

An Example Consider a society made up of two people: The Mayor (M) and the Teacher s Union (T ) There are two actions under consideration Using test scores to evaluate teacher performance and determine pay, called Pay for Performance (P P ) Paying teachers solely based on education and seniority, called Seniority Pay (SP ) 20 / 46

Example, continued The Mayor prefers pay for performance U M (P P, (0, 0)) = 10 U M (SP, (0, 0)) = 2 The Teacher s Union prefers seniority pay U T (P P, (0, 0)) = 1 U T (SP, (0, 0)) = 6 21 / 46

Example, continued 2 It may be possible to get both to agree to a move to performance pay by transferring money to the teachers (e.g., raising the average salary) Enough of a transfer might compensate the teachers union for the utility loss from adopting performance pay U M (P P, ( 10, 000, 000, 10, 000, 000)) = 5 U T (P P, ( 10, 000, 000, 10, 000, 000)) = 7 22 / 46

Quasi-Linear Preferences Suppose you can separate person i s utility from a policy (a, t) into two components Payoff from action a is v i (a) Payoff from transfer t i is simply t i U i (a, t) = v i (a) + t i Two important assumptions Payoffs from money are linear, so money = utility Additive separability of transfers and policy 24 / 46

Splitting the Problem QL preferences is a model that allows us to split policy problems into two components: 1. Efficiency: Use action to maximize total utility. 2. Distribution: Use transfers to compensate any losers. Congress created Trade Adjustment Assistance (TAA) in the Trade Expansion Act of 1962 to help workers and firms adjust to dislocation that may be caused by increased trade liberalization. It is justified now, as it was then, on grounds that the government has an obligation to help the losers of policy-driven trade opening. Congressional Research Service 25 / 46

QL and Utilitarianism Under utilitarianism, prefer (x, t) to (y, t ) if and only if U 1 (x, t) + U 2 (x, t) > U 1 (y, t ) + U 2 (y, t ) v 1 (x) + t 1 + v 2 (x) + t 2 > v 1 (y) + t 1 + v 2 (y) + t 2 Given a balanced budget, this is equivalent to: v 1 (x) + v 2 (x) > v 1 (y) + v 2 (y) With QL preferences, transfers don t matter for utilitarianism, all that matters is the utility implications of the action 26 / 46

QL and Pareto Efficiency A Pareto efficient policy is one that is not Pareto dominated Suppose there is a policy (x, t) such that there is some other y x with n i=1 v i(x) < n i=1 v i(y) Under QL, if all budget balanced transfer schemes are possible, (x, t) cannot be Pareto efficient Switch action to y and then choose transfers to make up the difference to any losers There is still utility left over 27 / 46

QL, Pareto Efficiency, and Utilitarianism A policy is only Pareto efficient if it uses the action that maximizes the sum of the v i s Any policy that does so is Pareto efficient Transfers take from one person and give to another, which doesn t affect Pareto efficiency Think about the sum of the v i s as the amount of utility pie One action yields a small pie the other yields a large pie Transfers affect the division of the pie 28 / 46

Any Division of a Small Pie is Pareto Dominated 29 / 46

2 Possible Actions Small pie divided 25% to person 1 and 75% to person 2 Large pie all going to person 1 Suppose no transfers are made Move from the small pie to the large pie is a move to Pareto efficiency Move from small pie to large pie is not a Pareto improvement 30 / 46

31 / 46

Creating a Pareto Improvement If we choose transfers correctly we can always create a Pareto improvement after we move to Pareto efficiency More total utility, so can compensate any distributional losers from action change 32 / 46

33 / 46

34 / 46

An Example 2 actions: Free Trade (F T ) or Protectionism (P ) 2 People: Capital (C) and Labor (L) v C (FT) = 12 v C (P) = 4 v L (FT) = 2 v L (P) = 9 Free trade is the utilitarian optimum 35 / 46

Example, continued Suppose status quo is (P, t C = 0, t L = 0) Not Pareto efficient Pareto improving change: (F T, t C = 7.5, t L = 7.5) Use transfers to compensate Labor for the utility loss associated with free trade 36 / 46

The Bridge We have built a bridge that allows us to first achieve Pareto efficiency and then insure ourselves that we can achieve Pareto improvements This bridge leans on two critical assumptions 1. Correct transfers will be chosen 2. Quasi-linear preferences 38 / 46

Limited Transfers Many factors might get in the way of making transfers Technological constraints (collecting transfers is hard or expensive) Informational constraints (who are the winners and losers) Economic constraints (transfers may induce other kinds of inefficiency) Political constraints (what if losers from action change lack power) If transfers are not made, Pareto efficiency on its own need not be normatively compelling 39 / 46

Non Quasi-Linear Preferences Money is not equal to utility For instance, diminishing marginal utility in money Transfer of equal amount of money from one person to another does not imply transfer of equal amount of utility Suppose the action hurts those who value money very little Have to transfer a lot of money to make up for utility loss Take the money from people who value it a lot See Example 3.4.1 in the book 40 / 46

Relationship to Cost-Benefit Analysis In cost-benefit, we ask something like whether a proposal, on net, increases total utility relative to status quo A policy that fails cost-benefit can t be a Pareto improvement A policy that passes cost-benefit need not be a Pareto improvement Be cautious about using cost-benefit as a normative criterion for good policy 42 / 46

Are Pareto Improvements Really Uncontroversial We ve slipped in a welfarist consequentialism This is not as bad as having slipped in consequentialism about wealth Pareto improvements are unequivocally good if the only thing we care about is utility There are perfectly sensible normative frameworks that would reject some policies that raise everyone s utility Values beyond welfare 43 / 46

Take Aways A policy change that is a Pareto improvement is (maybe) unambiguously good We know a lot about how to achieve Pareto efficiency, but a move to efficiency need not be unambiguously good QL model suggests thinking about achieving Pareto improvements in two steps. 1. Take policy action that improves efficiency (size of pie). 2. Compensate any losers with transfers. 44 / 46

Takeways 2 There are important caveats Will transfers be made? Since preferences aren t actually QL, how justified am I in separating efficiency and distribution? Sometimes you might want to pursue policies that are not Pareto improvements Distributional effects, political effects You are on more tenuous normative grounds 45 / 46

Where We Are Going? Are there really any Pareto improvements to be had? Social dilemmas Fundamental facts about human interactions that create opportunities for good policy We ll need to learn some game theory Governance dilemmas The government is not a Pareto improving machine 46 / 46