MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec

Similar documents
Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

Reputation and Signaling in Asset Sales: Internet Appendix

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Answers to Problem Set 4

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

Supplementary Material for: Belief Updating in Sequential Games of Two-Sided Incomplete Information: An Experimental Study of a Crisis Bargaining

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

STOCHASTIC REPUTATION DYNAMICS UNDER DUOPOLY COMPETITION

FIGURE A1.1. Differences for First Mover Cutoffs (Round one to two) as a Function of Beliefs on Others Cutoffs. Second Mover Round 1 Cutoff.

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Roy Model of Self-Selection: General Case

Persuasion in Global Games with Application to Stress Testing. Supplement

Certification and Exchange in Vertically Concentrated Markets

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Settlement and the Strict Liability-Negligence Comparison

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

Game Theory: Normal Form Games

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Econometrica Supplementary Material

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Universidade de Aveiro Departamento de Economia, Gestão e Engenharia Industrial. Documentos de Trabalho em Economia Working Papers in Economics

Games of Incomplete Information

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec pp. ec1 ec23

Strategic Trading of Informed Trader with Monopoly on Shortand Long-Lived Information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

THEORIES OF BEHAVIOR IN PRINCIPAL-AGENT RELATIONSHIPS WITH HIDDEN ACTION*

Supplemental Material: Buyer-Optimal Learning and Monopoly Pricing

October An Equilibrium of the First Price Sealed Bid Auction for an Arbitrary Distribution.

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

An optimal board system : supervisory board vs. management board

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium

The Irrelevance of Corporate Governance Structure

Feedback Effect and Capital Structure

Sentiments and Aggregate Fluctuations

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion

1 Dynamic programming

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

Price Experimentation with Strategic Buyers

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Dynamic signaling and market breakdown

Lecture Notes on Adverse Selection and Signaling

The Probationary Period as a Screening Device: The Monopolistic Insurer

THE PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIVERSITY. Department of Economics. January Written Portion of the Comprehensive Examination for

Equilibrium payoffs in finite games

Rationalizable Strategies

Reputation and Securitization

DRAFT. 1 exercise in state (S, t), π(s, t) = 0 do not exercise in state (S, t) Review of the Risk Neutral Stock Dynamics

Econ 302 Assignment 3 Solution. a 2bQ c = 0, which is the monopolist s optimal quantity; the associated price is. P (Q) = a b

Basic Informational Economics Assignment #4 for Managerial Economics, ECO 351M, Fall 2016 Due, Monday October 31 (Halloween).

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Directed Search and the Futility of Cheap Talk

The test has 13 questions. Answer any four. All questions carry equal (25) marks.

Choice under Uncertainty

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec pp. ec1 ec14

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

Bargaining Order and Delays in Multilateral Bargaining with Asymmetric Sellers

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

MONOPOLY (2) Second Degree Price Discrimination

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

Economics 703: Microeconomics II Modelling Strategic Behavior

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

Signaling Games. Farhad Ghassemi

Information Acquisition under Persuasive Precedent versus Binding Precedent (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Yao s Minimax Principle

Out of equilibrium beliefs and Refinements of PBE

Information Design in the Hold-up Problem

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

Course notes for EE394V Restructured Electricity Markets: Locational Marginal Pricing

Economics 171: Final Exam

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

The Value of Information in an Agency Model with Moral Hazard

Limitations of Dominance and Forward Induction: Experimental Evidence *

Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ

Ec101: Behavioral Economics

Bailouts, Bank Runs, and Signaling

GERMAN ECONOMIC ASSOCIATION OF BUSINESS ADMINISTRATION GEABA DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES IN ECONOMICS AND MANAGEMENT

Competition among Risk-Averse Newsvendors

Optimal Delay in Committees

B. Online Appendix. where ɛ may be arbitrarily chosen to satisfy 0 < ɛ < s 1 and s 1 is defined in (B1). This can be rewritten as

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky

PURE-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA WITH NON-EXPECTED UTILITY PLAYERS

Trade Costs and Job Flows: Evidence from Establishment-Level Data

Discussion of Risks to Price Stability, The Zero Lower Bound, and Forward Guidance: A Real-Time Assessment

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 7: Moral Hazard. Patrick Legros

Transcription:

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi 10.1287/mnsc.1110.1334ec e-companion ONLY AVAILABLE IN ELECTRONIC FORM informs 2011 INFORMS Electronic Companion Trust in Forecast Information Sharing by Özalp Özer, Yanchong Zheng, and Kay-Yut Chen, Management Science, doi 10.1287/mnsc.1110.1334.

ec2 An e-companion to: Trust in Forecast Information Sharing Appendix EC.1: A Snapshot from the Experiment Software Figure EC.1 provides a snapshot of the supplier s computer screen. Subject role and decision in the current stage of a period Place to input decision Demand and payoff functions Price, cost, and demand constants Reported information from partner Decision support tool: Column 1 gives a list of possible demand values; Column 2 gives the probability of realizing no more than the given demand values; and Column 3 shows the supplier's payoff under the trial capacity for each demand value. Figure EC.1 Sample Snapshot of the Supplier s Screen Appendix EC.2: Additional Experimental Results EC.2.1. Comparing the Capacity Decision to Newsvendor Experiments To see whether there exists any systematic error in the suppliers capacity decision irrespective of whether or not they believe the reports (e.g., the mean anchoring behavior found in Schweitzer and Cachon 2000), we compare the capacity decision with K s (ˆξ) in Equation (3) (i.e., the optimal capacity if they believe the reports) using the Wilcoxon signed rank test. The results show that the capacity decision is significantly lower than K s (ˆξ) in all four treatments (e.g., in Figure 1(b), most of the data points lie below the diagonal line). The fact that the suppliers build less capacity than K s (ˆξ) in the high capacity cost condition is in contrast to the general finding in newsvendor experiments that people buy too much in the low-profit condition. This is a consequence of the existence of asymmetric forecast information. When capacity cost is high, the suppliers are more hesitant to trust the reports because the potential loss is high if the forecast information is inflated. Therefore, they tend to discount a large amount from the reported forecast when determining capacity. This discounting counteracts the

ec3 mean anchoring and insufficient adjustment behavior, and hence ameliorates the systematic decision bias commonly observed in newsvendor experiments with no information asymmetry. EC.2.2. Time Trends in Participants Decisions Are Not Prevalent In 5.2 and 7.2 we show that the coefficients for t in the GLMs indicate some time trends in the participants decisions. To determine whether these time trends are prevalent among the participants, we further test time effects at the individual level; i.e., estimating the following GLMs with each participant s data separately: ˆξ t = Intercept + λ m T t + λ m x ξ t + η t, K t = Intercept + λ m T t + λ s k ˆξ t + η t. The variables have the same interpretation as in Equations (5) and (6). The regression results show that most manufacturers who inflated forecasts more over time and most suppliers who built less capacity over time are involved in treatment C H U L. Since a high capacity cost imposes higher risk for the suppliers to trust the reports, they tended to set low capacity. As the manufacturers learned about this tendency, they inflated the forecasts gradually more to ensure abundant supply. This argument is supported by the participants responses to the post-experiment questionnaire. Nevertheless, these time effects are not prominent in the other treatments. Ultimately, more than 2/3 of the participants in the one-time-interaction treatments and 3/4 of the participants in the repeated-interaction treatments do not exhibit time trends in their decisions. Therefore, we determine that individual decision time trends are not prevalent in our experiments. Here we provide some more detailed discussion about the above result. Figure EC.2 provides two graphical demonstrations for the typical trends of the participants decisions. Figure EC.2(a) shows 70 60 HS RP 100 50 HB RP 50 Forecast Inflation 40 30 20 10 0 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 Periods Capacity Adjustment 0-50 -100-150 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 Periods (a) Manufacturer s Forecast Inflation (b) Supplier s Capacity Adjustment Figure EC.2 Sample Plots of Individual Decisions

ec4 the forecast inflation over time for two manufacturers, one in treatment C H U L (high capacity cost, low market uncertainty, one-time interaction) and the other in treatment RP (repeated interactions, partial information feedback). Figure EC.2(b) shows the capacity decision over time for two suppliers, one in treatment C H U H (high capacity cost, high market uncertainty, one-time interaction) and the other in treatment RP. We plot the capacity adjustment, K (µ + ˆξ), instead of the capacity decision, against time to control for the dependency between K and ˆξ. First observe that both forecast inflation and capacity adjustment are quite stable over time, confirming that participants mainly use stationary strategies in the experiments. Also note that forecast inflation is much higher in C H U L than in RP, and capacity is much lower in C H U H than in RP. This observation further confirms our result that repeated interactions improve the efficacy of forecast sharing and the level of cooperation in a supply chain. Table EC.1 summarizes the regression results for the four participants shown in Figure EC.2. Note that the coefficients for t are not significant, verifying that individual strategies do not change over time. The regression results for other participants who do not exhibit time-varying decisions are similar. Table EC.1 Regression Results for Testing Time Trends in Individual Decisions Forecast Inflation (Figure EC.2(a)) Capacity Decision (Figure EC.2(b)) Estimate (s.e.) Estimate (s.e.) Participant in C HU L Participant in RP Participant in C HU H Participant in RP Intercept 32.099 (2.916) 9.408 (1.060) Intercept 176.152 (11.782) 219.065 (6.580) t -0.003 (0.050) 0.024 (0.020) t -0.078 (0.191) 0.127 (0.122) ξ 0.956 (0.017) 0.997 (0.006) ˆξ 0.550 (0.063) 0.950 (0.040) Note: Values in parentheses are the standard errors; : p-value < 0.01. EC.2.3. Reducing Market Uncertainty Increases Relative Forecast Inflation In this section, we consider forecast inflation as a percentage of the range of market uncertainty (i.e., (ˆξ ξ)/( ɛ ɛ), referred to as relative inflation ) and investigate how relative inflation is affected by changes in market uncertainty. In contrast, we refer to the forecast inflation measured by ˆξ ξ as absolute inflation. We fit the following random-effects GLM: ( ) ˆξ ξ = Intercept + λ C C L + λ U U L + λ CU C L U L + λ x ξ it + λ T t + δ i + ε it, ɛ ɛ it where the variables have the same interpretation as in Equation (5). Table EC.2 summarizes the regression results. We observe that the interaction term C L U L is not significant, so it suffices to consider the effect of market uncertainty regardless of the magnitude of capacity cost. The coefficient for U L is significantly positive (p-value < 0.05), suggesting that a lower market uncertainty actually leads to higher relative inflation. We show in 5.2 that when capacity cost is low, a lower market uncertainty does not induce significant changes in absolute inflation. This is consistent with the observation here

ec5 Table EC.2 Regression Results for Comparing Relative Inflation Variable Intercept C L U L C L U L ξ t Estimate 0.288-0.294 0.313 0.044-0.001 0.003 (s.e.) (0.085) (0.119) (0.119) (0.168) (0.000) (0.000) Note: 0.000 means the value is less than 0.0005. Values in parentheses are standard errors; : p-value < 0.05; : p-value < 0.01. that relative inflation is lower in treatment C L U H than in C L U L. In addition, we show in 5.2 that when capacity cost is high, a lower market uncertainty induces a significant reduction in absolute inflation. Hence, the observation here that relative inflation is lower in C H U H than in C H U L suggests that the reduction in absolute inflation due to a lower market uncertainty is not as large as the reduction in market uncertainty itself. Appendix EC.3: Additional Analytical Results EC.3.1. An FOSD Updated Belief Leads to the Optimal Capacity Increasing in ˆξ In 3 we argue that if the supplier s updated belief about ξ is increasing in ˆξ in the first-order stochastic dominance (FOSD) order, then the supplier s optimal capacity decision, which maximizes E ξ [Π s (K, ξ) ˆξ], will be increasing in ˆξ. We provide a proof of this statement as specified in the following lemma. Lemma EC.1. If the supplier s updated belief about ξ, F (ξ ), is increasing in the first-order stochastic dominance order; i.e., ˆξ 1 > ˆξ 2 implies F (y ˆξ 1 ) < F (y ˆξ 2 ) for all y, 23 then the supplier s optimal capacity K (ˆξ), which maximizes E ξ [Π s (K, ξ) ˆξ], is increasing in ˆξ. Proof. Let γ (w c c k )/(w c) and note that γ (0, 1). Following the method for solving a standard newsvendor problem, the supplier s optimal capacity is given by K (ˆξ) = µ+r 1 (γ ˆξ), where R( ˆξ) is the c.d.f. for ξ + ɛ given the updated belief F ( ˆξ). We first claim that R(z ˆξ 1 ) < R(z ˆξ 2 ) for all z if ˆξ 1 > ˆξ 2. 24 This is equivalent to saying ɛ ɛ Pr(ξ z ɛ ˆξ 1 )g(ɛ)dɛ < ɛ ɛ Pr(ξ z ɛ ˆξ 2 )g(ɛ)dɛ for all z if ˆξ 1 > ˆξ 2. But this statement is true because given ɛ, F (z ɛ ˆξ 1 ) < F (z ɛ ˆξ 2 ) for all z if ˆξ 1 > ˆξ 2 by assumption. Given the above claim, we see that R 1 (γ ˆξ 1 ) > R 1 (γ ˆξ 2 ) if ˆξ 1 > ˆξ 2. Therefore, we have K (ˆξ 1 ) > K (ˆξ 2 ) if ˆξ 1 > ˆξ 2, proving that K (ˆξ) is increasing in ˆξ. EC.3.2. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE) in the Model with Disutility of Deception For this case, the expected utilities are given as U Lm (ˆξ, K, ξ) = (r w)e ɛ min(µ + ξ + ɛ, K) βϕ(ˆξ ξ), ] U Ls (ˆξ, K) = (w c)e ξ,ɛ [min(µ + ξ + ɛ, K) ˆξ c k K, (EC.1) (EC.2) where the notation E[ ] reflects that the supplier uses Bayes Rule to update his belief about ξ given ˆξ. We have the following result. 23 To be more precise, the inequality is strict only for those y such that one of the F (y ) values is in (0, 1). 24 The strict inequality has the same interpretation as in footnote 23.

ec6 Proposition EC.1. The following two types of semi-separating PBE do not exist in the model with disutility of deception: (i) a pure-strategy PBE in which the manufacturer s reporting function is continuous, nondecreasing, and has flat parts in some subinterval(s) (but not the whole interval) of [ξ, ξ]; and (ii) a mixed-strategy PBE in which the manufacturer randomizes between a separating strategy and a pooling strategy. Proof. We will argue the nonexistence of either form of semi-separating equilibria by first assuming one exists and then deriving a contradiction. First note that in both types of equilibria, reporting ˆξ 1 < ξ is dominated by reporting ˆξ 2 = ξ. This is because reporting ˆξ 2 (compared to ˆξ 1 ) weakly increases the first term in Equation (EC.1) and strictly decreases the second term (without the minus sign). 25 Therefore, the manufacturer is strictly better off. Case i: The reporting function has flat parts. Without loss of generality, we assume that the manufacturer reports ˆξ p on the interval [ξ 1, ξ 2 ] where ξ 1 ξ and ξ 2 ξ. Since we consider a semi-separating equilibrium, at least one of the above inequalities must be strict. Also assume the manufacturer reports ˆξ s (ξ) on the separating intervals. Since the reporting function is continuous, we have ˆξ s (ξ 1 ) = ˆξ p and ˆξ s (ξ 2 ) = ˆξ p. For simplicity, we will refer to the private forecast as a manufacturer s type. When a supplier receives ˆξ p, he can only infer that the actual type is within [ξ 1, ξ 2 ]. Let ξ follow c.d.f. F ( ) truncated on [ξ 1, ξ 2 ] and let R( ) be the c.d.f. for ξ + ɛ. Then a supplier receiving ˆξ p builds capacity K p = µ + R 1 (γ). When the supplier receives ˆξ s (ξ), he can perfectly infer the type and builds capacity K s (ˆξ) = µ + ξ(ˆξ) + G 1 (γ), where ξ(ˆξ) is the private forecast inferred from ˆξ. First consider the case ξ 1 > ξ. Type ξ 1 must be indifferent between reporting ˆξ p and ˆξ s (ξ 1 ). If she reports ˆξ p, the supplier builds K p and hence the manufacturer s expected utility is Π p = (r w)e min(µ + ξ 1 + ɛ, µ + R 1 (γ)) βϕ(ˆξ p ξ 1 ). If she reports ˆξ s (ξ 1 ), the supplier infers that her type is ξ 1 and the manufacturer s expected utility is Π s = (r w)e min(µ + ξ 1 + ɛ, µ + ξ 1 + G 1 (γ)) βϕ(ˆξ s (ξ 1 ) ξ 1 ). Type ξ 1 being indifferent between pooling and separating implies that Π p = Π s. Note that since ˆξ s (ξ 1 ) = ˆξ p, the second terms in Π p and Π s are equal. We claim that R 1 (γ) > ξ 1 +G 1 (γ). Recall that R( ) is the c.d.f. for ξ + ɛ. We know ξ + ɛ ξ 1 + ɛ, hence Pr(ξ + ɛ x) Pr(ξ 1 + ɛ x); i.e., R(x) G(x ξ 1 ) (the inequality is binding only when both sides are equal to zero or one). Therefore, R 1 (γ) > ξ 1 + G 1 (γ) for γ (0, 1). Then for ɛ > G 1 (γ), the first term in Π p is strictly greater than the first term in Π s. This implies that Π p > Π s and contradicts the indifference assumption for type ξ 1. For the case ξ 2 < ξ, a similar argument can show that Π s > Π p for type ξ 2. Therefore, a semi-separating equilibrium specified in Case i does not exist. 25 The strict decrease of the second term is due to the assumptions: ϕ(0) = 0 and ϕ(x) > 0 for all x 0.

ec7 Case ii: The manufacturer randomizes between pooling and separating. As in Case i, we assume the pooling and separating strategy to be reporting ˆξ p and ˆξ s (ξ) respectively, for all ξ [ξ, ξ]. Note that ˆξ s (ξ) is an increasing function and satisfies ˆξ s (ξ) ξ because under-reporting is a dominated strategy. This implies that ˆξ s ( ξ) = ξ. First consider the case ˆξ p = ξ. Since ˆξ s (ξ) is continuous, there exists ξ 0 close to ξ such that ˆξ s (ξ 0 ) ξ 0 < ˆξ p. Then type ξ 0 will strictly prefer ˆξ s (ξ 0 ) to ˆξ p because the former strategy results in a strictly greater capacity and the difference in the disutility of deception from both strategies is negligible (due to the continuity of ϕ( )). Therefore, randomizing is not optimal for type ξ 0. Now consider the case ˆξ p < ξ. Then type ξ will strictly prefer ˆξ s ( ξ) = ξ to ˆξ p because the former strategy results in the highest capacity and zero disutility of deception. Therefore, randomizing is not optimal for type ξ. To summarize, a randomizing strategy specified in Case ii is never optimal for the manufacturer. To conclude, both types of semi-separating PBE do not exist in the model with disutility of deception.