ISSN BWPEF Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions. Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University of London.

Similar documents
On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

Zhen Sun, Milind Dawande, Ganesh Janakiraman, and Vijay Mookerjee

Strategy -1- Strategy

An Ascending Double Auction

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership

Chapter 3. Dynamic discrete games and auctions: an introduction

Notes on Auctions. Theorem 1 In a second price sealed bid auction bidding your valuation is always a weakly dominant strategy.

HW Consider the following game:

All Equilibrium Revenues in Buy Price Auctions

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

ABattleofInformedTradersandtheMarket Game Foundations for Rational Expectations Equilibrium

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

Auctions: Types and Equilibriums

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

Games of Incomplete Information ( 資訊不全賽局 ) Games of Incomplete Information

Game Theory Problem Set 4 Solutions

Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Signaling in an English Auction: Ex ante versus Interim Analysis

Making Money out of Publicly Available Information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

ECO 426 (Market Design) - Lecture 9

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky

All-Pay Contests. (Ron Siegel; Econometrica, 2009) PhDBA 279B 13 Feb Hyo (Hyoseok) Kang First-year BPP

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Internet Trading Mechanisms and Rational Expectations

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2

Countering the Winner s Curse: Optimal Auction Design in a Common Value Model

An Ascending Double Auction

Games of Incomplete Information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Graduate School of Management and Economics

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

Auction is a commonly used way of allocating indivisible

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome.

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

This is the author s final accepted version.

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Auditing in the Presence of Outside Sources of Information

Econ 8602, Fall 2017 Homework 2

Multiunit Auctions: Package Bidding October 24, Multiunit Auctions: Package Bidding

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Econ 302 Assignment 3 Solution. a 2bQ c = 0, which is the monopolist s optimal quantity; the associated price is. P (Q) = a b

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

SI 563 Homework 3 Oct 5, Determine the set of rationalizable strategies for each of the following games. a) X Y X Y Z

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization

Efficiency in auctions with crossholdings

In Class Exercises. Problem 1

Lectures on Trading with Information Competitive Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibrium (Grossman and Stiglitz AER (1980))

The Asymptotic Shapley Value for a Simple Market Game

Double Auction Markets vs. Matching & Bargaining Markets: Comparing the Rates at which They Converge to Efficiency

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

Auction. Li Zhao, SJTU. Spring, Li Zhao Auction 1 / 35

SONDERFORSCHUNGSBEREICH 504

CS 573: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture date: March 26th, 2008

CS711 Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Estimating Market Power in Differentiated Product Markets

1 Auctions. 1.1 Notation (Symmetric IPV) Independent private values setting with symmetric riskneutral buyers, no budget constraints.

PhD Qualifier Examination

Auctions in the wild: Bidding with securities. Abhay Aneja & Laura Boudreau PHDBA 279B 1/30/14

Player 2 H T T -1,1 1, -1

Up till now, we ve mostly been analyzing auctions under the following assumptions:

Today. Applications of NE and SPNE Auctions English Auction Second-Price Sealed-Bid Auction First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

Information in Financial Markets

Is Japanese Dutch Auction Unreasonable?: A Note on Dutch Auction with Mari

January 26,

BIROn - Birkbeck Institutional Research Online

Mechanism Design and Auctions

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

Yao s Minimax Principle

Auctions 1: Common auctions & Revenue equivalence & Optimal mechanisms. 1 Notable features of auctions. use. A lot of varieties.

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty

Auction Theory: Some Basics

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Expected Value of a Random Variable

PROBLEM SET 6 ANSWERS

UCLA Department of Economics Ph.D. Preliminary Exam Industrial Organization Field Exam (Spring 2010) Use SEPARATE booklets to answer each question

Game Theory Fall 2003

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

Mechanism Design and Auctions

The Optimality of Being Efficient. Lawrence Ausubel and Peter Cramton Department of Economics University of Maryland

Equilibrium payoffs in finite games

A folk theorem for one-shot Bertrand games

On the existence of coalition-proof Bertrand equilibrium

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

Transcription:

ISSN 1745-8587 Birkbeck Working Papers in Economics & Finance School of Economics, Mathematics and Statistics BWPEF 0701 Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions Arup Daripa Birkbeck, University of London January 2007 Birkbeck, University of London Malet Street London WC1E 7HX

Uninformative Equilibrium in Uniform Price Auctions Arup Daripa January 2007 Abstract I analyze the incentive for costly information collection in a multi-unit commonvalue uniform-price auction in which bidders submit demand functions. I show that so long as there are some bidders who have a very high cost of information collection, even if there are a large number of other bidders who face an arbitrarily small cost of information collection, there are equilibria in which no bidder collects information. KEYWORDS: Costly information acquisition, uniform price auction, uninformed bidders, uninformative equilibrium JEL CLASSIFICATION: D44 Department of Economics, Birkbeck College, University of London, Malet Street, Bloomsbury, London WC1E 7HX, UK. E-mail: a.daripa@bbk.ac.uk

1 INTRODUCTION I analyze the incentive for costly information collection in a multi-unit common-value uniform-price auction in which bidders submit demand functions. There are some bidders who have the option of receiving a costly signal of the unknown true value. There are also some bidders who face a prohibitively high cost of receiving a signal. Important work by Pesendorfer and Swinkels (1997) shows that in a common value setting, large uniform price auctions aggregate information fully. With n bidders each demanding at most 1 unit, and k units, if both k and (n k) become large, the auction price converges to the true value. This is true even if only a small proportion of bidders are informed. The equilibrium is also the unique among symmetric equilibria. The purpose of this note is to show that so long as there are some uninformed bidders (bidders who have a very high cost of information collection), even if there are a large number of bidders who face an arbitrarily small cost of information collection, there are equilibria in which no one collects information so long as the supply is large enough. I allow demand function bids, but the result would hold with unit demand as well, but with the additional requirement that the number of uninformed bidders rises as supply increases. The rational expectations (RE) approach provides a systematic way to investigate the informational role of prices. An unappealing feature of these models is that the traders are naive price takers. The qualifier naive implies that an RE equilibrium is manipulable in the sense that an agent can obtain any allocation in equilibrium by misrepresenting his preferences. Naive price-taking by agents in RE models gives rise to certain well known paradoxes. Grossman and Stiglitz (1980) show that if information is costly, an informationally efficient equilibrium cannot exist. There is a conflict between equilibrium prices fully revealing all relevant information, and the incentive to obtain costly information. Once the price taking assumption is removed and the price formation process is modeled (Milgrom (1981),Dubey, Geanakoplos, and Shubik (1987),Jackson (1991)), there is no necessary conflict between the incentive to acquire costly information and revelation of information through prices. The examples of uninformative equilibria here point to a different conflict that between incentive to collect costly information, and the extent to which uninformed bid- 2

ders attempt make use of the information of the informed by demanding units at high prices, reducing information rent, and therefore the incentive to collect information. 2 THE MODEL The total supply is normalized to 1. This is supplied in S parts. The normalization implies that each unit is a fraction 1/S of the total supply, and thus each unit is a smaller fraction of the total supply as supply increases. This serves to capture the idea that for as the auction size gets larger, the value of each unit gets smaller. The value of the total supply is V. Each unit is valued at V/S. The value V is a random variable with a continuous distribution function F( ) and density function f ( ) over a support [0, V]. The distribution of V is public information. Some bidders can obtain an informative signal about V at a cost c > 0. I assume the standard common values scenario. Let X i [0, 1] denote the signal potentially received by informed bidder i, i I. Let g(x i V) denote the conditional density of X i given the common value V. Conditional on V, the random variables X 1,..., X NI are independently and identically distributed. For notational convenience I define the signal of a bidder who remains uninformed as φ. Thus each bidder draws a signal from [0, 1] {φ}. A bidder with signal φ has access to only public information. There are also some bidders who face a prohibitively high cost of information and therefore never collect information, and only have access to public information. Let N I 1 be the number of potentially informed bidders, and N U 1 be the number of bidders who have a prohibitively high cost of information collection and remain uninformed. Let I and U denote the sets of potentially informed and uninformed bidders, respectively. All bidders are risk neutral. 3

2.1 BIDS AND STRATEGIES A bid is any decreasing function q(p) mapping the set of prices [0, V] to the set of quantities {0, 1,..., S}. Since there are S discrete units, a bid function is a step function: 0 for p 1 < p V, 1 for p 2 < p p 1, q(p) =.. S for 0 p p S, The following representation of a bid function is very useful. Note that the inverse of a bid function can be derived as follows: { max p {p q(p) q} if this exists, p( q) = 0 otherwise. The resulting function p( ) is the inverse demand function, and thus a bid can be written as a vector (p 1,..., p S ), such that p(q) =. p 1 p 2 p S over 1 unit, over 2 units,. over S units, where V p 1 p 2... p S 0. (2.1) Let Ω be the set of vectors (p 1,..., p S ) that satisfy (2.1). Then Ω R S + is the set of bid functions. This is compact and convex. A pure strategy of bidder i I has two components. First, he must decide whether to spend c to collect information, and then decide which bid to submit. A bid by i I is a mapping from [0, 1] {φ} to Ω. A pure strategy for i is written as (D, q i (p)(x i )), where D {Y, N}. A pure strategy for uninformed bidder j, j U is simply a bid q j (p) Ω. I analyze a simultaneous game. Each potentially informed bidder i I decides whether to obtain costly information and submits a bid. The decision about information acquisition is private and not observed by others. Simultaneously, other bidders submit bids. 4

2.2 MARKET CLEARING PRICE AND ALLOCATION RULE The market clearing price is defined as follows. Definition 1. For any K S, the market clearing price m(k) is given by the highest price at which demand exceeds or equals K units. Thus ( m(k) = sup p p q i (p)( ) + q j (p) K i I j U Finally, the quantity won by a particular bid needs to be specified. Suppose bidder h I U submits a demand function q h (p) specifying positive prices for k units, k S. Also, let k be the highest integer below k such that p k q w h (p) is specified below. k if p k > m(s), q w h (p) = k + α h (k k ) if p k = m(s), 0 otherwise, ). > p k. The winning function where 1 α h = i I k q i (m(s))( ) + q j (m(s)). j U 1 If α h (k k ) is not an integer the bidder is allocated the greatest positive integer (including 0) less than this. The remainder is allocated randomly according to proportional probabilities. 5

3 UNINFORMATIVE EQUILIBRIUM An equilibrium is uninformative if no bidder spends c to collect information. 3.1 AN EQUILIBRIUM WITH ZERO PAYOFF FOR ALL BIDDERS Consider K i 0 for all i I and K j 0 for all j U such that i I K i = K I and j U K j = S K I l, where l 1. Now consider the following profile of strategies. 1. For all i I, bidder i chooses not to collect information and submits the following bid: p 1 =... = p Ki = V, and p Ki +1 =... = p S = EV. 2. Similarly, for all j U bidder j submits the following bid: p 1 =... = p Kj = V, and p Kj +1 =... = p S = EV. The strategy of each bidder is to demand some units at price V, and demand all available units at the price EV. Given the above strategy profile, the market clears at EV and each bidder earns a zero payoff. I show below that this strategy profile is a Nash equilibrium for large enough S. Proposition 1. For any given l 1 and c > 0, there exists S such that for any S > S the strategy profile above is a Nash equilibrium. Proof: Let S be given by the following: ( ) maxi I K i + l E(V V > EV) = c. (3.1) S First, let us see if any i I has a profitable deviation to information collection. Note that even if any such bidder reduces demand to zero units, the market clearing price is unaffected and stays at EV. Therefore, the only way information can benefit a bidder is that for high enough signals he could demand an additional l units at a price slightly higher than EV and earn a positive payoff. Therefore an upper bound to the payoff of bidder i I from information collection is given by ( K i + l )E(V V > EV). It is easy S to see from equation (3.1) that for S > S the payoff from collecting information is less 6

than the cost c. Therefore not collecting information is a best response for each bidder i I. From the argument above, we know that given the strategy profile, all bidders must be uninformed. Now let us see whether the bid submitted by any bidder is a best response. Any bidder h I U, by demanding either fewer units at the price V or by reducing some of the prices (p 1,..., p Kh ) to any other price greater than or equal to EV cannot change the market clearing price. Also by changing some of the prices (p 1,..., p Kh ) to any price below EV the bidder wins fewer units, but the overall payoff remains zero. Finally, if any such bidder demands more than K h units at some prices greater than or equal to EV, either this does not affect the market clearing price (if the total demand at prices strictly above EV is still lower than S), in which case the payoff is still zero, or this leads to market clearing at some price strictly above EV in which case payoff is strictly negative. Thus the strategy of each bidder is a best response. This completes the proof. 3.2 DISCRETE PRICES: AN EQUILIBRIUM WITH POSITIVE PAYOFFS FOR ALL BIDDERS In the example above, the market clearing price cannot be any lower than EV. Otherwise, it is always possible for any bidder to benefit by raising the price by a very small amount which increases winning quantity discretely. If price changes in discrete units, another factor starts to have a bite. It is possible to win all marginal units (l units in the example above) by posting a higher price, but this also raises the price paid on all infra-marginal units won by the bidder (K h for h I U in the above example). Using this effect, it is possible to sustain a price lower than EV in equilibrium, earning each bidder a strictly positive payoff. Suppose price bids must be in units of. Let n be a positive integer such that n = V. Therefore any m with m n is a feasible price. Let p < EV be a feasible price such that EV p 2. (3.2) I assume that is not too large so that the above condition does hold for some p < EV. Let S > N I + N U. Consider K i > 0 for all i I and K j > 0 for all j U be such 7

that i I K i = K I N I and j U K j = S K I 1. The difference with the previous example is that K i and K j are now all strictly positive, and l is set to 1. Now consider the following profile of strategies. 1. For all i I, bidder i chooses not to collect information and submits the following bid: p 1 =... = p Ki = V, and p Ki +1 =... = p S = p. 2. Similarly, for all j U bidder j submits the following bid: p 1 =... = p Kj = V, and p Kj +1 =... = p S = p. The following result shows that for large enough S, the above strategy profile is a Nash equilibrium. Proposition 2. Given any c > 0, and any p satisfying (3.2), there exists S such that for any S > S the strategy profile above is a Nash equilibrium. ( ) maxi I K Proof: Let S be such that i + 1 E(V V > p) = c. The rest of the proof S is exactly like the previous proof, the only extra factor is to check whether any bidder has an incentive to raise the price on the marginal unit. The ( expected payoff ) of bidder 1 h I U under the given strategies is given by π h = K h + (EV p). N I + N U The fraction in the first expression arises from the fact that each bidder demands S units at the price p and therefore the marginal unit is allocated to any bidder with probability of 1/(N I + N U ). Next, the payoff from raising the price on the marginal unit is π h = (K h + 1) (EV p ). Equilibrium requires π h π h, which implies ( ) NI + N (EV p) U 1 (K N I + N h + 1). U But (3.2) is sufficient for this to hold. 8

REFERENCES DUBEY, P., J. GEANAKOPLOS, AND M. SHUBIK (1987): The Revelation of Information in Strategic Market Games: A Critique of Rational Expectations Equilibria, Journal of Mathematical Economics, 16, 105 37. 2 GROSSMAN, S., AND J. STIGLITZ (1980): On the Impossibility of Informationally Efficient Markets, American Economic Review, 70 (June), 393 408. 2 JACKSON, M. (1991): Equilibrium, Price Formation and the Value of Private Information, Review of Financial Studies, 4 (1), 1 16. 2 MILGROM, P. (1981): Rational Expectations, Information Acquisition and Competitive Bidding, Econometrica, 49, 921 43. 2 PESENDORFER, W., AND J. SWINKELS (1997): The Loser s Curse and Information Aggregation in Common Value Auctions, Econometrica, 65, 1247 1282. 2 9