agency problems P makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer of a contract to A that specifies a schedule of outputcontingent

Similar documents
Definition of Incomplete Contracts

Transactions with Hidden Action: Part 1. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

CONTRACT THEORY. Patrick Bolton and Mathias Dewatripont. The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 7: Moral Hazard. Patrick Legros

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

Internet Appendix to: Common Ownership, Competition, and Top Management Incentives

Moral Hazard: Dynamic Models. Preliminary Lecture Notes

Relational Incentive Contracts

A Multitask Model without Any Externalities

Moral Hazard Example. 1. The Agent s Problem. contract C = (w, w) that offers the same wage w regardless of the project s outcome.

Adverse Selection and Moral Hazard with Multidimensional Types

IS TAX SHARING OPTIMAL? AN ANALYSIS IN A PRINCIPAL-AGENT FRAMEWORK

THE MIRRLEES APPROACH TO MECHANISM DESIGN WITH RENEGOTIATION (WITH APPLICATIONS TO HOLD-UP AND RISK SHARING) By Ilya Segal and Michael D.

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

Renegotiation and Collusion in Organizations

Financial Contracting with Adverse Selection and Moral Hazard

Volume 29, Issue 3. The Effect of Project Types and Technologies on Software Developers' Efforts

ADVERSE SELECTION PAPER 8: CREDIT AND MICROFINANCE. 1. Introduction

Self Investment in Human Capital: A Quadratic Model with an. Implication for the Skills Gap

Eco2102: Topics in Micro Theory I Contract Theory

CHAPTER 1: Moral Hazard with Single Agent

Backward Integration and Risk Sharing in a Bilateral Monopoly

Limited liability, or how to prevent slavery in contract theory

Diskussionsbeiträge des Fachbereichs Wirtschaftswissenschaft der Freien Universität Berlin. The allocation of authority under limited liability

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium

Microeconomic Theory II Spring 2016 Final Exam Solutions

On the Optimal Use of Ex Ante Regulation and Ex Post Liability

A Simple Model of Bank Employee Compensation

Transaction Costs and the Robustness of the Coase Theorem

Problem Set: Contract Theory

Explicit vs. Implicit Incentives. Margaret A. Meyer Nuffield College and Department of Economics Oxford University

UNIVERSITY OF OSLO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

Alternative sources of information-based trade

Principal-Agent Models

BACKGROUND RISK IN THE PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama. and. Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Chapter 9 Dynamic Models of Investment

Does Competition Solve the Hold-up Problem?

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

CONSUMPTION AND INVESTMENT DECISION: AN ANALYSIS OF AGGREGATE AND TIME-ADDITIVE MODELS

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

Optimal Labor Contracts with Asymmetric Information and More than Two Types of Agent

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Econ 101A Final Exam We May 9, 2012.

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation

Moral Hazard. Economics Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior. Instructor: Songzi Du

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core

Equity, Vacancy, and Time to Sale in Real Estate.

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 3

University of Konstanz Department of Economics. Maria Breitwieser.

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Practice Problems. w U(w, e) = p w e 2,

Economics 502 April 3, 2008

1. Cash-in-Advance models a. Basic model under certainty b. Extended model in stochastic case. recommended)

FIGURE A1.1. Differences for First Mover Cutoffs (Round one to two) as a Function of Beliefs on Others Cutoffs. Second Mover Round 1 Cutoff.

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Lecture 14. Multinational Firms. 2. Dunning's OLI, joint inputs, firm versus plant-level scale economies

Topic 7. Nominal rigidities

Where do securities come from

Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment

TOWARD A SYNTHESIS OF MODELS OF REGULATORY POLICY DESIGN

Collective versus Relative Incentives

OWNERSHIP AND RESIDUAL RIGHTS OF CONTROL Ownership is usually considered the best way to incentivize economic agents:

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

Monetary Economics. Lecture 23a: inside and outside liquidity, part one. Chris Edmond. 2nd Semester 2014 (not examinable)

Lecture Note: Monitoring, Measurement and Risk. David H. Autor MIT , Fall 2003 November 13, 2003

THE OPTIMAL ASSET ALLOCATION PROBLEMFOR AN INVESTOR THROUGH UTILITY MAXIMIZATION

Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership

Delegation and incentives

Economics and Finance,

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Problem Set 2: Sketch of Solutions

The Margins of Global Sourcing: Theory and Evidence from U.S. Firms by Pol Antràs, Teresa C. Fort and Felix Tintelnot

Asymmetric Information: Walrasian Equilibria, and Rational Expectations Equilibria

JEFF MACKIE-MASON. x is a random variable with prior distrib known to both principal and agent, and the distribution depends on agent effort e

Financial Intermediation, Loanable Funds and The Real Sector

Insurance and Perceptions: How to Screen Optimists and Pessimists

WORKING PAPER SERIES Full versus Partial Delegation in Multi-Task Agency Barbara Schöndube-Pirchegger/Jens Robert Schöndube Working Paper No.

CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #18: Multi-Parameter Revenue-Maximization

Discussion Papers In Economics And Business

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Signaling Games. Farhad Ghassemi

Chapter 7 Moral Hazard: Hidden Actions

Economics 101A (Lecture 25) Stefano DellaVigna

The Value of Information in an Agency Model with Moral Hazard

Online Appendix: Extensions

Markets as beneficial constraints on the government

Lecture 3: Information in Sequential Screening

Transcription:

agency problems 1 We illustrate agency problems with the aid of heavily stripped-down models which can be explicitly solved. Variations on a principal agent model with both actors risk-neutral allow us to illustrate a canonical benchmark case, multi-tasking problems and informed-principal ones. We illustrate intertemporal agency problems using a two-period model with a riskaverse agent, which yields linear incentives. We conclude by briefly looking at more recent developments of the field such as present-biased preferences and motivated agents. Within modern economic analysis, early recognition of the importance of agency problems goes back to at least Marschak (1955), rrow (1963) and auly (1968). These early works are followed by the classical contributions of Mirrlees (1975), Holmström (1979), Shavell (1979) and Grossman and Hart (1983). The canonical form of the principal agent problem still in use crystallizes in Holmström (1979) and Grossman and Hart (1983). risk-neutral rincipal hires a risk-averse gent. Both actors are necessary to generate output, which depends stochastically on s actions. These are generally referred to as effort (e) and, crucially are not observable by or any third party like a Court. In jargon, effort is neither observable nor verifiable, and hence no contractual arrangements can depend on e. (nderlini and Felli, 1998, consider a principal agent problem in which e is in principle contractible, but where the equilibrium contract does not include it because of complexity considerations arising from the difficulties of describing it.) The interests of and are not aligned because e causes disutility to. makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer of a contract to that specifies a schedule of outputcontingent wages. s offer is rejected unless it meets s individual rationality constraint (henceforth IR), stating that s expected utility cannot be less than that yielded by his next-best alternative employment. In addition, the problem may or may not include an explicit limited liability constraint (henceforth LC) stating that, regardless of output, s wage cannot go below a given level. fter a contract is signed, chooses e, then the uncertain output is realized, and finally payments are made according to the contract. In the canonical model there is a trade-off between insurance and incentives. Optimal risksharing would require to insure against output uncertainty. However, doing so would leave without any incentives to exert effort: would be guaranteed a constant wage and hence would choose that e which gives minimal disutility. Typically, s choice is instead to offer a contract that does not fully insure, so as to give him incentives to exert effort. The contract

2 compensates for the risk he bears in order to satisfy the IR (and possibly the LC). If e is sufficiently productive in the stochastic technology, s expected profit increases as a result. The need to generate effort via incentives yields an agency problem. The equilibrium contract may be far from the first-best world in which a social planner can choose e at will. lower than socially efficient e is selected and is not fully insured. When both and are risk-neutral, an agency problem also arises if the LC binds (and typically the IR does not). (If the reverse is true, then giving incentives to has no cost since he does not mind risk and the IR binds on his expected payoff. In fact in this case, the social optimum coincides with the constrained social optimum in which a social planner can choose e, but only subject to giving the appropriate incentives to.) In this case in order to give incentives can pay him more when output indicates that effort is higher. This drives a wedge between s marginal cost for increased e and its social marginal cost. This in turn dictates that the equilibrium contract will differ from the first-best, and a second-best constrained-inefficient outcome obtains. Because of its tractability, the case in which both and are risk-neutral and the LC binds while the IR does not is a good benchmark to illustrate the mechanics of the problem and some of the more recent developments of the theory. simple benchmark hires to carry out a task that requires unobservable non-contractible effort e [0, 1]. s effort determines the probability that the task is successful in generating output. Output equals 1 with probability e and 0 with probability 1 e. Output is observable and contractible. First, offers a contract to, then accepts or rejects it. fter a contract is signed, chooses e. contract is a pair of reals (w 1,w 0 ), with the first being the wage (in units of output) that pays if output is 1, and the second being the wage if output is 0. Importantly, has limited liability. He cannot be paid a negative wage in any state of the world. This generates the two LCs w1 0 and w 0 0. Both and are risk-neutral, and dislikes effort which generates disutility e 2 /2. Given (w 1,w 0 ) and e, s payoff is e(1 w1) (1 e)w 0, while s is given by ew 1 + (1 e)w 0 e 2 /2. The outside options of both and payoffs must be non-negative. These are the IRs. are normalized to zero, so that in equilibrium both expected Given (w 1,w 0 ), s choice of e is immediately computed as e = w 1 w 0, this is the incentive constraint (henceforth IC) of the agent. If both w 0 and w 1 are lowered by the same amount e does not change. Hence in equilibrium w 0 = 0 and e = w 1. Taking into account IC, maximizes

e(1 e). Therefore, in equilibrium, e = w 1 = 1/2. Hence s equilibrium payoff is Π = 1/4, while s is Π = 1/8, so that the IR does not bind for either or. If a social planner were able to choose e at will, this would be chosen so as to maximize e e 2 /2, expected output minus cost of effort. So the first-best level of effort is e = 1. In this hypothetical world, Π +Π =1/2, while in equilibrium Π +Π =3/8. This gap is the result of the agency problem; is motivated by the difference w1 w 0. Because of limited liability, the only way for to motivate is to raise w1. This makes s effort too costly at the margin for : the (expected) cost of effort e is w1 e= e 2, so that the marginal cost is 2e. This exceeds the social marginal cost, which is / e [e 2 /2] = e, thus inducing an inefficient second-best outcome. 3 Multi-tasking Starting with Holmström and Milgrom (1991), the theory evolved to encompass the multi-tasking case in which has to carry out multiple tasks that affect output. (See also Holmström and Milgrom, 1994.) Some of the insights can be conveyed adapting the simple benchmark model above. now has two tasks; one is standard (S) and one is noisy (N). He chooses two effort levels: 2 2 S N e S and e N, both in [0, 1]. Choosing (e S,e N ) costs a disutility of ( e + e )/4. The two tasks are perfect complements in the stochastic technology. Given (es,e N ), output equals 1 with probability min {e S,e N }, and 0 with probability 1 min{e S,e N }. s in the benchmark, s payoff is expected output minus expected wage, while s payoff equals his expected wage minus the disutility of effort. The LC and IR are as before. Task N is noisier than task S in the following sense. Output is not contractible. Instead, each task yields a binary signal that can be contracted on. The signal σ S for the S task is equal to 1 with probability e S, and 0 with probability 1 e S. The signal σ N for the N task is equal to 1 with probability [e N p + (1 e N )(1 p)] and equal to 0 with the complementary probability, with p [1/2, 1]. So, if p = 1/2 then σ N contains no information about e S, while if p = 1, the signals σ S and σ N are equally informative about the respective tasks. Because of the signal structure, a contract is now a quadruple of wages (w S1,w S0,w N1,w N0 ), one for each task, and for each possible value of the corresponding signal. s in the benchmark, in equilibrium we must have w S0 = w N0 = 0. Given (w S1,w S0,w N1,w N0 ), the ICs pin down e S and e N as satisfying e S = 2w S1 and e N = 2w N1 (2p 1). Maximizing s profit using these restrictions gives that in equilibrium es = e N = max{0, 1/2 (1 p)/(8p 4)}. When p = 1 this model yields the same first best and the equilibrium payoffs as the benchmark above. When p = 3/5 or less then

e S = e N = 0. The literature highlights some features of the equilibrium for values of p [1/2, 1). s p decreases, so that task N becomes more noisy, two changes occur. In equilibrium, e N decreases. 4 This is not very surprising, given the increased noise. What is less straightforward is that e S decreases as well: increased noise yields softer incentives on the standard task, as well as the noisy one. The complementarity between the tasks (extreme in the version used here, but this is not necessary) dictates that, as e N becomes more expensive for because of the noise, he will choose to induce lower values of es as well. nother way to check this is that the equilibrium values of both w S and w N decrease as p goes down. When p 3/5, σ N is not informative enough. In this case e S = e N = w S1 = w N1 = 0. This has been interpreted as no contract being signed. The no-contract outcome obtains even though an informative contractible signal for both tasks is available. Informed principal Myerson (1983) and Maskin and Tirole (1990; 1992) examine the case in which has private information, creating a potential signalling role for the contract offer. Despite the intricacies involved, the simple benchmark model above can be adapted again to illustrate some of the key points. (The computations below all pertain to the case of common values analysed in Maskin and Tirole, 1992.) There are two types of principal, H and L. is of type H with probability φ = 18/29 and of type L with probability 1 φ = 11/29. The principal s type is his private information. If type H, s outside option is k = 9/32, while if is of type L then s outside option is 0, as in the benchmark above. Hence, if H and L is of separate in equilibrium, there are two IRs for, while if pooling obtains s expected outside option is φ k = 81/464, and he faces a single IR. s LCs are as in the benchmark above. First learns his type. Then he offers a contract to, which may take the form of a menu (wages contingent on output and s type). t this point updates his beliefs about s type and then decides whether to accept or reject. (s in any signalling game, the issue of off-theequilibrium-path beliefs arises. The simplest way to deal with this issue is to assume that s beliefs after observing an unexpected offer are that is of type H with probability 1. This is implicitly assumed in all computations below.) fter a contract is signed tells which part of the menu applies in his case (if the contract is in fact a menu). Finally, chooses effort, output is realized and payoffs are obtained.

5 There is a single task requiring effort which stochastically produces output as in the benchmark model. Output is contractible. s payoffs and IR are also as above. s payoff is also as in the benchmark above, except that he takes expectations using his beliefs. In a separating equilibrium H and L offer two distinct pairs of output-contingent wages: (w H1,w H0 ) and (w L1,w L0 ) respectively. s ICs dictate that after being offered (wh1,w H0 ) effort is e H = w H1 w H0, while after being offered (w L1,w L0 ) effort is e L = w L1 w L0. Since Separation requires that neither H nor L has an incentive to offer the other type s wage pair. s private information does not enter directly his payoff, this can be true only if the expected profits for the two types of principals, ΠH and Π L, are the same. This is the truth telling (henceforth TC) constraint, which, using IC, since w H0 can be shown to be 0, reads Π H = e H (1 e H ) = e L (1 e L ) w L0 = Π L. Since k = 9/32, one of the two IRs for the agent does bind. Using IC this yields e H = w H1 = 3/4. Using TC, this implies e L = 1/2, w L0 = 1/16 and w L1 = 9/16. With these values Π H = Π L = 3/16. With informed principals, the literature highlights the possibility of pooling equilibria, in which M M M M the contract is a menu. Both H and L offer a menu ( wh1, wh0, wl1, w L0), which has to accept or reject based on his expected IR. fter a contract is signed, tells which pair of outputcontingent wages applies. The TC constraint still applies, since both H and L have to be willing to indicate to the appropriate wage pair. In fact, using IC and w 0 = 0, IC still reads M H M M (1 M ) M (1 M ) M M H eh eh el el wl0 Π = = =Π L. Using the single binding expected IR and the ICs, which are unchanged, yields M 2 M 2 M H L L (18/58)( e ) + (11/ 29)[( e ) + w ] = 81/ 464. Using the TC constraint this gives eh = w H1 = 5/8, e L = 1/2, w L0 = 1/64 and w L1 = 33/64. With these values Π H = Π L = 15/64. Thus both types of relaxes s IR which binds in expectation. separation case. The increased profit for enjoy strictly higher profits than under separation. ooling H H can lower wh1 which increases affects M Π H relative to the L via the TC constraint. L lowers both output-contingent wages to satisfy the TC constraint, which in turn increases with M Π H. M Π L to keep it in line Intertemporal incentives Holmström and Milgrom (1987) analyse the case of a relationship between and that extends over time. Some of the main insights can be gained in the following simple set-up. There are two time periods the first denoted F and the second denoted S. chooses an effort in [0, 1] in both periods. Output can be either 1 or 0, and output draws are independent across the

6 two periods. The first period effort is denoted e F. The second period effort if output is 1 in the first period is e 1S, while the second period effort if output in the first period is 0 is e 0S. The probability that output is 1 is e F in the first period, and e is (with i {0, 1}) in the second period. is paid at the end of the two periods, as a function of observed output in the two periods. The wage paid if output is i {0, 1} in period F and j {0, 1} in period S is denoted w ij. Neither nor discounts the future. While is risk-neutral, is risk-averse with an exponential utility with a constant absolute risk-aversion coefficient equal to 1/2. His effort in the two periods is perfectly substitutable. Given a wage scheme wij and effort levels e F and e is his expected utility is while 1 1 Π = ef e1s exp ( w11 ef e1s) + (1 e1s )exp ( w10 ef e1s) 2 2 1 1 (1 ef ) e0s exp ( w01 ef e0s) + (1 e0s ) exp ( w00 ef e0s) 2 2 s expected payoff is Π = ef e1s (2 w11) + (1 e1s )(1 w10) + (1 ef ) e0s (1 w01) + (1 e0s)( w00) The optimal incentive scheme is found by maximizing Π subject to IR constraints imposing that Π 1 and Π 0 and an assumption that (these levels of reservation payoff can be taken to be a normalization for can earn a certain payoff of 0 elsewhere, yielding a utility level of 1), and subject to the IC constraints which now impose that e F, e 0S and e 1S should jointly maximize Π given the incentive scheme w ij. The IR constraint is binding for while it is not binding for. The IC constraint can be subsumed in the first order conditions obtained by differentiating Π with respect to e F and e is and setting these equal to 0 which are sufficient for a maximum. This way to proceed is known in the literature as taking the first-order approach. In the more general case considered for instance by Holmström and Milgrom (1987) this is not viable. In the simple case considered here, the firstorder approach works because we are assuming that the exponent of effort variables 1/2 in this case plus s constant absolute risk-aversion coefficient also 1/2 in this case sum to 1. Even in single-period agency models, whether the first-order approach is valid or not is an intricate question first uncovered by Mirrlees (1975). Subsequent contributions on this topic can be found in Grossman and Hart (1983), Rogerson (1985) and Jewitt (1988). To characterize the optimal incentive scheme for the two-period problem it is useful to first consider the second period (S) subproblem after output i {0, 1} has been realized in the first period (F). These problems are

obtained considering (continuation) payoffs for and given by the relevant square bracket 7 term of and above, and with an IR constraint for given by his utility level (contingent Π on output in F) in the solution to the two-period problem, after factoring out the common term exp{ef/2}. Π If we use these binding IR constraints and the first-order IC constraints it can be seen that the difference (w i1 w i0 ) > 0 is independent of i the second-period incentive premium Δ S = (w i1 w i0 ) does not depend on first-period output. Hence, if we use the first-order IC constraints it is also the case that e 0S = e 1S = e S (0, 1). s IR constraints in each period S sub-problem determines wi0. The period S sub-problems can then be plugged into the two-period problem. Viewed from period F we can think of as offering two certainty equivalent wages ci for each period F output. Notice that we can write ci = w i πi where w i is the expected period S wage when the realized period F output is i and πi is the associated risk-premium. Since (w i1 w i0 ) = Δ S is independent of i, and s utility exhibits constant absolute risk-aversion we then get π 0 = π 1 = π. Hence factoring out the common term exp{π/2} from utility, the period F problem can be seen as having the same form as the two period S sub-problems with a different IR constraint for. Hence, as before, the difference Δ F = ( w 1 w 0 ) does not depend on s reservation utility and in fact ΔF = Δ S = Δ. For the same reason e F = e S = e. Using Δ F = Δ S = Δ and e F = e S = e we then get that the optimal incentive scheme is linear in output in the sense that w 01 = w 10 = w 00 + Δ and w 11 = w 00 + 2Δ. Given w 00, the wage increases by a fixed amount Δ for each unit of realized output over the two periods. In the simple model we have used here output is either 1 or 0. The linearity result holds in the same model (with an arbitrary finite number of periods) when there are N possible output realizations each period. In this case the incentive scheme is linear in accounts in essence linear in a vector of variables that count the number of realizations of each possible output level. Hellwig and Schmidt (2002) clarify that linearity in accounts need not imply linearity in aggregate output, and in fact some additional assumptions are needed for the latter to hold. They show that if can destroy output unnoticed, and only observes aggregate output at the end of the last period, then the (approximately) optimal incentive scheme is indeed linear in aggregate output. Both Holmström and Milgrom (1987) and Hellwig and Schmidt (2002) are principally concerned with a continuous-time model in which controls the drift of a (multi-dimensional) Brownian motion process that represents output. The continuous-time version of the problem yields

8 elegant closed-form solutions that confirm the linearity result. Hellwig and Schmidt (2002) analyse in detail the status of the continuous-time model as the limit of discrete-time models. The linearity of incentive schemes is of great interest in applications because of the prominence in practice of linear (or approximately linear) incentive schemes. In all known theoretical settings, linear optimal incentive schemes rely on exponential utility functions for both and, whenever the latter is not risk-neutral. Stochastically independent periods also play a crucial role. Finally, the tight linear characterizations of intertemporal incentive schemes also rely on s ability to commit in advance to an incentive scheme, and on s ability to commit not to quit before the end. The question of whether a full-commitment long-term contract can be implemented via a sequence of short-term contracts has been analysed in a general context by Malcomson and Spinnewyn (1988), Fudenberg, Holmström and Milgrom (1990) and Rey and Salanié (1990). common thread of this literature is that s ability to monitor s savings decisions plays a key role in the possibility of short-term implementation of long-term contracts. Recent developments Since its inception the literature on agency problems and applications has grown dramatically, influencing many areas of economics ranging from development to finance. gency theory has found a prominent place in many graduate and undergraduate programs in economics. Recent texts that provide a comprehensive treatment of the field include Salanié (2000), Laffont and Martimort (2002) and Bolton and Dewatripont (2005). Recent developments in the actual analytical framework relax some of the basic assumptions of the canonical model. Eliaz and Spiegler (2006) and O Donoghue and Rabin (2005) focus on the underlying behavioural assumptions. The first paper tackles an environment in which agents may differ in their cognitive abilities, which generates dynamically inconsistent behaviour. The second paper is concerned with the effect of present bias in the agent s preferences on the optimal incentive scheme. In both cases the optimal incentive scheme becomes more realistically sensitive to detail than in the standard case. Besley and Ghatak (2005) focus on the case of motivated agents in the provision of a public good. Motivated agents do not always regard effort as a cost. This has important effects on incentive design, which in turn sheds light on the nature of non-profit organizations. Luca nderlini and Leonardo Felli

See also contract theory; incentive compatibility; incomplete contracts; information economics; mechanism design; moral hazard 9 Bibliography nderlini, L. and Felli, L. 1998. Describability and agency problems. European Economic Review 42, 35 59. rrow, K. 1963. Uncertainty and the welfare economics of medical care. merican Economic Review 53, 941 73. Besley, T. and Ghatak, M. 2005. Competition and incentives with motivated agents. merican Economic Review 95, 616 36. Bolton,. and M. Dewatripont. 2005. Contract Theory. Cambridge, M: MIT ress. Eliaz, K. and R. Spiegler. 2006. Contracting with diversely naive agents. Review of Economic Studies 73, 689 714. Fudenberg, D., Holmstrom, B. and Milgrom,. 1990. Short-term contracts and long-term agency relationships. Journal of Economic Theory 51, 1 31. Grossman, S. and Hart, O. 1983. n analysis of the principal agent problem. Econometrica 51, 7 45. Hellwig, M. and Schmidt, K. 2002. Discrete-time approximations of the Holmström Milgrom Brownian-motion model of intertemporal incentive provision. Econometrica 70, 2225 64. Holmström, B. 1979. Moral hazard and observability. Bell Journal of Economics 10, 74 91. Holmström, B. and Milgrom,. 1987. ggregation and linearity in provision of intertemporal incentives. Econometrica, 55, 303 328. Holmström, B. and Milgrom,. 1991. Multitask principal agent analyses: incentive contracts, asset ownership, and job design. Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 7, 24 52. Holmström, B. and Milgrom,. 1994. The firm as an incentive system. merican Economic Review 84, 972 91. Jewitt, I. 1988. Justifying the first-order approach to principal agent problems. Econometrica 56, 1177 1190. Laffont, J.-J. and Martimort, D. 2002. The Theory of Incentives. rinceton: rinceton University ress. Malcomson, J. and Spinnewyn, F. 1988. The multiperiod principal agent problem. Review of Economic Studies 55, 391 407. Marschak, J. 1955. Elements for a theory of teams. Management Science 1, 127 37.

10 Maskin, E. and Tirole, J. 1990. The principal agent relationship with an informed principal: the case of private values. Econometrica 58, 379 409. Maskin, E. and Tirole, J. 1992. The principal-agent relationship with an informed principal II: common values. Econometrica 60, 1 42. Mirrlees, J. 1975. The theory of moral hazard and unobservable behavior: part I. Mimeo, Nuffield College, Oxford University. ublished in Review of Economic Studies 66 (1999), 3 21. Myerson, R. 1983. Mechanism design by an informed principal. Econometrica 51, 1767 98. O Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. 2005. Incentives and self control. Mimeo, University of California, Berkeley. auly, M. 1968. The economics of moral hazard. merican Economic Review 58, 531 37. Rey,. and Salanié, B. 1990. Long-term, short-term and renegotiation: on the value of commitment in contracting. Econometrica 58, 597 619. Rogerson, W. 1985. The first-order approach to principal agent problems. Econometrica 53, 1357 67. Salanié, B. 2000. The Economics of Contracts. Cambridge, M: MIT ress. Shavell, S. 1979. On moral hazard and insurance. Quarterly Journal of Economics 93, 541 62. Index terms agency problems commitment common values continuous-time models contract theory discrete-time models first-order approach incentive design insurance incentives trade-off intertemporal incentives limited liability linear incentive schemes menu contracts noisy tasks non-profit organizations pooling equilibria

principal and agent separating equilibria signalling soft incentives 11