CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Similar documents
CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Games of Incomplete Information ( 資訊不全賽局 ) Games of Incomplete Information

Oligopoly Games and Voting Games. Cournot s Model of Quantity Competition:

Strategy -1- Strategy

University of Hong Kong

Today. Applications of NE and SPNE Auctions English Auction Second-Price Sealed-Bid Auction First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction

In Class Exercises. Problem 1

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

Notes on Auctions. Theorem 1 In a second price sealed bid auction bidding your valuation is always a weakly dominant strategy.

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

HW Consider the following game:

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

Economics 101A (Lecture 21) Stefano DellaVigna

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

1 Solutions to Homework 3

Noncooperative Market Games in Normal Form

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

Challenge to Hotelling s Principle of Minimum

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

Markets with Intermediaries

Markets with Intermediaries

Economics 101A (Lecture 21) Stefano DellaVigna

Game Theory Lecture #16

Chapter 11: Dynamic Games and First and Second Movers

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Review, oligopoly, auctions, and signaling. Block 3 Jul 1, 2018

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Graduate School of Management and Economics

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Simon Fraser University Spring 2014

Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming

Advanced Microeconomic Theory EC104

1 Solutions to Homework 4

ECON106P: Pricing and Strategy

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

ECO 426 (Market Design) - Lecture 9

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions.

EC 202. Lecture notes 14 Oligopoly I. George Symeonidis

Game Theory Problem Set 4 Solutions

Lecture Notes on Anticommons T. Bergstrom, April 2010 These notes illustrate the problem of the anticommons for one particular example.

When we did independent private values and revenue equivalence, one of the auction types we mentioned was an all-pay auction

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

Auctions. Agenda. Definition. Syllabus: Mansfield, chapter 15 Jehle, chapter 9

Economic Management Strategy: Hwrk 1. 1 Simultaneous-Move Game Theory Questions.

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July time : 1 hour. Do all 4 questions. All count equally.

Thursday, March 3

LECTURE NOTES ON GAME THEORY. Player 2 Cooperate Defect Cooperate (10,10) (-1,11) Defect (11,-1) (0,0)

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Auctions. Episode 8. Baochun Li Professor Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering University of Toronto

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Auctions: Types and Equilibriums

Problem Set 2 Answers

Economics Honors Exam 2009 Solutions: Microeconomics, Questions 1-2

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Strategy -1- Strategic equilibrium in auctions

Spring 2017 Final Exam

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 11

Player 2 L R M H a,a 7,1 5,0 T 0,5 5,3 6,6

Microeconomics I. Undergraduate Programs in Business Administration and Economics

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Recap First-Price Revenue Equivalence Optimal Auctions. Auction Theory II. Lecture 19. Auction Theory II Lecture 19, Slide 1

PRISONER S DILEMMA. Example from P-R p. 455; also 476-7, Price-setting (Bertrand) duopoly Demand functions

Subjects: What is an auction? Auction formats. True values & known values. Relationships between auction formats

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

13.1 Infinitely Repeated Cournot Oligopoly

Games with Private Information 資訊不透明賽局

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Econ 101A Final exam Th 15 December. Do not turn the page until instructed to.

CS711 Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

1 Intro to game theory

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India February 2008

Ten Little Treasures of Game Theory and Ten Intuitive Contradictions: Instructions and Data

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

Auction Theory: Some Basics

Social Network Analysis

Follow the Leader I has three pure strategy Nash equilibria of which only one is reasonable.

Notes for Section: Week 4

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Solution Problem Set 2

Auction is a commonly used way of allocating indivisible

Game Theory Notes: Examples of Games with Dominant Strategy Equilibrium or Nash Equilibrium

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Game Theory and Auctions

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall 2012

These notes essentially correspond to chapter 13 of the text.

Transcription:

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO March 22, 2015

Homework #1 Homework #1 will be due at the end of class today. Please check the website later today for the solutions to HW1 and HW2, which is due on 4/5.

Review of Last Lecture Last week, we looked at a classic application of game theory in economics: the behavior of oligopolies. In Cournot oligopoly, firms choose their quantity of output. Nash equilibrium outcome: firms split the market. Output and profits are in between the case of monopoly and perfect competition. In Bertrand oligopoly, firms choose their price. Consumers only buy from the lowest price seller. Nash equilibrium outcome: firms set P = MC, make zero profit. Same as perfect competition.

Hotelling s Model of Electoral Competition This is a widely used model in political science and industrial organization, Hotelling s linear city model. Players choose a location on a line; payoffs are determined by how much of the line is closer to them than other players. Here, location represents a position on a one-dimensional political spectrum, but it can also represent physical space or product space.

Location on Political Spectrum v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 v 5 x min m Political position is measured by position on an interval of numbers x min is the most left-wing position, x max is the most right-wing position Voters are located at fixed positions somewhere on the line. This position represents their favorite position. In this example, there are five voters with favorite positions at v 1...v 5. The median position m is the position such that half of voters are to the left or equal to m, and the other half are to the right or equal to m. Voters dislike positions that are farther away from them on the line. They are indifferent between positions to their left and right that have the same distance. x max

Attracting Voters Based on Position Candidates can choose their position. Assume that voters vote for a candidate based only on distance to the voter s position. They always vote for the closest candidate. If there is a tie (two candidates with the same distance), the candidates will split the vote. Therefore, each candidate will attract all voters who are closer to him than any other candidate.

Attracting Voters Based on Position Suppose there are three candidates who choose positions at x 1, x 2, x 3. All voters to the left of x 1 will vote for x 1. Likewise, all voters to the right of x 3 will vote for x 3. Between candidates x 1 and x 2, each candidate will attract voters up to the midpoint (x 1 + x 2 )/2. The candidate that attracts the most votes wins. Ties are possible. Candidates most preferred outcome is to win. A tie is less preferable; the more the tie is split, the less preferred. Losing is the least preferable outcome.

Candidates Payoff Function Payoffs can be represented by this function: n if candidate wins u i (x 1,...x n ) = k if candidate ties with n k other candidates 0 if candidate loses Definition of Hotelling s Game of Electoral Competition: Players: the candidates Actions: each candidate can choose a position (a number) on the line Preferences: Each candidate s payoff is given by the function above.

Let s Play the 2-Person Game Assume voters (or consumers) are uniformly distributed along a line that begins at 0 and ends at 100. I will choose 2 players. Each player will write down a number from 0 to 100. This is their position on the line. Calculate the portion of the line that is closer to each player. The player with the larger portion wins (if portions are equal, there is a tie).

Two Candidates Suppose there are two candidates that choose positions x 1, x 2. The median position (half of voters are on the left, half on the right) is m. Let s examine the best response function of player 1 to x 2. Case 1: x 2 < m Player 1 wins if x1 > x 2 and (x 1 + x 2 )/2 < m. Every position between x j and 2m x j is a best response. Case 2: x 2 > m By the same reasoning, every position between 2m xj and x j is a best response. Case 3: x 2 = m Choosing m results in a tie; any other choice results in a loss. Therefore, x 1 = m is the best response.

Best Response Function Best response function is: {x 1 x 2 < x1 < 2m x2} if x 2 < m B 1 (x 2 ) = {m} if x 2 = m {x 1 2m x 2 < x1 < x2} if x 2 > m Unique Nash equilibrium is when both candidates choose m.

Direct Argument for Nash Equilibrium At (m, m), any deviation results in a loss. At any other position: If one candidate loses, he can get a better payoff by switching to m. If there is a tie, either candidate can get a better payoff by switching to m.

Implications of Equilibrium Conclusion: competition between candidates drives them to take similar positions at the median favorite position of voters In physical or product space: competing firms are driven to locate at the same position, or offer similar products This is known as Hotelling s Law or principle of minimum differentiation Requires the one-dimensional assumption on voter/consumer preferences. If there is more than one dimension (e.g. consumers care about both price and quality), this result may not hold

War of Attrition This game was originally developed as a model of animal conflict. Two animals are fighting over prey. Each animal gets a payoff from getting the prey, but fighting is costly. Each animal chooses a time at which it will give up fighting; the first one to give up loses the prey. This can be applied to any kind of dispute between parties, where there is some cost to waiting.

Setup of the Game Two players are disputing an object. The player that concedes first loses the object to the other player. Time is a continuous variable that begins at 0, goes on indefinitely. Assume that player i places value v i on the object (may be different from other player s value). If player i wins the dispute, he gains v i in payoff. Time is costly. For each unit of time that passes before one side concedes, both players lose 1 in payoff.

Payoffs Suppose that player i concedes first at time t i. Player i s payoff: t i Player j s payoff: v j t i If both players concede at the same time, they split the object. Player i s payoff: vi /2 t i Player j s payoff: vj /2 t i

Let s play War of Attrition I will choose 2 players, with valuations of 5 and 10. Each player will write down a number t i 0. Reveal them simultaneously. Suppose that t i < t j. Player i s payoff: ti Player j s payoff: vj t i If t i = t j, they split the object. Player i s payoff: vi /2 t i Player j s payoff: v j /2 t i

Definition of the Game Players: two parties in a dispute. Actions: each player s set of actions is the set of concession times (a non-negative number). Preferences: Payoffs are given by the following function: t i u i (t 1, t 2 ) = v i /2 t i v i t j if t i < t j if t i = t j if t i > t j

Best Response Function Intuitively, if the other player is going to give up quickly, you should wait a longer time. But if the other player is determined to wait a long time, you should concede as soon as possible. Suppose player j chooses t j. Case 1: t j < v i Any time after tj is a best response to t j. Payoff: v i t j

Best Response Function Case 1: t j < v i Any time after t j is a best response to t j. Payoff: v i t j Case 2: t j = v i Any time after or equal to v i is a best response. Payoff: 0 Case 3: t j > v i ti = 0 is the best response. Payoff: 0

Nash Equilibrium (t 1, t 2 ) is a Nash equilibrium if and only if: t 1 = 0, t 2 v 1 or t 2 = 0, t 1 v 2

Implications of Equilibrium Players don t actually fight in equilibrium. Either player can concede first, even if he has the higher valuation. Equilibria are asymmetric: each player chooses a different action, even if they have the same value This can only be a stable social norm if players come from different populations (e.g. owners always concede, challengers always wait)

Let s Hold an Auction I will auction off 50 yuan. If you want to submit a bid, write down your ID number and bid (a number 0) on the piece of paper. I will pay the difference between 50 and the highest bid. (If it is negative, then the winner should pay me.) If there is a tie, the difference will be evenly divided among everyone with the highest bid. What do you predict the outcome will be?

Let s Hold an Auction This type of auction is called a first-price, sealed-bid auction. first-price, because the winner (the highest bidder) pays his bid sealed-bid, because bids are made secretly, then revealed simultaneously Also a type of common-value auction, since the value of the prize is the same to all players What are the Nash equilibria of this auction?

Let s Hold an Auction What are the Nash equilibria of this auction? Assume two players who bid x 1, x 2. The value of the prize is V. Let s find Player 1 s best response to x 2. Suppose x 2 < V. No matter what x1 is, Player 1 can always improve his payoff by choosing a number closer to, and greater than, x 2. No best response exists. Suppose x 2 > V. Any number less than x2 gives the same payoff of 0. This is the set of best responses. Suppose x 2 = V. Any number V gives the same payoff of 0. This is the set of best responses. x 1 = V, x 2 = V is the only Nash equilibrium.

Let s Hold an Auction Outcome is similar to Bertrand duopoly. Two players are enough to compete profits away to zero.

Auctions A good is sold to the party who submits the highest bid. A common form of auction: Potential buyers sequentially submit bids. Each bid must be higher than the previous one. When no one wants to submit a higher bid, the current highest bidder wins. The actual winning bid has to only be slightly higher than the second-highest bid. We can model this as a second-price auction: the winner is the highest bidder, but only has to pay the second-highest price.

Second-price, sealed-bid auction Assume that each person knows his valuation of the object before the auction begins, so that valuation cannot be changed by seeing how others behave. Therefore, there is no difference if all bids are made secretly, then simultaneously revealed: a closed-bid auction. Each player submits the maximum amount he is willing to pay. The highest bidder wins, and pays the second-highest price.

Setup of the Game There are n bidders. Bidder i has valuation v i for the object. Assume that we label the bidders in decreasing order: v 1 > v 2 >... > v n Each player submits a sealed bid b i. If player i s bid is the highest, he wins and has to pay the second-highest bid b j. Payoff: v i b j Otherwise, does not win. Payoff: 0 To break ties, assume player with the highest valuation wins.

Let s Hold a Second-Price Auction I will choose 2 players. Each player will draw a card, which is either 5 or 8. This will be your valuation of the prize. We will reveal everyone s valuation. The players will write down their bids (a number 0) on a piece of paper. The highest bidder wins the prize, and pays the second-highest price. We will calculate everyone s payoff.

Nash Equilibrium with 2 Players Suppose there are 2 players with valuations v 1, v 2. Assume v 1 > v 2. Each player bids b i. If b1 > b 2, Player 1 s payoff is v 1 b 2, Player 2 s payoff is 0. If b2 > b 1, Player 1 s 0, Player 2 s payoff is v 2 b 1. If b1 = b 2, Player 1 s payoff is v 1 b 1, Player 2 s payoff is 0.

Best Response Function with 2 Players Let s find Player 1 s best response function. If b2 < v 1, Player 1 can get a positive payoff by bidding b 1 b 2. Best response is b 1 b 2. If b 2 = v 1, Player 1 will get a zero payoff with any bid. Best response is b 1 0. If b2 > v 1, Player 1 can get a zero payoff by bidding b 1 < b 2, or a negative payoff if b 1 b 2. Best response is b 1 < b 2. Player 2: If b1 < v 2, Player 2 can get a positive payoff by bidding b 2 > b 1. Best response is b 2 > b 1. If b 1 = v 2, Player 2 will get a zero payoff with any bid. Best response is b 2 0. If b1 > v 2, Player 2 can get a zero payoff by bidding b 2 b 1, or a negative payoff if b 2 > b 1. Best response is b 2 b 1.

Nash Equilibrium With More Than 2 Players If there are more than 2 players, best response function becomes very complicated. There are many Nash equilibria in this game. Let s examine some special cases.

All Players Bid their Valuation (b 1...b n ) = (v 1...v n ), i.e. every player s bid is equal to his valuation. Player 1, who has the highest valuation, wins the object and pays v 2. Player 1 s payoff: v 1 v 2 > 0, all other players: 0 Does anyone have an incentive to deviate? Player 1: If Player 1 changes bid to b2, outcome does not change If Player 1 changes bid to < b2, does not win, gets lower payoff of 0 Players 2... n: If Player i lowers bid, still loses. If Player i raises bid to above b1 = v 1, wins, but gets negative payoff v i v 1 < 0

Player 1 Bids Valuation, All Others Bid 0 (b 1...b n ) = (v 1, 0...0), i.e. all players except player 1 bids 0 Player 1 wins, pays 0. Payoff: v 1 Does anyone have an incentive to deviate? Player 1: Any change in bid results in same outcome (because of tie-breaking rules) Players 2... n: If Player i raises bid to v1, still loses If Player i raises bid to > v1, wins, but gets negative payoff v i v 1 This outcome is better off for player 1, but worse off for the seller of the object

An Equilibrium where Player 1 Doesn t Win (b 1...b n ) = (v 2, v 1, 0,...0). Player 2 wins the auction and pays price v 2. All players get a payoff of 0. Player 1: If he raises bid to x < v 1, still loses. If he raises bid to x v 1 he wins, gets payoff of 0 Player 2: If he raises bid or lowers to x > v2, outcome unchanged If he lowers bid to x v2, loses auction, gets payoff of 0 Players 3... n: If he raises bid to x v 1, still loses If he raises bid to > v 1, wins, but gets negative payoff v i v 1

An Equilibrium where Player 1 Doesn t Win (b 1...b n ) = (v 2, v 1, 0,...0). Player 2 wins the auction and pays price v 2. All players get a payoff of 0. Player 2 s bid in this equilibrium exceeds his valuation. This seems risky - what if player 1 decided to bid higher than v 2? In a dynamic setting, player 2 s bid is not credible. Later on, we ll study ways of showing that these kinds of outcomes are implausible.

Equilibria with Weakly Dominant Actions For each player i, the action v i weakly dominates all other actions Player i can do no better than bidding v i, no matter what other players bid If the highest bid of other players is v i, then: If player i bids v i, payoff is 0 (either win and pay v i, or don t win) If player i bids bi v i, payoff is zero or negative If the highest bid of the other players is b < v i, then: If player i bids vi, wins and gets payoff v i b If player i bids b i v i, either wins and gets same payoff, or loses and gets payoff of 0 Second-price auction has many Nash equilibria, but the only equilibrium where each player plays a weakly dominant action is (b 1...b n ) = (v 1...v n ).

First-price, sealed bid auction with n players We saw that in the first-price sealed bid auction with 2 players who had the same valuation, the only NE was (b 1, b 2 ) = (v 1, v 2 ). Now, let s allow n players, and valuations can differ among players. Assume that if there is a tie, the winner is the player with the highest valuation. First, let s check the obvious case, where everyone bids their valuations: (b 1...b n ) = (v 1...v n ) The winner, Player 1, has an incentive to deviate: he can increase his payoff by lowering his bid from v 1 to v 2. Note that this results in the same payoffs as the second-price auction.

NE of first-price auction There are many NE, but in all of them, the winner is Player 1 (the player with the highest valuation of the object). Suppose the action profile is (b 1,..., b n ) and Player 1 does not win. b i > b 1 for some i 1. If b i > v 2, then Player i s payoff is negative, so he has an incentive to deviate by bidding 0. If b i v 2, then Player 1 can increase his payoff from 0 to v 1 = b i by bidding b i. Therefore, no such action profile is a NE.

Review of Random Variables A random variable is a variable that can take on different values, according to some probability distribution. A finite, discrete random variable is random variable that can take on a finite number of values. For example, suppose that y is a random variable that can take on two values: y = 1 occurs with probability p, y = 0 occurs with probability 1 p. y can represent the outcome of flipping a biased coin that shows 1 on one side and 0 on the other side. If we flip this coin a very large number of times, the frequency (i.e. the fraction of flips) of showing 1 will be p.

Expected Values The expected value of a random variable is the weighted sum of all possible outcomes, weighted by the probability of occurrence. For the biased coin example, the expected value is: E(y) = Pr(y = 1) 1 + Pr(y = 0) 0 = p 1 + (1 p) 0 In general, the expected value (EV) of a discrete random variable that can take on n outcomes y 1,...y n with probabilities p 1,...p n is = p E(y) = p 1 y 1 + p 2 y 2 +... + p n y n The sum of probabilities over all outcomes must add up to 1.

Next Lecture & Homework Homework #1 will be due at the end of class today. Please check the website later today for the solutions to HW1 and HW2, which is due on 4/5. For next week, please read Chapter 4.