How do we cope with uncertainty?

Similar documents
UNCERTAINTY AND INFORMATION

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

Insurance, Adverse Selection and Moral Hazard

Eco 300 Intermediate Micro

Chapter 9 THE ECONOMICS OF INFORMATION. Copyright 2005 by South-Western, a division of Thomson Learning. All rights reserved.

Price Theory Lecture 9: Choice Under Uncertainty

Pindyck and Rubinfeld, Chapter 17 Sections 17.1 and 17.2 Asymmetric information can cause a competitive equilibrium allocation to be inefficient.

Lecture 18 - Information, Adverse Selection, and Insurance Markets

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Uncertainty. Contingent consumption Subjective probability. Utility functions. BEE2017 Microeconomics

4 Rothschild-Stiglitz insurance market

Microeconomics (Uncertainty & Behavioural Economics, Ch 05)

University of California, Davis Department of Economics Giacomo Bonanno. Economics 103: Economics of uncertainty and information PRACTICE PROBLEMS

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 812

Expected value is basically the average payoff from some sort of lottery, gamble or other situation with a randomly determined outcome.

5/2/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 24: Uncertainty and Information 2. Today. The Story So Far. Preferences and Expected Utility

Consumer s behavior under uncertainty

Managerial Economics

05/05/2011. Degree of Risk. Degree of Risk. BUSA 4800/4810 May 5, Uncertainty

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Asymmetric Information

Economics Homework 5 Fall 2006 Dickert-Conlin / Conlin

Market Failure: Asymmetric Information

Project Risk Analysis and Management Exercises (Part II, Chapters 6, 7)

Dynamic games with incomplete information

CASE FAIR OSTER PRINCIPLES OF MICROECONOMICS E L E V E N T H E D I T I O N. PEARSON 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Prentice Hall

Uncertainty. The St. Petersburg Paradox. Managerial Economics MBACatólica

Mock Examination 2010

Lecture - Adverse Selection, Risk Aversion and Insurance Markets

EXAMPLE OF FAILURE OF EQUILIBRIUM Akerlof's market for lemons (P-R pp )

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Lecture 10 Game Plan. Hidden actions, moral hazard, and incentives. Hidden traits, adverse selection, and signaling/screening

Lecture 12: Introduction to reasoning under uncertainty. Actions and Consequences

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

5. Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior

Practice Problems. U(w, e) = p w e 2,

Economics 101A (Lecture 25) Stefano DellaVigna

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Final Solutions ECON 301 May 13, 2012

Decision Analysis under Uncertainty. Christopher Grigoriou Executive MBA/HEC Lausanne

ECONOMICS OF UNCERTAINTY AND INFORMATION

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Lecture 13: Asymmetric information

Choice Under Uncertainty (Chapter 12)

The Economics of Public Policy 7. Market Failures due to Asymmetric Information

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

Economics 101A (Lecture 26) Stefano DellaVigna

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Financial markets in developing countries (rough notes, use only as guidance; more details provided in lecture) The role of the financial system

ASHORTCOURSEIN INTERMEDIATE MICROECONOMICS WITH CALCULUS. allan

Managerial Economics Uncertainty

12.2 Utility Functions and Probabilities

U(x 1, x 2 ) = 2 ln x 1 + x 2

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Fall Module I

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 9. Demand for Insurance

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Banking, Liquidity Transformation, and Bank Runs

AS/ECON 4070 AF Answers to Assignment 1 October 2001

Development Economics Part II Lecture 7

Revision Lecture Microeconomics of Banking MSc Finance: Theory of Finance I MSc Economics: Financial Economics I

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

Economics Honors Exam Review (Micro) Mar Based on Zhaoning Wang s final review packet for Ec 1010a, Fall 2013

CHAPTER 29 Job market signaling Market for lemons 1-1

Closed book/notes exam. No computer, calculator, or any electronic device allowed.

Chapter 05 Understanding Risk

Econ 101A Final Exam We May 9, 2012.

CONTRACT THEORY. Patrick Bolton and Mathias Dewatripont. The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

Golden rule. The golden rule allocation is the stationary, feasible allocation that maximizes the utility of the future generations.

U(x 1. ; x 2 ) = 4 ln x 1

Incentives and Information Security

Notes 10: Risk and Uncertainty

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

AS/ECON AF Answers to Assignment 1 October Q1. Find the equation of the production possibility curve in the following 2 good, 2 input

Basic Tools of Finance (Chapter 27 in Mankiw & Taylor)

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2009 examination. 2008/2009 syllabus

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

Dynamic Lending under Adverse Selection and Limited Borrower Commitment: Can it Outperform Group Lending?

Lecture 13: Social Insurance

Problem Set. Solutions to the problems appear at the end of this document.

A key characteristic of financial markets is that they are subject to sudden, convulsive changes.

This assignment is due on Tuesday, September 15, at the beginning of class (or sooner).

SCREENING BY THE COMPANY YOU KEEP: JOINT LIABILITY LENDING AND THE PEER SELECTION EFFECT

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

ECMC49S Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Feb 27, 2007 Duration: From 3:05pm to 5:00pm Total Marks: 100

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 8: Insurance Markets

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Learning Objectives = = where X i is the i t h outcome of a decision, p i is the probability of the i t h

How Markets Work: Lessons for Workers Compensation

Part 4: Market Failure II - Asymmetric Information Adverse Selection and Signaling

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Principles of Finance Risk and Return. Instructor: Xiaomeng Lu

Transcription:

Topic 3: Choice under uncertainty (K&R Ch. 6) In 1965, a Frenchman named Raffray thought that he had found a great deal: He would pay a 90-year-old woman $500 a month until she died, then move into her grand apartment...but Raffray died at the age 77, having flocked over $184,000 for an apartment he never got to live in... This reminds us that life is full of uncertainty Agents face uncertainty both as demanders of goods but also as suppliers of inputs When buy car, it might be a lemon! (bad quality) When you supply labour you may suffer serious accident while on the job. But outcomes are not always bad: You might win the lotto (it could be you!), You invested in housing and the market exceeded your expectations. The bottom line is that consumers make decisions without knowing for certain what the consequences will be! In this topic we use the basic tools we have learned so far to study choice under uncertainty! 1 2 How do we cope with uncertainty? To study uncertainty we look at an individual s decision whether or not to accept a gamble. Suppose M= and offered a gamble For each 1 you bet you lose 1 if a heart is drawn but receive 40p if club, spade or diamond. How much do you bet? To answer this we use the procedure developed so far. But need to say something on what goods/commodities you are choosing when deciding how much to bet. But with one difference now we have contingent commodities and states of the world. consumption 140 if a not heart slope: -0.4.4 0.4 e -1 1 endowment: no gambling? 3 states of the world 99 consumption if a heart 4 Probability and expected value What about the likelihood that different states of the world occur? This likelihood is measured by probability (if event cannot occur the probability is zero; if it occurs with certainty the probability is 1). Probability of a heart drawn from a fair deck of cards is 13/52=1/4. Probability of not a heart is drawn is ¾. For a given random process the probabilities of all the states of the world must sum up to 1. What is then the expected winnings of previous gamble? ¾ *.40 + ¼ * (-1) =.05 ; this is the expected value of the gamble (what you expect on average to happen). Suppose now that the gamble is as follows: if a heart appears you win a 1 if not then you lose 0.33, what is the expected value of the gamble? ¼ * 1 ¾ * 0.33 = 0.25-0.25 =0 a gamble with 0 expected monetary gain is called actuarially fair (on average you win or lose nothing) but what is the slope of the budget constrain associated with this bet? it is simply ρ * W + (1 ρ)* L = 0 L ρ = W 1 ρ 5 6 1

a not heart Example: Bet 20, with fair odds (win 20 with prob. ¼, lose 20/3 with prob. ¾) e ¼*(+20)+¾*(-20/3) =1200/12=. odds: the ratio of probabilities of two events ρ * W + (1 ρ)* L = 0 L ρ = W 1 ρ fair odds line: The expected value of consumption is equal at every bundle on fair odds line a heart 7 Just as individuals have preferences between different goods, they have preferences between consumption in different states of the world (i.e., different combinations of contingent commodities). The normal assumptions still apply here but we need one additional: the marginal utility of consumption is independent of the state of the world. Preferences between contingent commodities reflect an individual s attitude towards risk. 8 Risk averse consumers are those who do not like risk. They always prefer a sure thing and will not accept an actuarially fair gamble (this is the definition). Risk lovers prefer uncertainty so they prefer a gamble to a sure thing. Risk neutral people are indifferent among all alternatives with the same expected value. Preferences (risk loving) other Now we need to rank the various alternatives. You care about the amount of consumption in both states of the world certainty line connects all possible endowment points (it is the locus of all possible certain consumption levels slope ρ * W + (1 ρ)* L = 0 L ρ = W 1 ρ fair odds line 9 heart 10 Preferences (risk neutral) Preferences (risk averse) other certainty line other certainty line fair odds line= indifference curve fair odds line heart 11 heart 12 2

Equilibrium Equilibrium for a risk averse (how much does she bet?) Equilibrium occurs where the highest indifference curve possible is reached on the budget constraint. Will a risk averse consumer accept an actuarially fair gamble? No! Why? Because ends up with same level of wealth (equal to her endowment!) without facing the uncertainty of the gamble! other a bet e though on average there is a gain she does not bet a lot of money budget constraint 13 heart 14 Equilibrium for a risk lover (how much does she bet?) heads a e though on average there is a loss she bets all of her income (corner solution) Which type of preference is more relevant for understanding behaviour? There is strong evidence that for the important decisions most people are risk averse (most people buy insurance at a high price). Lotteries (and casinos!) suggest that many people are risk lovers for small bets. tails 15 16 Risk premia Risk premium: extra return on an investment to compensate for risk. Example. return in bad state certainty line 15 10 e b 17 15 20 return in good state 18 3

Should we keep all eggs in one basket? Diversification: the process of buying several assets in order to reduce risk. Example: 2 assets, both same expected return, but (perfectly) negatively correlated. Then split investment! (Diversify). Application: Tax evasion Tax evasion: the failure to pay taxes that are legally due. Optimal policy? If risk averse penalty should be such that she faces an actuarially fair gamble. The higher the tax the higher should the penalty be! (See example). 19 20 Example Consider Elena who is risk averse and amoral citizen. Her before tax income is 1,500. She faces a tax system t=1/3 (if declares 1,500 then net income is 1,500(1- t)= 1,000. If she decides to evade taxes and caught then is is fined f=0.8 for every evaded. not (1-r) 1,500 C.na 1,000 b e certainty line 21 1,000-C.a=taxes not paid C.a 1,000 20 audited (r) 22 Optimal policy Recall that Elena is risk averse. What it then the optimal policy (i.e, policy that reduces tax evasion). (1 r) t rf = 0 f * 1 r = t r Equation says: The penalty rate should be set so that it at least equals the odds of not being audited time the tax rate. Suppose r=0.1 then (1-r)/r=9 so a high penalty is required (9*t=3 for each evaded the evader should be fined 3.) Also the higher the tax, t, the higher the fine, f. Why? 23 24 4

Insurance Previously we asked whether consumers would like to gamble. Typically consumers have no choice (life is uncertain). Fair insurance Premium: the price of obtaining insurance coverage. Actuarially fair insurance: the premium paid is equal to the expected payout of the insurance provider. Example: Scarlet is obstetrician facing probability p of being sued and losing. She wants to buy insurance with premium k 25 26 Preferences (full insurance) Actuarially fair is when p=k. endowment C-ns a slope: -p/(1-p) if sued the she has 0 income C-ns a insurance expenditure C*ns sl: -p/1-p in the sense that C*s=C*ns b b C-s 27 C*s C-s 28 Demand for unfair insurance Equilibrium with actuarially unfair insurance If the premium equals expected benefit then firms make no profits (possibly negative if consider labour costs, i.e., operating costs). So typically insurance policies are unfair (expected payments are less than premium paid---on average). Think of two different people (that belong two different risk classes) but yet pay more or less on same risk premia. 29 C-ns 45 certainty line C-s 30 5

When the insurance policy is actuarially unfair even a risk-averse individual purchases less than full insurance. Intuition: When the premium is higher than the expected payoff it is rational to assume some risk in return for reducing the payments to the insurance. Decision making with many uncertain outcomes: Von Neumann-Morgenstern utility So far the focus was on only two possible outcomes. But in many realistic situations there are more than two possible outcomes. We now introduce decision trees. 31 32 A decision tree Utility functions for uncertain outcomes decision node economics pass fail pass 0.2 0.8 0.4 10,000 3,000 7,000 U c, c, c,..., c ; ρ, ρ, ρ,..., ρ ) = ρ u( c ) +... + ρ u( c ) ( 1 2 3 n 1 2 3 n 1 1 n n Von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function: A utility function where the utility associated with some uncertain event is the expected value of the utilities of each of the possible outcomes politics fail 0.6 2,000 Now, what about sequential decisions? 33 34 Asymmetric Information In markets buyers and sellers have different information Example 1: Seller and buyer of second hand car; seller knows quality but buyer does not (car may be lemon or plum ). Example 2: Labour markets: Employees know ability of themselves but employer does not. Example 3: Incumbents know ability but voters do not. Information about quality, ability may be costly to obtain (sometimes impossible: may be impossible or costly for a firm to determine how productive employees are). All these problems of asymmetric information may cause problems with the efficient functioning of a market. Terminology: Hidden action: action taken by a party not observed (but affected) by another 35 36 6

Adverse selection: Selection of inappropriate outcomes due to asymmetric information (e.g car market). Moral hazard: inappropriately taken actions (e.g insurance). (Aside: Akerlof, Spence and Stiglitz Nobel Prize winners in economics for their work on asymmetric information). The market for Lemons (interesting example) people want to sell their second hand cars. people want to buy a second hand car. Everyone knows that 50 are lemons and 50 are plums. Asymmetric information: owner knows quality but buyers does not. The owner of a lemon wants 1,000. 37 38 The owner of a plum wants 2,000. The buyers are willing to pay 2,400 for a plum and 1,200 for a lemon. If information is perfect then market works Problems arises when quality is not observable. Assume that, when quality is not observed a buyers is willing to pay the expected quality of a second hand car 1 1 1,200+ 2,400 = 1,800 2 2 In this case no plum will be sold only lemons! Why? Because the owners of plums would not sell because the price offered by the buyers is below their reservation price. Only sellers of lemons would be in the market. 39 40 Quality choice Variation of previous idea quality now is determined by producers Suppose consumers buy umbrellas (U) for high quality they are willing to pay 14 and for low 8 (and is impossible to tell quality without trying Us) Suppose that cost of of both qualities of U is 11.50 What is the equilibrium quality of Us? Consumers are uncertain about quality so expect average quality sold p = 14q + 8(1 q) 3 cases to consider 1. Only low quality Us will be produced 2. Only high quality Us will be produced 3. Both qualities will be produced 41 42 7

Case 1: Consumer will only pay low-quality price (but because it costs 11.50 no Us will be produced) Case 2: Consumers are willing to pay 14 but price is 11.50 (so consumer surplus is 2.50) Case 3: Competition makes sure that price is 11.50. Average quality must have a value (for consumers to buy) of at lease the cost of Us that is, 14q + 8(1 q) 11.50 Equilibrium Price, p 11.50 14q + 8(1 q) 11.50 q=1 Demand Many equilibria!! Supply 7/12 Fraction of high quality Us, q 43 44 Adverse selection Example described adverse selection problem (low quality crowd out high quality products). Why? Because information is costly to acquire. Another example: Insurance Insurance company wants to design an insurance scheme for bicycles based on average theft rate. What will happen? Insurance company will go bankrupt! Why? Only high risk consumers would buy insurance! (they are the ones who need it!)--adverse selection again! It then follows that insurance should base scheme on risky customers. Similar problem with health insurance. 45 46 Moral hazard Moral hazard arises when probability of event is affected by the action taken: Example: insurance of bicycle but also health insurance. If consumer is completely insured against the bad outcome then the incentive to take appropriate care is missing: This lack of incentive is called moral hazard. Problem arise because effort is unobservable! Moral hazard and adverse selection Moral hazard refers to situations where one side of the market cannot observe actions of the other (also called hidden action). Adverse selection refers to situations where one side of the market cannot observe the type or quality of the goods on other side of market (also called hidden information). 47 48 8

Equilibrium characterisation Equilibrium in a market involving hidden actions is characterised by some form of rationing. Equilibrium in a market involving hidden information is characterised by too little trade (due to negative externalities the bad quality imposes on good quality good). Equilibrium in both instances is inefficient. Signalling In car market example asymmetric information caused problems But the owners of good cars have incentive to signal the quality of car to potential buyers (warranty!) Signalling makes market perform better. 49 50 Spence s model of education 2 types of workers, able and unable. The able has marginal product a and the unable b, with a>b. In total there are L able and K unable workers. Output is al+bk. If ability was known the firm would offer wage equal to marginal productivity of types. But ability is not observable so firm offers expected wage w=la+kb. Workers (in particular the able ones) have incentive to distinguish themselves from the unable ones. How? By choosing some level of education not attainable by the unable ones. 51 52 Equilibria In this example there are 2 possible (for this course) equilibria. Pooling: meaning that both types choose the same level of education. This is an equilibrium in which able and unable workers pool on the same policy. In this case firm cannot distinguish type and therefore offers expected wage. Separating: Both types have an incentive to choose a level of education such that the types of workers are revealed. In this equilibrium firm knows types and sets wages according to marginal productivity of workers. Both equilibria have interesting features The separating is inefficient from a social point of view. Able workers invest in signals that confer no social benefit (only private). 53 54 9

In the pooling the wage set, in the presence of unable workers, is depressed (externality), giving the able workers the incentive to invest in costly signals In general signalling is not bad since, as in example with types of cars, it facilitates trade. END OF TOPIC 3. 55 10